Skip to main content

Epistemic Foundationalism (II): Epistemic Intuitionism

  • Chapter
Empirical Justification

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series in Philosophy ((PSSP,volume 34))

  • 82 Accesses

Abstract

Epistemic intuitionism provides an account of immediate justification that is currently unpopular among foundationalists. It is notorious particularly for its reliance on the doctrine of the epistemological given. Since there are various notions of the given in circulation, there are also various versions of intuitionism. To circumscribe the relevant versions of epistemic intuitionism, I find it useful to distinguish four general kinds of given: the phenomenological given, the factual given, the linguistic given, and the epistemological given.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Here I am following James Cornman’s article ’Materialism and Some Myths about Some Givens’, The Monist 56 (1972), 216–226. For a helpful survey of various theories of the given see J. J. Ross, The Appeal to the Given ( Allen and Unwin, London, 1970 ).

    Google Scholar 

  2. See Chisholm, Theory of Knowledge (Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, 1966), pp. 27–28, and idem, Theory of Knowledge, 2d ed. ( Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, 1977 ), pp. 21–22.

    Google Scholar 

  3. A. J. Ayer suggests the following options in ’Basic Propositions’, in idem, Philosophical Essays (Macmillan, London, 1954), pp. 105–124. Cf. Alan H. Goldman, ’Appearing Statements and Epistemological Foundations’, Metaphilosophy 10 (1979), 229–230. The first of the following options is defended by Pollock in Knowledge and Justification ( Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1974 ), pp. 73–75.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See William Alston, ’Varieties of Privileged Access’, American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971), 231. Cf. Bruce Aune, Knowledge, Mind, and Nature (Random House, New York, 1967), Chapter 2, and idem, ’Chisholm on Empirical Knowledge’, in E. Sosa (ed.), Essays on the Philosophy of R. M. Chisholm (Editions Rodopi, Amsterdam, 1979), pp. 240–241. A. J. Ayer espouses something like the irrefutability thesis in ’Privacy’, in idem, The Concept of a Person (St. Martin’s Press, New York, 1963 ), p. 73.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See Sellars, ’Epistemic Principles’, in H.-N. Castañeda (ed.), Action, Knowledge, and Reality, p. 339. Cf. Lehrer, Knowledge ( Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1974 ), pp. 107 - 110.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See Quinton, The Nature of Things (Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1973), Chapter 5, and idem, ’The Foundations of Knowledge’, in B. Williams and A. Montefiore (eds.), British Analytical Philosophy ( Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1966 ), pp. 55–86.

    Google Scholar 

  7. For a summary of and references to some of the important psychological literature relevant to this notion of attention-attraction, see David I. Mostofsky, ’The Semantics of Attention’, in D. Mostofsky (ed.), Attention: Contemporary Theory and Analysis ( Appleton-Century-Crofts, New York, 1970 ), pp. 9–24.

    Google Scholar 

  8. The same is true of the accounts of immediate justification in Carl Ginet, Knowledge, Perception, and Memory (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1975), Chapter 3; John Pollock, Knowledge and Justification, Chapter 3; James Cornman, Skepticism, Justification, and Explanation (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1980), Chapter 2; and Alan Goldman, ’Appearing Statements and Epistemological Foundations’, Metaphilosophy 10 (1979), 227–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. See Alston, ’Self-Warrant: A Neglected Form of Privileged Access’, American Philosophical Quarterly 13 (1976), 267.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Cornman, Skepticism, Justification, and Explanation, pp. 33–34, and Reichenbach, ’Are Phenomenal Reports Absolutely Certain?’, Philosophical Review 61 (1952), reprinted in R. M. Chisholm and R. Swartz (eds.), Empirical Knowledge ( Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, 1973 ), pp. 354–356.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See Chisholm, Perceiving: A Philosophical Study (Cornell University Press, Ithaca, 1957), Chapter 4, and idem, Theory of Knowledge, 2d ed. ( Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, 1977 ), pp. 30–33.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See Lehrer, Knowledge, pp. 114–119.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See, for example, Chisholm, Perceiving: A Philosophical Study, Chapter 7, and James Van Cleve, ’Foundationalism, Epistemic Principles, and the Cartesian Circle’, The Philosophical Review 88 (1979), 87–90.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See, for example, Lehrer, Knowledge, pp. 121, 143–144, 152–153, and Alvin Plantinga, ’Is Belief in God Rational?’, in C. F. Delaney (ed.), Rationality and Religious Belief ( University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, 1979 ), pp. 20–26.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See Ayer, ’Phenomenalism’, in idem, Philosophical Essays (Macmillan, London, 1954), pp. 134–139; idem, The Problem of Knowledge (Penguin Books, Ltd., London, 1956), pp. 125–126; and Dicker, Perceptual Knowledge (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1980 ), pp. 193–209.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Dicker’s challenge to the deceiver hypothesis relies heavily on O. K. Bouwsma, ’Descartes’ Evil Genius’, The Philosophical Review 58 (1949), 141–151, reprinted in A. Sesonke and N. Fleming (eds.), Meta-Meditations ( Wadsworth, Belmont, CA: 1966 ).

    Google Scholar 

  17. See Lewis, An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation (Open Court, La Salle, Illinois, 1946), pp. 248–250. Cf. Lewis, The Philosopher Replies’, in P. A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of C. I. Lewis ( Open Court, La Salle, 1968 ), pp. 656–658.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See Chisholm, Theory of Knowledge, 1st ed. (Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, 1966), Chapter 3. Cf. Chisholm, Perceiving: A Philosophical Study ( Cornell University Press, Ithaca, 1957 ), Chapter 6.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Heidelberger, ’Chisholm’s Epistemic Principles’, Noûs 3 (1969), 75–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Chisholm, Theory of Knowledge, 2d ed. (Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, 1977), pp. 75–76; and idem, ’On the Nature of Empirical Evidence’, in G. S. Pappas and M. Swain (eds.), Essays on Knowledge and Justification ( Cornell University Press, Ithaca, 1978 ), pp. 269–276.

    Google Scholar 

  21. See Firth, ’Ultimate Evidence’, Journal of Philosophy 53 (1956), reprinted in R. J. Swartz (ed.), Perceiving, Sensing, and Knowing (Doubleday, Garden City, New York, 1965), pp. 486–496. For some further criticisms of Chisholm’s critical cognitivism, see Cornman, Skepticism, Justification, and Explanation, pp. 91–98, 110, and idem, ’On Justifying Nonbasic Statements by Basic-Reports’, in G. S. Pappas (ed.), Justification and Knowledge (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1979 ), pp. 138 — 141.

    Google Scholar 

  22. For some helpful suggestions in this connection, including a reply to Quine’s notorious objections, see Hilary Putnam, ’“Two Dogmas” Revisited’, and ’Analyticity and Apriority: Beyond Wittgenstein and Quine’, in Realism and Reason, Philosophical Papers, Vol. 3 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983), pp. 87–97, 115–138; and, especially, idem, ’The Analytic and the Synthetic’, in Mind, Language, and Reality, Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2 ( Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1975 ), pp. 33–69.

    Google Scholar 

  23. On this kind of probability see Carnap, ’Inductive Logic and Rational Decisions’, in R. Carnap and R. Jeffrey (eds.), Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability (University of California Press, Berkeley, 1971), p. 25; and Henry Kyburg, ’Epistemological Probability’, in Epistemology and Inference ( University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1983 ), pp. 204–216.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Here, of course, I am alluding to the forementioned distinction between propositional and doxastic justification. My present talk of “believing on the basis of” is intended to be basically equivalent to the above talk of “believing in light of”. For some other ways to construe ’believes on the basis of’ see George Pappas, ’Basing Relations’, in Justification and Knowledge, pp. 51–63. Cf. Robert Audi, ’The Causal struture of Indirect Justification’, Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983), 398–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. See, for instance, John Pollock, ’A Plethora of Epistemological Theories’, in Justification and Knowledge, pp. 98, 100; and Carl Ginet, Knowledge, Perception, and Memory (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1975), p. 125. Cf. Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind ( Hutchinson, London, 1949 ), pp. 242–243.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1985 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Moser, P.K. (1985). Epistemic Foundationalism (II): Epistemic Intuitionism. In: Empirical Justification. Philosophical Studies Series in Philosophy, vol 34. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-4526-5_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-4526-5_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-2042-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-4526-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics