Skip to main content

The Thing and the Work

  • Chapter
  • 214 Accesses

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 99))

Abstract

In § 17 we have seen that Heidegger had reached the point where it became clear that the question concerning the essence of art is to be approached by means of a careful study of the work of art. One of the first things which everyone immediately notices when confronted with works of art is, in Heidegger’s view, that they are things, things not made by nature but by man. Yet most aesthetic theories pass by this aspect of the work of art in silence. One is convinced that even though it is indeed true that art works are things made by man, nonetheless it is true also that what makes them be the beautiful works they are, consists in something else. In other words, most aesthetic theories give some kind of symbolic interpretation of art works and claim that in each work of art there is something else over and above the thingly feature of the art work. It is thus understandable that in these theories one will make a distinction between some material substrate and a form, some material element and some formal element, between sensuous material and some “idea”, or between form and content.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. FvH, 17; cf. HW, 57(69).

    Google Scholar 

  2. FvH, 14–19.

    Google Scholar 

  3. HW, 8–10 (19–20).

    Google Scholar 

  4. HW, 10–11 (20–22).

    Google Scholar 

  5. FvH, 21–23.

    Google Scholar 

  6. HW, 12 (22).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Cf. An Introduction to Metaphysics, part III, EM, 73–149 (79–164); cf. also all the essays contained in Martin Heidegger, Early Greek Thinking, transl. by David Farrell Krell and Frank A. Capuzzi (New York: Harper and Row, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Cf. Johannes Lohmann, “M. Heidegger’s Ontological Difference1 and Language”, in On Heidegger and Language, ed. by Joseph J. Kockelmans (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1972), pp. 303–363.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. also Joseph J. Kockelmans, “Ontological Difference, Hermeneutics, and Language”, in On Heidegger and Language, pp. 195–234; WRH, 3–15;

    Google Scholar 

  10. A. Dondeyne, “La diffé rence ontologique chez M. Heidegger”, in Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 56 (1958), 35–62;

    Google Scholar 

  11. Alberto Rosales, Transzendenz und Differenz. Ein Beitrag zum Problem der ontologischen Differenz beim frühen Heidegger (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  12. HW, 14 (24).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Cf. SZ, § 29 and passim; cf. WP, 35–42 (75–91).

    Google Scholar 

  14. HW, 12–14 (22–25).

    Google Scholar 

  15. SZ, §§ 29 and 13; cf. FvH, 33–35.

    Google Scholar 

  16. HW, 15 (26).

    Google Scholar 

  17. GP, §§ 8 and 9; cf. FvH, 43–45.

    Google Scholar 

  18. HW, 14–16 (25–26).

    Google Scholar 

  19. HW, 16–17 (26–28); cf. FvH, 44–47.

    Google Scholar 

  20. SZ, §§ 15–18.

    Google Scholar 

  21. SZ, 65–66 (94–95).

    Google Scholar 

  22. SZ, 68–69 (97–98).

    Google Scholar 

  23. SZ, 69 (98).

    Google Scholar 

  24. SZ, 69–72 (99–102); for the preceding see also William J. Richardson, “Heidegger’s Way Through Phenomenology to the Thinking of Being”, in Heidegger: The Man and the Thinker, ed. by Thomas Sheehan (Chicago: Precedent Publishing Co., 1981), pp. 79–93.

    Google Scholar 

  25. SZ, 72–73 (102–103).

    Google Scholar 

  26. SZ, 73–74 (103–104).

    Google Scholar 

  27. SZ, 74–76 (104–107).

    Google Scholar 

  28. HW, 17–18 (28).

    Google Scholar 

  29. HW, 18 (28).

    Google Scholar 

  30. HW, 18 (28–29).

    Google Scholar 

  31. HW, 18 (29).

    Google Scholar 

  32. HW, 18–19 (29–30).

    Google Scholar 

  33. HW, 19 (30). Cf. “Vom Wesen und Begriff der Phusis. Aristoteles, Physik B, 1”, in W, 237–299; “On the Being and Conception of Phusis in Aristotle’s Physics B, 1”, English translation by Thomas J. Sheehan, in Man and World, 9 (1976), 219–270.

    Google Scholar 

  34. HW, 19–20 (30).

    Google Scholar 

  35. FvH, 57–58.

    Google Scholar 

  36. HW, 20 (31).

    Google Scholar 

  37. HW, 20–22 (30–32). Cf. FvH, 57–64.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Cf. GP, § 5; SZ, § 7.

    Google Scholar 

  39. SZ, § 45.

    Google Scholar 

  40. SZ, § 63.

    Google Scholar 

  41. HW, 20; cf. FvH, 60–62.

    Google Scholar 

  42. FvH, 62–64.

    Google Scholar 

  43. HW, 21–22 (32).

    Google Scholar 

  44. FvH, 65–66.

    Google Scholar 

  45. HW, 22 (32–33).

    Google Scholar 

  46. Martin Heidegger, Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs, ed. by Petra Jaeger (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1979), pp. 63–99.

    Google Scholar 

  47. HW, 22(33).

    Google Scholar 

  48. FvH, 68–71.

    Google Scholar 

  49. HW, 22–23 (33–34).

    Google Scholar 

  50. Meyer Schapiro, “The Still Life as a Personal Object — A Note on Heidegger and van Gogh”, in The Reach of Mind, ed. by M.L. Simmel (New York: Springer, 1968), 203–209, p. 205.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Ibid., p. 206.

    Google Scholar 

  52. HW, 65 (78). Cf. Schapiro, loc. cit., p. 206.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Cf. Jan Hulsker, The Complete van Gogh (New York: Abrams, 1980), Nos. 1569, and 1364, respectively.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Cf. Jacques Derrida, La vérité en peinture (Paris: Flammarion, 1978), 291–436, pp. 375–379, 418–421.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Derrida, op. cit., p. 325.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Ibid., pp. 353–367.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Ibid., pp. 367–375.

    Google Scholar 

  59. HW, 24 (35).

    Google Scholar 

  60. HW, 25 (36).

    Google Scholar 

  61. Cf. Derrida, loc. cit., p. 327.

    Google Scholar 

  62. HW, 17 (27).

    Google Scholar 

  63. HW, 20 (31). Cf. Derrida, loc. cit., pp. 336–338.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Derrida, loc. cit., pp. 338–343.

    Google Scholar 

  65. HW, 23 (34).

    Google Scholar 

  66. FvH, 71–72.

    Google Scholar 

  67. SZ, § 29.

    Google Scholar 

  68. FvH, 72–78.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Cf. Joseph J. Kockelmans, “Alcune Riflessioni Sulla Concezione Della Terra In Heidegger”, in Humanitas, 4 (1978), 445–468.

    Google Scholar 

  70. FvH, 78–82.

    Google Scholar 

  71. HW, 23–24 (34–35).

    Google Scholar 

  72. FvH, 82–85.

    Google Scholar 

  73. SZ, §§ 35–38, 68.

    Google Scholar 

  74. FvH, 85–90.

    Google Scholar 

  75. HW, 24–27 (35–38). Cf. WBH, 95–96. — To describe the relationship between work and truth Heidegger sometimes uses the expression “(sich) ins Werk setzen”, “to establish (itself) in the work”. The German expression is often incorrectly translated as “to set (itself) to work”. Note that “ins Werk setzen” is one of the synonyms of the verb schicken which is related to Schickung and Geschick (to send, destiny, sending, mittence); other synonyms of schicken are einrichten and ordnen, expressions which Heidegger also uses to express the relation between work and truth. Cf. HW, 49 (61). In the Addendum Heidegger states that “setzen” must be taken in the sense of the Greek thesis (setting, placing) and not in the modern sense of positing. Cf. UK, 71 (82–83). In view of the fact that the verbs “setzen” and “to set” are etymologically closely related, I often use the expression “to set (itself) into the work” for “(sich) ins Werk setzen”. Note that both “setzen” and “to set” mean to cause something to be in a place or position that is allotted to it, to put it in a place that is adapted to receive it. Heidegger says several times that the expression “(sich) ins Werk setzen” is ambiguous; it seems to me that this ambiguity is best preserved in English if the expression is translated as “setting (itself) into the work”. Cf. UK, 74 (86–87).

    Google Scholar 

  76. FvH, 91–100.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes (Reclam), 73–74 (86).

    Google Scholar 

  78. Hw, 27–28 (38–39).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1985 Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kockelmans, J.J. (1985). The Thing and the Work. In: Heidegger on Art and Art Works. Phaenomenologica, vol 99. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-5067-2_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-5067-2_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-247-3144-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-5067-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics