Skip to main content

Truthlikeness by Distributive Normal Forms

  • Chapter
Likeness to Truth

Part of the book series: The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science ((WONS,volume 30))

  • 100 Accesses

Abstract

According to Wittgenstein statements picture reality as it is or as it might be.1 It is a notorious problem in Wittgenstein scholarship to spell out exactly what is meant by this thesis, and to reconcile Wittgenstein’s various pronouncements on the matter. This exegetical problem is not our main concern (though some light may be thrown on it by what follows) but the thesis itself is extremely suggestive, and elements of it can be used to elucidate what might at first appear to be a purely syntactic approach to the problem of rigorously characterizing truthlikeness. The concept will be defined by means of the properties of certain special formulas (strings of symbols) but this procedure is legitimate only because these formulae, suitably interpreted, picture reality, or possible kinds of states of affairs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Wittgenstein [1921]. As is usual, Wittgenstein’s own numbering of theses is used in the text here.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Hintikka [1965]. In sections 4.3 and 4.5 an intuitive account of the structure of constituents is given, and in appendix 8.4 and 8.5 a detailed mathematical account is given.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See any textbook on first-order logic; for example, Bell and Machover [1976], pp. 15–8. See also the appendix, 8.1.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Those familiar with the literature on truthlikeness will recognise here Miller’s famous hot-Minnesotan-Arizonan example. (Miller [1974], p. 176.) The argument Miller bases on this example (and others like it) is discussed in greater depth in chapter 6. It might be noted here that implicit in the discussion in 4.1 is only one way of interpreting Miller’s argument. Another completely different way will be discussed in chapter 6.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Quine [1970] pp. 4–5.

    Google Scholar 

  6. ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Carnap [1971], p. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See Niiniluoto [1977], [1978a], [1978b], [1979a], [1979b] and Tuomela [1978] and [1979]. See Niiniluoto [1982] for a reply to some of the criticisms that ensue (first published in Oddie [1981]). These replies are dealt with in later sections.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See Tichy [1976], pp. 39–40. Tichy calls this concept verisimilitude P because it seems to capture some of the ingredients of Popper’s approach to the problem.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Niiniluoto [1978b], p. 302.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See Niiniluoto [1978a], p. 448ff.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Niiniluoto [1978a], p. 448 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Niiniluoto [1982], p. 294.

    Google Scholar 

  14. ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  15. The example was originally contained in correspondence to Niiniluoto and it is reported in his [1979a], p. 371.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Niiniluoto [1979a], p. 372.

    Google Scholar 

  17. ibid., p. 375.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See note 9.

    Google Scholar 

  19. I communicated this counterexample to the d-sequence approach to Tichy in [1977]. He acknowledged it in his [1978a]. Niiniluoto also acknowledged the error in his [1978b], p. 317.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Oddie [1981], pp. 245-6. Niiniluoto’s reply, by way of an isotope example, is discussed below, section 4.5.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Tuomela [1978].

    Google Scholar 

  22. Oddie [1981], pp. 246–8.

    Google Scholar 

  23. This argument is challenged by Urbach [ 1983 ]. For a full analysis of Urbach’s paper see section 6. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See Tichy [1978b] for several such examples.

    Google Scholar 

  25. The condition that linkages be fair is elaborated in Oddie [1979a].

    Google Scholar 

  26. Niiniluoto [1979a], p. 375.

    Google Scholar 

  27. An attempt has been made, at Otago University, to programme the distance measure presented here. Although the computer gave correct results in simple cases, in more complicated cases the computer took an enormous amount of time to achieve what can be done intuitively in a much shorter time.

    Google Scholar 

  28. This was proved in conjunction with Gerard Liddell of the Mathematics Department, Otago University. The proof has not yet been published.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Niiniliioto ([1982], p. 290) complains that at this point I violate my own methodology: ‘It seems clear that in distinguishing “clear-cut” examples from “borderline cases” reference to existing definitions is permitted by Oddie. In other words, one may use putative general principles about verisimilitude in evaluating whether a given example is a “clear-cut” one or not—and this is an instance of methods which, according to Oddie’s own understanding of the nature of explication, leads to a policy of “anything goes”.’ Of course the mere fact that two theories disagree over an example does not justify the claim that the example is not clear-cut. If it did then it would indeed follow that no theory could be rejected in favour of any other—anything goes. Rather, in this case, it is simply that I do not have any strong intuition on the matter, and the claim that it is a borderline case (and not simply a deficiency on my part) is confirmed by the fact that three very closely related, only subtly different, attempts to capture the notion of closeness of fit yield three completely different judgements.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1986 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Oddie, G. (1986). Truthlikeness by Distributive Normal Forms. In: Likeness to Truth. The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol 30. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-4658-3_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-4658-3_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-8570-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-4658-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics