Skip to main content

The Methodology of Interpretation in Legal Dogmatics

  • Chapter
The Rational as Reasonable

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 4))

  • 182 Accesses

Abstract

The problematics of interpretation may enter the question in two types of situations in legal research praxis. I shall call these a law text centered research strategy and a problem centered research strategy.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 49 ff. Aleksander Peczenik has pointed out to me that the distinction between text-oriented and problem-oriented viewpoints only concerns the so-called context of discovery. With the reservations made in the text, this holds true. Worth mentioning is, however, that the research strategy may be slight ly different depending on from which “end” one takes his starting point.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Regarding the concept of norm propositions see Niiniluoto, Beiheft 3, p. 172, Wróblewski, ‘Verification and Justification in the Legal Sciences’, pp. 196 ff. and esp. gp. 201 ff., and Sintonen, Matti, Problems of Interpretation and Truth in Legal Science, Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 2, pp. 77 ff. See also Klami, Finalistinen oikeusteoria, pp. 19 ff. See also Aarnio, Alexy, and Peczenik, Rechtstheorie 1982, pp. 427 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Niiniluoto, ‘Truth and Legal Norms’, In: Conditions of Validity and Cognition in Modern Legal Thought, ARSP, Beiheft 25 (1985), pp. 168 ff. and especially pp. 182 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See von Wright, G. H., Ts and Ought’, In: Man, Law and Modern Forms of Life, 1985, pp. 263 ff. especially p. 272.

    Google Scholar 

  5. In connection with the conceptual relation between the norm standpoint and the norm recommendation, R. M. Hare’s distinction between the frastic and neustic parts of a sentence is interesting. According to Hare, the neustic component shows whether it is a question of an indicative or imperative use of language. In a corresponding manner the persuasive component has a role to play in norm recommendations. See Hare, Language of Morals, pp. 15 ff. and esp. p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Regarding definitions in general, see Niiniluoto, Johdatus tieteenfilosofiaan, p. 160. See also Koch, Hans-Joachim and Rüssman Helmut, Juristische Begründslehre, pp. 147 ff. and pp. 280 ff. and Klug, Ulrich, Juristische Logik, 3rd ed., pp. 87 ff. Especially in regard to the analytical nature of interpretative statements, see Niiniluoto, ‘Language, Norms and Truth’, p. 177 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Aarnio, On Legal Reasoning, p. 59 ss.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Cr. also Klami, Finalistinen oikeusteoria, p. 62. and Peschka, Vilmos, Die Theorie der Rechtsnormen, pp. 44 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Hart, op. cit., pp. 77 ff., MacCormick, Neil, op. cit., p. 229 and Ross, Directives and Norms, p. 91.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ross, op. cit., pp. 84 ff: “a set of secondary rules is required to specify what sanctions may be exacted of those who violate the substantive law… Such rules are directed to the judge…”

    Google Scholar 

  11. In this connection Kelsen uses the term, “Zurechnung”. See Reine Rechtslehre, p. 22. About the relation between “Is” and “Ought”: von Wright, G. H., Is and Ought. Man, Law and Modern Forms of Life. pp. 263 ff. and Weinberger, Ota, ‘“Is” and “Ought” Reconsidered’, ARSP 1984, p. 454 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Alchourron, Carlos and E. Bulygin, Normative Systems, p. 41 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Cf. Dworkin, Ronald, ‘The Model of Rules’, In: Taking Rights Seriously, sections 1–4.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Searle, J. R., op. cit., pp. 56 ff. and Ross, Directives and Norms, p. 53. — A good analysis is presented by Riccardo Guastini in: ‘Six Concepts of “Constitutive Rule”’, p. 488 ff. and also Tuori, K., Oikeusnormien asettamismenettelyt ja oikeuden, Kriisitendenssit, Politiiikka 3 (1985), pp. 189 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Regarding competence norms, see Ross, op. cit., pp. 130 ff. and Zitting, Simo, ‘Omistajan oikeuksista ja velvollisuuksista F, LM 1952, pp. 394 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Regarding this, see Aarnio, Perillisen oikeusasemasta, p. 71 ff. 17Makkonen, Zur Problematik der juristischen Entscheidung, pp. 27 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  17. For general comments on this, see Weinberger, Christiane and Ota, Logik, Semantik und Hermeneutik, pp. 64 ff. and pp. 96 ff. See also Esser, Josef, Vorverständnis und Methodenwahl in der Rechtsfindung, passim, and Jonsson, Inge, ‘Riktningar inom 1800-talets hermeneutik’, pp. 65 ff. Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 150 ff. and Aarnio, ‘Outline of a Hermeneutic Approach in Legal Theory’, In: Philosophical Perspectives, pp. 47 ff. Cf. Villa, Vittorio, ‘Legal Science and Hermeneutic Point of View’, pp. 509 ff., and in general Villa, Teorie della Scienza Giuridica e Teorie delle Scienze Naturali, passim. Stig Strömholm emphasizes the general differences between linguistic interpretation and the legal interpretation of texts. He particularly points to four aspects: (a) legal interpretation has a broader and more relevant connection to the social context than do other forms of interpretation, (b) there is an hierarchial division of roles among the interpreters, (c) legal interpretation must fulfill certain axiological goals such as justice, and (d) the focus of interpretation, legal norms, form a system. Cf. Strömholm, ‘Juridisk tolkningsmetodik före 1800-talets “moderna genombrott”’, pp. 47 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  18. This is especially the case in classical text hermeneutics, Cf. Aarnio, ‘Philosophical Perspectives in Jurisprudence’, pp. 56 ff. Hans-Georg Hinderung gives a good analysis of the problem in Rechtsnorm und Verstehen, passim. See also Larenz, Karl, Methodenlehre der Rechtswissenschaft, p. 85 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Cf. Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 154–155. The philosophical problematics of “conventions” is dealt with in a very interesting manner in Lars Hertz-berg’s paper, ‘Science and Certainty’, pp. 60 ff. especially pp. 72 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See about these types of sentences p. ff.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 75 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cf. Aarnio, op. cit., p. 90.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Cf. Aarnio, op. cit., p. 122.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Regarding sources of law, see Peczenik, Juridikens metodproblem, pp. 109 ff. and Strömholm, op. cit., pp. 287 ff. and Ross, On Law and Justice, pp. 82 ff. See also Makkonen, Kaarle (ed.), Oikeudellinen lähdemateriaali, 1979, pp. 16 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See e.g. Björne, Lars, Deutsche Rechtssysteme im 18. und 19. Jahrhundert, especially p. 131 ff. where one can find a really remarkable analysis about the historical development of the so-called systematic, thinking in legal science.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Alanen, Aatos, Yleinen oikeustiede ja kansainvälinen yksityisoikeus, 1965, p. 56 and Peczenik, Juridikens metodproblem, pp. 136–137. About the customary law in general: Klami, Hannu Tapani, Gewohnheitsrecht als Rechtsquelle, pp. 4 ff. and pp. 44 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Brusiin, op. cit., pp. 7 ff. and Alanen, op. cit., p. 57. See also Strömholm, op. cit., pp. 187 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Alanen, op. cit., pp. 58 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Makkonen, Zur Problematik der juridischen Entscheidung, p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Alanen, op. cit., p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 135 ff. Regarding precedent in general, see Brusiin, op. cit., pp. 167 ff. Peczenik, op. cit., pp. 104 ff., Strömholm, op. cit., pp. 333 ff. Regarding the position of precedents in American law, see Radin, Max, ‘Case Law and Stare Decisis’, pp. 3 ff. An excellent analysis can be found in: Saarenpää, Ahti E., ‘Court Decisions as the Focus of Study’, SSL 1984, pp. 123 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  32. On the distinction Aarnio, A., Oikeussāānnōten tulleinnasta, pp. 89 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  33. See, however, the Supreme Court decision KKO 2649/19.10.1966 and Miettinen, M in Minutes of the XXI Annual Meeting of the Lawyers Union in Finland, 1970, pp. 80 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  34. The Royal Letter to the Court of Appeal in Gōta 1682 and Nehrman, D., Inledning til then swenska jurisprudentiam civilem, 1729, p. 72.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Brusiin, op. cit., pp. 157 ff. and Makkonen, Zur Problematik der juridischen Entscheidung, pp. 153 ff. See also Jørgensen, Stig, Law and Society, pp. 110 ff. For comments on the relationship between general principles of law and juridical induction, see Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 201 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Perelman, Chaim, Juristische Logik als Argumentationslehre, p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Aarnio, ‘Eternal and Changing Law’, In: Philosophical Perspectives in Jurisprudence, p. 100 ff. In this connection, the criticisms that Dworkin directs at Hart’s views of legal principles is interesting. What is important is what turns principles into legal principles. Cf. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, pp. 36 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Regarding this criticism, see Aarnio, ‘The Development of Legal Theory and Philosophy of Law in Finland’, pp. 9 ff. See also Aarnio, ‘150 anni di filosofia del diretto in Finlandia’, pp. 809 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Aarnio, The Development of Legal Theory and Philosophy of Law in Finland, pp. 20 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  40. As far as the goal reasoning according to the pragmatic instrumentalism is concerned one can find an excellent analysis in: Summers, Robert S., Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory, pp. 60 ff. Regarding the consideration of consequences in general, see MacCormick, op. cit., pp. 100 ff. See also Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 84 ff, which deals with interpretation presented in the form of so-called technical norms, Klami, Finalistinen oikeusteoria, pp. 42 ff. and Peczenik, Juridikens metodproblem, p. 150 ff. Peczenik presents the so-called ideological interpretation method in general.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Perelman, op. cit., p. 79 and p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Perelman, op. cit., p. 43 and Germann, O. A., Methodische Grundfragen, pp. 4 ff. See also Rahlf, Joachim, ‘Die Rolle der historischen Auslegungsmethode in der Rechtsprechung des BGH’, pp. 27 ff. In Scandinavian realism, criticism of the will of the legislator has been presented especially by Karl Olivecrona, Cf. e.g. Law as Fact, pp. 65 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  43. See Note 21 of Part III.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Aarnio, Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 3, pp. 51–53.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Also on the basis of this doctrine four sources of law rise over all others: written law, travaux préparatoires, court decisions and customary law. See also Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 133 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Peczenik, op. cit., pp. 48 ff., Peczenik, ‘The Structure of a Legal System’, Rechtstheorie 6 (1975), p. 7 ff. and Peczenik, Rechtstheorie 2 (1980), pp. 150 ff. Cf. H. L. A. Hart’s concepts “permissive” and “mandatory”, The Concept of Law, p. 246 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  47. For a more detailed analysis of this, see Summers, Robert S., The Types of Substantive Reasons: The Core of a Theory of Common Law Justification’, pp. 724 ff. (Also available in ARSP, Beiheft 11). See also Summers, Robert S. and Leigh B. Kelley, ‘“Economist Reasons” for Common Law Decisions — A Preliminary Inquiry’, pp. 213 ff. Cf Golding, Martin P., Legal Reasoning, pp. 39 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Summers, op. cit., pp. 726 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Summers, op. cit., pp. 728 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  50. See Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, pp. 25 and 44. Regarding these comments, see Alexy, Robert, ‘Zum Begriff des Rechtsprincips’, Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 1, 1979, pp. 59 ff., esp. pp. 63 ff. See also Eckhoff and Sundby, Rettssysterner: Systemteoretisk innfring i rettsfilosofin, 1976, pp. 128 ff. Regarding this, see Jareborg, Nils, ‘Regler och riktlinjer’, TfR 1979, pp. 385 ff. With the reservations made, the text corresponds to Jareborg’s view of the matter. Cf., however, Eckhoff, TfR 1980, p. 145. Regarding the term “guiding standard”, see Eckhoff, ‘Guiding Standards in Legal Reasoning’, p. 205 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Regarding Wittgenstein’s concept of rules, see Philosophical Investigations, § 218–219. In this, Wittgenstein emphasizes that following a rule is similar to “following blind”. There is no choice in the matter. Rules are like the tracks of a railroad: “and infinitely long rails correspond to the unlimited application of a rule (§ 218). Henry Le Roy Finch observes, on the other hand, that we have no obligation to follow a rule (op. cit., p. 197). A rule compels us only if we begin to follow it. In this sense, it is a question of an “either-or” situation. See also Brand, Gerd, The Central Texts of Wittgenstein, pp. 125 ff. An excellent analysis about the Wittgensteinian concept of rule, Kripke, Saul A.: Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, esp. pp. 7 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Peczenik, Juridikens metodproblem, p. 86 and concerning the standards of preference pp. 118–120.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Regarding analogy in general, see Frändberg, Ake, Om analog användning av rättsnormer, pp. 16 ff., Koch and Rüssman, op. cit., pp. 259 ff. and especially Peczenik, op. cit., pp. 74 ff. See also Aarnio, On Legal Reasoning, pp. 70 ff. and Alexy, Theorie der juristischen Argumentation, pp. 343 ff. About case-analogy Golding, Martin P., Legal Reasoning, pp. 44 ff. and pp. 97 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Peczenik, op.cit., p. 76.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ibid., p. 74.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Koch and Rüssman, op. cit., pp. 257 ff. and Klug, op. cit., pp. 132 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, p. 130.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Aarnio, On Legal Reasoning, p. 72.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Alanen, op. cit., p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  60. See e.g. Larenz, Karl, Methodenlehre der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 255 ff., Engisch, K.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Einführung in das juristische Denken, p. 256 and Zippelius, Reinhold, Rechtsphilosophie, pp. 221 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Regarding isomorphic situations, see Stenius, Erik, ‘Wittgensteinin “puhtaan kielen kritiikki”‘, p. 45 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  63. In general, see Alexy, op.cit., p. 342, Klug, op. cit., p. 128 and Koch and Rüssman, op. cit., p. 258. Cf. Golding, M. P., ‘Principled Decision-Making and the Supreme Court’, pp. 208 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Alanen, op. cit., p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Allowing extending analogy in criminal law will lead to a conflict with the principle of nulla poena sine lege. On the other hand, a complete prohibition on analogy will lead to an unevenness of application, as similar cases cannot be dealt with in a similar fashion. For this reason, in the Finnish literature, it has been usual to warn only against analogy in malam partem. Cf. Honkasalo, Brynolf, ‘Suomen rikosoikeus’, Yleiset opit I, p. 50. See also Peczenik, op. cit., pp. 89–90.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Peczenik, op. cit., p. 85.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Alanen, op. cit., p. 161.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Peczenik, op. cit. p. 76. See about the methods of legal interpretation in general Bydlinski, F., Juristische Methodenlehre und Rechtsbegriff, pp. 437 ff., Larenz, Karl, Methodenlehre der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 188 ff. See also Vernengo, Roberto J., Curso de Teoria General del Derecho, pp. 411 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Alanen, op. cit., p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Alexy, op. cit., p. 319.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Regarding these concepts see Victor, Dag, Rättssystem och vetenskap, 1977, pp. 21 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Ibid., pp. 25 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Ibid., pp. 27–28.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Regarding the so-called “intertwinement thesis”, see Aarnio, The Significance of the Theoretical Element in Legal Research, In: Philosophical Perspectives in Jurisprudence, pp. 120 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  76. It is a question of subsumption. See e.g. Koch and Rüssmann, pp. 64 ff. Cf. Larenz, op. cit., p. 256 and Alexy, op. cit., pp. 274 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  77. See, in general, Ahmavaara, Yrjö, Informaatio, p. 112. The expression used as an example, “someone”, is an unspecified singular term. See Jareborg, Nils, Begrepp och brottsbeskrivning, p. 94. To supplement the text, see Chapter 4 of Jareborg’s book, p. 93 ff. See also Hart, op. cit., p. 4, pp. 15 ff. and pp. 122 ff., Vernengo, Roberto, J., Curso de Teoria General del Derecho, pp. 406 ff. and Wróblewski, Jerzy, ‘Fuzziness of Legal System’, pp. 311 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  78. In this connection there is reason to recall Wittgenstein s characterization of the concept of “family resemblance”. It is precisely in connection with open terms that we can say that individual meaning contents are “related” to each other only in the sense that the strands of a rope form the rope. See Philosophical Investigations, § 66–75. The problem of open terms has been dealt with in a noteworthy manner by Furberg Mats, in Saying and Meaning, pp. 72 ff. See also Hart, op. cit., pp. 121 ff, which touches upon the problem of the so-called “open texture”.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Regarding this concept, see e.g. Regnell, Hans, Semantik, p. 69 and Ross, op. cit., pp. 135 ff. See also Ekelöf, Per Olof, Semantik och juridik. Svensk Juristtidning 1966, pp. 497 ff. and Jareborg, op. cit., pp. 98 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Aarnio, ‘Formal Incorrectness and the Invalidity of Legal Acts’, SSL, pp. 19 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Ahmavaara, op. cit., p. 112 and Jareborg, op. cit., p. 108. See also Regnell, op. cit., pp. 75 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Jareborg, op. cit., pp. 121 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Ibid., p. 108. When the same term refers to several different matters, the concept of “polysemia” has often been used.

    Google Scholar 

  84. See von Wright, G. H., ‘Normit ja logiikka’, Ajatus 1963, pp. 255 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Regarding the concept of the legislator, see Peczenik, Juridikens metodproblem, pp. 112–113.

    Google Scholar 

  86. See Brusiin, op. cit., pp. 24 ff., Coing, Helmut, Grundzüge der Rechtsphilosophie, pp. 328 ff., Makkonen, Zur Problematik der juridischen Entscheidung, pp. 122 ff. and Peczenik, op. cit., pp. 76 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  87. A rather complete definition of the concept of the gap is given by Alchourrón and Bulygin. See Normative Systems, pp. 145 ff. and the comments on this in Aarnio, On Legal Reasoning, pp. 60 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  88. See also Wróblewski, Jerzy, ‘System of Norms and Legal System’, Rivista Internationale di Filosofia del Diritto 2 (1972).

    Google Scholar 

  89. Alchourrón and Bulygin, op. cit., p. 146.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Ibid., p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Kelsen, Hans, Reine Rechtslehre, p. 348 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Alchourrón and Bulygin, op. cit., p. 51 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Ibid., p. 146; cf. pp. 31 ff. and pp. 106 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Peczenik, op. cit., p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  95. From the general point of view it is a question of a more precise outlining of the meaning content of the expression in question. Regarding this concept, see Naess, Arne, Empirisk semantik, pp. 6–13 and pp. 26 ff. and Naess, Arne, Interpretation and Preciseness, p. 350 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  96. See Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 120–121. The basis of the diagram is Naess’ presentation of pro-and counter-argumentation. See Empirisk semantik, pp. 67 ff. Ilmar Tammelo has called this type of reasoning “a zetetic process”. See Tammelo, Zetetischer Verfahren für juristisches Aufweisen; Rechtstheorie 1978, pp. 421 ff. For comments on this see Wimmer, Franz, ‘Überlegungen zu Tammelos Unterscheidung von Euduktion, Produktion und Seduktion,’ Rechtstheorie 1979, pp. 338 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Peczenik, The Basis of Legal Justification, pp. 33 ff. Peczenik makes, on good grounds, a distinction between the contextually sufficient and the deep justification. See also op. cit., pp. 1 ff., 28 ff, and 110 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  98. See Alexy, op. cit., pp. 272 ff and Wróblewski, ‘Legal Syllogism and Rationality of Judicial Decision’, ‘Rechtstheorie 5 (1974), pp. 39 ff., Wróblewski, ‘Legal Decision and Its Justification’, Proceedings of the World Congress for Legal and Social Philosophy. 1971, pp. 412 ff. and Wróblewski, ‘Justification of Legal Decisions’, Revue Internationale de Philosophic La Nouvelle Rhétorique. Essais en hommage à Chaim Perelman 127–128 (1979), pp. 277 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  99. A more extensive analysis of syllogistic deduction is to be found in Tammelo, Ilmar and Helmut Schreiner, Grundzüge und Grundverfahren der Rechtslogik. I., pp. 110 ff. See also Aarnio, On Legal Reasoning, pp. 59–60, Koch- Rüssmann, op. cit., pp. 14 ff. and pp. 59 ff. and Makkonen, op. cit., pp. 47 ff. Regarding deductive reasoning, very clear criticism is to be found in MacCormick, op. cit., pp. 19 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  100. See MacCormick, op. cit., pp. 19–52 and esp. pp. 100 ff., which separates “second-order justification” from the deductive reasoning in a decision. This latter justification corresponds to the term, “external justification”.

    Google Scholar 

  101. The description of Ex-justification is, in this section, based on the discussions and common work that the author has had with Aleksander Peczenik in 1984–85. See also Peczenik, Creativity and Transformations in Legal Reasoning, pp. 280 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Aarnio, Perillisen oikeusasemasta, pp. 362 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 133 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Alexy, op. cit., pp. 221 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Larenz, op. cit., pp. 198 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Regarding these principles, see Ross, op. cit., pp. 164 ff. and Peczenik, op. cit., pp. 110 ff and Strömholm, op. cit., pp. 428 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  107. See Kommentar zum Allgemeinen Gesetzbuch (hrsg. von Heinrich Klang und Franz Gschnitzer), p. 103 and p. 107. Regarding the significance of travaux préparatoires in general. See Strömholm, Legislative Material and Constitution of Statutes. SSL 1966, pp. 175 ff. and Rahlf, op. cit., pp. 28 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 134 ff. and Aarnio, On Legal Reasoning, pp. 109 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Aarnio, On Legal Reasoning, pp. 216 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Cf. Peczenik, op. cit., p. 113, where he states that lawyers know whose intention is to be taken into consideration. Peczenik’s view would seem to oversimplify the situation, as research praxis has shown countless examples where different decisions on the same matter have made use of the disparate views of various instances.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Larenz, Karl, Methodenlehre der Rechtswissenschaft, p. 322. Larenz uses a concept of an “objective-teleological” argument. This concept refers to the objective goal involved in legal order.

    Google Scholar 

  112. See e.g. Strömholm, Rätt, rättskällor och rättstillämpning, p. 405

    Google Scholar 

  113. Perelman, op. cit., p. 79.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Peczenick, op. cit., p. 191. It is this that is referred to in the text as the “objective” meaning (interpretation).

    Google Scholar 

  115. Klang and Gschnitzer, op. cit., p. 104. See also Zippelius, Reinhold, Rechtsphilosophie 1982, pp. 199 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Regarding this, see Alexy, op. cit., pp. 322 ff., who distinguishes between systemic interpretation in a strict and in a broad sense. The former (“systematische Überprüfung im engeren Sinne”) is connected with the logical consistency between the statement being interpreted and the statements used to support it. The latter (“systematische Überprüfung im weiteren Sinne”) can be characterized by speaking of the practical consistency between statements. Alexy calls the former “logical control of consistency” and the latter “practical control of consistency” (“Konsistenz-kontrolle”). Regarding systemic points of view in interpretation in general, see Peczenik, op. cit., pp. 99 ff. and Strömholm, op. cit. pp. 401 ff. In Finnish legal science, Saarenpää has been the most consistent in emphasizing systemic points of view. See Tasajaon periaate, pp. 18 ff, and Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 121 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Regarding this problem, see Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, p. 137.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Cf. Alexy, who presents an interesting analysis of the significance of legal dogmatical statements in justification. He summarizes his analysis in the form of a rationality principle: “If a dogmatic argument is possible, it must be used”. See Alexy, op. cit., pp. 320 ff., and esp. p. 334. In other words a rational interpreter refers to a legal dogmatical opinion, too. At the same time, Alexy regards legal dogmatics as having several functions, such as the stabilization function, the technical task of furthering the learning and teaching of legal material and the heuristic function, in other words the task of presenting decision models with practical applications. See Alexy, op. cit., pp. 326–332.

    Google Scholar 

  119. Aarnio, On Legal Reasoning, pp. 183 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Regarding the so-called finalistic interpretation in general, see MacCormick op. cit., pp. 129 ff. See also Alexy, op. cit., pp. 295 ff., who deals with the problematics of so-called teleological interpretation, Larenz, op. cit., p. 322 and Peczenik, op. cit., pp. 150 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Klami, Legal Heuristics, esp. pp. 21–36.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Cf. Klami, Finalistinen oikeusteoria, p. 62, cf. pp. 128–129 and p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  123. See Peczenik, Juridikens metodproblem, p. 191. Cf. Walter, Robert, ‘Das Auslegungsproblem im Leichte der Reinen Rechtslehre’, p. 194 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Alchourrón and Bulygin, Normative Systems, pp. 21 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Brusiin, op. cit., p. 195. See also Alchourrón and Bulygin, op. cit., p. 53 and Krawietz, op. cit., p. 88 and p. 153.

    Google Scholar 

  126. Brusiin’s position on the matter is not quite clear, as on the other hand he believes that all legal interpretation “arises” from the reality of societal norms. Even so, for Brusiin “order” is a volitive concept, “system” a cognitive concept. An interesting analysis about the concept of legal system is presented in: Kerimov, D. A., Philosophische Probleme des Rechts, pp. 199 ff. especially p. 202 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Alchourrón and Bulygin, op. cit., pp. 50 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Alchourrón, Carlos, ‘Systematization and Change in the Science of Law’, Proceedings of the XI World Congress on Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, 1983 (in print), Bulygin, Eugenio, ‘Legal Dogmatics and the Systematization of Law’, in: op. cit. and Aarnio, Aulis, ‘On the Change of Legal System’, in: op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  129. Alchourrón and Bulygin, op. cit., pp. 9 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  130. Ibid., pp. 54–55.

    Google Scholar 

  131. Ibid., pp. 72 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Ibid., pp. 78 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  133. Kuhn, op. cit., Chapt. 3 and e.g. Chapt. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  134. See Ross, On Law and Justice, pp. 211 ff. and Zitting, Simo, An Attempt to Analyse the Owner’s Legal Position. SSL, 1959, pp. 234 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  135. I am indebted for the clarification in the text to Niilo Jääskinen who has demonstrated in our discussions the imprecision of the set of concepts in my earlier writings. Cf. Aarnio, On Legal Reasoning, pp. 272 ff. and Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 50 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  136. Tolonen, Juha, op. cit., pp. 36 ff., cf. pp. 174 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  137. Saarenpää, Tasajaon periaate, p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  138. Peczenik, ‘Norms and Reality’, in Essays in Legal Theory. 1969, pp. 9 ff. and Peczenik, ‘Empirical Foundations of Legal Dogmatics’, in ibid., pp. 60 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  139. Aarnio, Aulis, Jääskinen Niilo, Pöyhönen Juha and Uusitalo Jyrki, Paradigms, Change and Progress in Legal Dogmatics (in print); Section 2. See also Ralf Dreier’s excellent analysis in: ‘Zur Theoriebildung in der Jurisprudenz’ in Recht-Moral-Ideologie, 1981, pp. 70 ff. See also Dalberg-Larsen, Jørgen, Five Essays on Legal Science, pp. 68 ff., especially pp. 80 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  140. A detailed analysis is to be found in Aarnio, Perillisen oikeusasemasta, pp. 49 ff. (German summary), and for some comments on this, Saarenpää, ‘Court Decisions as the Focus of Study, pp. 128 ff. See also Aarnio, ‘En analys av arvinges rättsliga ställning’. Tidskrift utgiven av Juridiska Föreningen i Finland 6 (1980), pp. 363 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  141. See Ross, On Law and Justice, pp. 199 ff. Cf. Borum, O. A.,Arvefaldet, pp. 22 ff. and Malmström, Åke, Successionsrättsliga studier, pp. 38 ff. and pp. 198 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  142. Zitting, Simo, ‘An Attempt to Analyse the Owner’s Legal Position, SSL, 1959, pp. 234 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  143. See Zitting, op. cit. p. 229.

    Google Scholar 

  144. See Aarnio, Perillisen oikeusasemasta, pp. 89 ff. for an analysis of these doctrines.

    Google Scholar 

  145. Legal dogmatics which attempts to construct a systematic framework can be called theoretical legal dogmatics. See Aarnio, Denkweisen der Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 69 ff. and pp. 231 ff. as well as Aarnio, ‘The Significance of the Theoretical Element in Legal Research’, in: Philosophical Perspectives in Jurisprudence, pp. 123 ff. Cf. also Peczenik, Aleksander, ‘Legal Research, Growth of Science and Moral Theory’, pp. 137 ff., especially pp. 146 ff.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1987 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Aarnio, A. (1987). The Methodology of Interpretation in Legal Dogmatics. In: The Rational as Reasonable. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 4. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-4700-9_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-4700-9_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-8590-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-4700-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics