Skip to main content

The Ontology of Law

  • Chapter
The Rational as Reasonable

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 4))

  • 164 Accesses

Abstract

The sector of philosophy termed ontology examines the basic elements and the structure of the world. One basic point of contention in ontology is between nominalism and (conceptual) realism. With reference to Occam’s razor (the prohibition against assuming unnecessary entities) the nominalists accept only individual entities in their ontology. D. M. Armstrong describes the nominalist point of view as follows: “The fundamental contention of Nominalism is that all things that exist are only particulars.”1 Only these particulars are really existing. Conceptual realists would grant an independent existence also (yet not necessarily only) to concepts on a higher level, for example to the roundness of a thing. These exist regardless of a conscious subject. Conceptualism has represented a mediating position between these two: general concepts exist in the mind of the conscious subject. The point of departure for the conventionalist is that ontological commitments depend on the language used. This, in turn, is open to agreement, which means that also ontology is a matter of convention.2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Armstrong, D. M., Nominalism & Realism: Universals & Scientific Realism. Volume I, p. 12. Cf. also Niiniluoto, op. cit., pp. 123 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf. for example Tolonen, Juha, Der Allgemeine Erklährungshintergrund der wirtschaftlichen Ordnung und seine Anwendung auf das Aktiengesellschaftsrecht, pp. 17 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Finch, Henry Le Roy, Wittgenstein — the Later Philosophy, pp. 243–244.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., p. 243.

    Google Scholar 

  5. In the theory of law, this type of ontology has been defended by Osvi Lahtinen. Cf. his article ‘Kuolinpesä-konstruktiosta’, LM 1955, pp. 112 ff. and a comment on this article, Aarnio ‘On Finnish Legal Theory in the 20th Century’, in Legal Point of View, pp. 25 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Niiniluoto, op. cit., p. 129.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Klami, Finalistinen oikeusteoria, pp. 3 ff. See also Klami, ‘Dualism of Law’, In: Objektivierung des Rechtsdenkens, pp. 475 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Popper, Karl R., Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach, pp. 74 and 154 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Niiniluoto, op. cit., p. 129. Cf. also Popper, op. cit., pp. 156–160, which deals with the objectivity of World 3 and its nature as a Man-made product. Regarding the contingence and necessary existence of norms, see von Wright, G. H., Norm and Action, pp. 107 ff. In this connection it should be noted that if the ontology accepts so-called institutional facts in addition to entities and properties, many traditional problems regarding existence will find a solution. It is not, however, self-evident where (in the ontological sense) facts receive their institutional nature. For example Searle connects them with so-called constitutive rules, in which case we have come around once again to the problem of the existence of rules. Regarding constitutive rules and the concept of the institutional fact, see Searle, J. R., Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language, and also Searle, What is a Speech Act?, pp. 39 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Makkonen, op. cit., pp. 119 ff. Hans Kelsen often specifically equated existence with validity. He writes, “Mit dem Worte ‘geltung’ bezeichnen wir die spezifische Existenz einer Norm”, Reine Rechtslehre, 2nd Ed. p. 9. As will be observed in the following (Sections 3.2 and 3.4) sentence (1) has not been turned into sentence (2) in the sense intended by Kelsen.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Regarding the existence of a norm, see also von Wright, G. H., Norm and Action, pp. 107 ff. and Sintonen, Matti, Problems of Interpretation and Truth in Legal Dogmatics, Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 2, p. 83. From a legal point of view, see also Peczenik, Aleksander, Legal Data: An Essay About the Ontology of Law, pp. 99 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Wróblewski, Jerzy, ‘Verification and Justification in the Legal Sciences’. Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 1 (1979), pp. 207 ff. See also Wróblewski, ‘Dilemmas of the Normativistic Concept of Legal System’, Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 5 (1984), pp. 320 ff. where Wróblewski presents a more detailed analysis of the problem. Cf. Ross, Alf, Validity and the Conflict Between Legal Positivism and Natural Law, pp. 76 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See also Aarnio, Aulis, ‘On the Validity, Efficacy, and Acceptability of Legal Norms’. In: Philosophical Perspectives in Jurisprudence, pp. 152 ff. Cf. Guastini, Riccardo, ‘A Tentative Analysis of Two Juristic Sentences’, pp. 573 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Kelsen, Hans, Reine Rechtslehre, pp. 209 ff. Seppo Laakso gives an exceptionally lucid analysis of the matter. In: Oikeuden systeemiyhteys, pp. 51 ff. Regarding Kelsen’s theory, see e.g. Raz, Joseph, The Concept of a Legal System, pp. 93 ff. See also Laakso, ‘Puhtaan oikeusopin problematiikkaa’, Oikeustiede 1980, pp. 150 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See e.g. Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre, pp. 206–208. According to Kelsen, the fundamental norm is a logical necessity (“logisch unerlässich”). Such a conception, however, was rather late in being developed in Kelsen’s theory. In this connection see Laakso, ‘Puhtaan oikeusopin problematiikkaa’, pp. 152–153.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Kelsen, op. cit., pp. 208 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Peczenik, Grundlagen der juristischen Argumentation, pp. 42 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See here especially the criticism presented by Hermann Klenner about the “emptiness” of the Kelsenian system. Klenner, Vom Recht der Natur zur Natur des Rechts, pp. 139 ff., and Klenner, Rechtsleere, passim. See also Peschka, Vilmos, Die Theorie der Rechtsnormen, pp. 224 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Alchourrón, Carlos — Bulygin, Eugenio, Normative Systems, pp. 94 ff. For a more detailed analysis, see Peczenik, ‘On the Nature and Function of the Grundnorm’, pp. 282 ff. See also Raz, op. cit., pp. 95 ff. and Vernengo, Roberto J., ‘La Funcion Sistematica de la Norma Fundamenta’, pp. 3 ff., especially pp. 17 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Kelsen, op. cit., p. 219. The giving of a norm and its efficacy are conditions of the validity of the norm (Bedingung der Geltung) but the foundation (Grund) of a norm is always another, superior norm, and ultimately the fundamental norms. Regarding efficacy, see also Raz, op. cit., pp. 203 ff. See also Petev, Valentin, ‘Rechtsquellenlehre und Reine Rechtslehre’, Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 5, pp. 274–277.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Kelsen, Die philosophischen Grundlagen der Naturrechtslehre und Rechtspositivismus, pp. 8–9 and 18. See also Reine Rechtslehre, pp. 1–3.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Wróblewski, ‘Verification and Justification in the Legal Sciences’, Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 1 p. 212 ff. See also Weinberger, Ota, ‘Logik, Wirklichkeit und Positivität in der Reinen Rechtslehre’, Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 5 (1984), pp. 425 ff., especially pp. 436 ff. where Weinberger analyses the existence of law from the Kelsenian point of view.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Peczenik ‘On the Nature and Function of the Grundnorm’, Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 2, pp. 279 ff. and Peczenik, The Basis of Legal Justification, pp. 2 ff. and Peczenik, Grundlagen der juristischen Argumentation, pp. 5 ff. Regarding the concept of transformation, see Aarnio, Alexy, and Peczenik, Rechtstheorie 2 (1981), pp. 136 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Regarding the concept of “underpinning reasons”, see MacCormick, Legal Theory and Legal Reasonings, pp. 64 ff. and pp. 138–140.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. about “minimum demands” e.g. Hart, op. cit., pp. 189 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Regarding this matter see e.g. Ilium, Knud, ‘Some Reflection on the Method of Legal Science and on Legal Reasoning’. SSL 1968 pp. 49 ff. and Ilium, Lov og ret, pp. 53 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See about organic reactions, see Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre, pp. 182 ff. and Ross, op. cit. pp. 66 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Holmes, Oliver Wendell, ‘The Path of the Law’, in Collective Legal Papers, 1921, p. 173.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See also Summers, Robert S., Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory, especially p. 239 ff. and Summers, ‘Pragmatic Instrumentalism in Twentieth Century American Legal Thought — A Synthesis and Critique of Our Dominant General Theory about Law and Its Use’, Cornell Law Review 66 (1981), pp. 861 ff. and esp. pp. 904 ff. Summers remarks give a clear picture of the goals and contents of the tendency known as American realism.

    Google Scholar 

  30. See also Krawietz, Werner, Juristische Entscheidung und wissenschaftliche Erkenntnis, pp. 97 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Cf. Benditt, op. cit., pp. 12 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  32. von Wright, G. H., ‘Normien eksistenssi’. Lecture (mimeograph), passim.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Regarding this distinction see Hart, op. cit., pp. 77 ff. Ross (op. cit., p. 46) observes that a primary norm is always a directive for the judge.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Frank, Jerome, Law and the Modern Mind, p. 134 ff. See also Benditt, op. cit., pp. 10–11 and Summers, ‘Pragmatic Instrumentalism in Twentieth Century American Legal Thought’, p. 896 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ross, Om ret og retfaerdighed, p. 55. This is a literal translation, with minor stylistic adjustments. Thus, “conditions” has been put instead of “conditioning facts”. Cf. Ross, On Law and Justice, pp. 42 ff., where the translator of that book omitted the words “justify” and “justification”, and inserted the words “form the basis” and “reasoning” instead of them.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ross, Om ret og retfaerdighed, p. 41. A literal translation with very minor stylistic adjustments. In On Law and Justice Ross writes as follows:

    Google Scholar 

  37. See also Aarnio and Peczenik, Mas alia del realismo, Section 2.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ross, op. cit., pp. 48 ff. See also Bjarup, Jes, Skandinavischer Realismus, pp. 68 ff., Strömholm, op. cit., p. 100 and Lauridsen, Preben Stuer, Studier i retspolitisk argumentation, pp. 125 ff. and p. 234 ff. See also in general Bulygin, Eugenio, 4E1 Concepto de Vigencia en Alf Ross, pp. 3 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ross, op. cit., pp. 38 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Aarnio and Peczenik, Mas alla del realismo, Section 7.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Jørgensen, Stig, Law and Society, pp. 86 ff. and Jørgensen, Argumentation and Decision, pp. 381 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Benditt, op. cit., pp. 13 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Makkonen, Zur Problematik der juridischen Entscheidung, p. 59. See also Hart, op. cit., p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Hart, op. cit., pp. 132 ff and especially pp. 141–142.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Hart criticizes Ross’ view also in another respect, i.e. referring to the fact that Ross does not deal with the formal validity. Hart, op. cit., pp. 28 ff. and pp. 100 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ross has answered to the criticism pointing out that the main reason for the confusion is the ambiguous meaning of the word “validity”. When Ross speaks about (factual) validity, Hart discusses about the existence of a norm. To my mind, Ross is right in this respect. Hart himself writes, e.g. that when we assert that a legal system exists “we in fact refer in compressed, portemantean form to a number of heterogeneous social facts”. The truth of this assertion can be confirmed by “reference to actual practice; to the way in which courts identify what is to count as law”. Hart, op. cit. pp. 245–246.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Here it is also very important to note how the Fascist concept of valid law was based on “general view of law and justice”. What is in accordance with the consciousness of people was the real expression of (Fascist) German law. See e.g. Dietze, H. H., Naturrecht in der Gegenwart, p. 184 and in general Kaufman, Arthur, Rechtsphilosophie und Nationalsozialismus, pp. 19ff.

    Google Scholar 

  48. This kind of conception is really very alien to the view defended in this contribution although the basic idea of the connection between the valid law and societal value base is a parallel one. Cf. what is observed later regarding the views of Otto Brusiin (Note 44). See also Aarnio, ‘Eternal and Changing Law’. In: Philosophical Perspectives in Jurisprudence, pp. 94 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Niiniluoto, Ilkka, ‘On the Truth of Norm Propositions’. Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 3 (1981), pp. 171 ff. See also Niiniluoto, ‘On Truth and Argumentation in Legal Dogmatics’, Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 2 (1981), pp. 53 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Niiniluoto, Beiheft 3. p. 176.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1987 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Aarnio, A. (1987). The Ontology of Law. In: The Rational as Reasonable. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 4. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-4700-9_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-4700-9_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-8590-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-4700-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics