Skip to main content

Distance and Similarity

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 185))

Abstract

Intuitively speaking, a statement is truthlike or verisimilar if it is like the truth’ or ‘similar to the truth’. In other words, a truthlike statement has to ‘resemble the truth’ or to be ‘close to the truth’, but it need not be true or even probable (i.e., likely to be true).1 The notion of truthlikeness or verisimilitude can thus be regarded as a special case of the more general concept of similarity or resemblance. For this reason, we shall give in this chapter a survey of the work on similarity and dissimilarity that has been done in the fields of philosophy, logic, mathematics, statistics, information theory, computer science, biology, anthropology, psychology, and linguistics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. According to John Locke, “probability is likeness to be true” (An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, 1689, Book 4, Ch. XV). In many modern languages, the concept of probability is derived from the Latin verisimilitudo by combining the words ‘true’ (Latin verum) and ‘similitude’ (cf. Hartigan, 1971), but this should not lead us to confuse these concepts with each other. For the connection between truthlikeness and probability, see Chapter 5.2 below. For an analysis of the first component in the notion of truthlikeness — i.e., the truth — see Chapter 4.3 below.

    Google Scholar 

  2. The standard abbreviation ‘iff’ for ‘if and only if’ is used in this book.

    Google Scholar 

  3. log denotes here the natural logarithm.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Boorman and Olivier (1973) note — without giving any details — that the definition (28) can be generalized to cases where A 1 and A 2 are associated with different label sets V 1 and V 2 and where all the modes in A 1 and A 2 are labeled.

    Google Scholar 

  5. For the basic concepts and results of topology, see Bourbaki (1966) and Simmons (1963).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Y is compact if every class of closed subsets of Y with empty intersection has a finite subclass with empty intersection.

    Google Scholar 

  7. F. Bacon’s (1620) method of eliminative induction can be viewed as a systematic way of exploring analogies, as Keynes (1921) observes.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See the summary in Klug (1966). For the treatment of analogy in legal reasoning, see also Niiniluoto (1983b).

    Google Scholar 

  9. See, for example, Heywood (1976), Ruse (1973), Sneath and Sokal (1973). A nice illustration of taxonomical methods is given in the exhibition Dinosaurs and their living relatives, opened at the Natural History Museum, London, in 1979. It examines the question: Which living animals are most closely related to dinosaurs? On the basis of evidence about ‘homologies’ (i.e., “characteristics that are similar because they are inherited from a common ancestor”), it comes to the conclusion: “Birds are the closest living relatives of the dinosaurs. But some scientists think that birds and crocodiles are more closely related to each other than either of them is to dinosaurs”. For example, fossil birds, fossil crocodiles, dinosaurs, pretosaurs, and thecodontians share uniquely among them the homology that they have a hole in the skull in the front of the eye socket. (See Niiniluoto, 1980b.)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Dinosaurs and Their Living Relatives, p. 17. See also Sneath and Sokal (1973), Ch.6.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Multistate qualitative characters are treated in the same way — without assuming that the states of O i can be ordered (see Sneath and Sokal, 1973, p. 115). In J. C. Gower’s (1971) general similarity coefficient Math the value of 0 ≤ S ijk ≤ 1 expresses the similarity between the states x ij and x ik and W ijk is the weight for character O i . If S ijk = |x ij x ik | for quantitative states, Gower’s coefficient is a complement of a weighted mean character difference (36). In Chapter 3.2 below we generalize this idea to cases where Q i may be multistate qualitative characters. For a treatment of similarity relation with vague properties, see Bugajski (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  12. For pattern recognition, see Fu (1977, 1982), Chen (1973).

    Google Scholar 

  13. For cluster analysis, see Chen (1973), Sneath and Sokal (1973), van Ryzin (1977), Rao (1977), Zadeh (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Rosenfeld (1969, 1976, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  15. See also Carnap (1971b, 1980), Hilpinen (1973), Goodman (1972), and Eberle (1975). For a non-psychological, physicalistic interpretation of qualities, see Armstrong (1978a, b).

    Google Scholar 

  16. See Tversky (1977), Beals, Krantz, and Tversky (1968), Krantz and Tversky (1975), Sattath and Tversky (1977), Schwarz and Tversky (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Condition (47) need not be interpreted to imply that all metrics d can be used in defining the concept of similarity.

    Google Scholar 

  18. D. Lewis (1973), who uses as a primitive concept the notion of overall similarity between possible worlds, also argues that similarity is a directional relation.

    Google Scholar 

  19. For criticism of nominalism, see Armstrong (1978a, b), Loux (1978), and Bunge (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  20. The atoms correspond to Carnap’s Q-predicates (see Chapter 2.2).

    Google Scholar 

  21. For a criticism of negative and disjunctive properties, see Armstrong (1978b).

    Google Scholar 

  22. While I agree with Armstrong’s (1978a, b) criticism of nominalism and platonism, I am inclined to accept (against his view) a ‘Stoutian’ realism, where each particular has its own individual qualities or ‘tropes’ — and universals exist only as abstractions in the man-made World 3. However, I shall not develop these ideas here further, since nothing in this book depends on a solution to the classical problem of universals.

    Google Scholar 

  23. For these terms, see Stalnaker (1968).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1987 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Niiniluoto, I. (1987). Distance and Similarity. In: Truthlikeness. Synthese Library, vol 185. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-3739-0_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-3739-0_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-8170-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-3739-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics