Skip to main content

Perception

  • Chapter
  • 77 Accesses

Part of the book series: Martinus Nijhoff Philosophy Library ((MNPL,volume 28))

Abstract

The following thoughts were taken from Meinong’s literary remains:1 In the theory of knowledge, the degree of knowledge is the relationship between knowing and that which is known. In the beginning there is perception and its object.2 This relationship is a “basic fact,” and the theory of knowledge must state it as such. “It cannot be defined what the object of our knowledge of reality is, it can only be experienced.” That is the problem of transcendence.3 With the problem of transcendence, the theory of knowledge has, to its own disadvantage, “tied a knot, and by adding new loops has created for itself a never ending maze.” Alexander’s action should be imitated: It should simply be stated as a fundamental and characteristic property of existential knowledge that it is able to transcend.4

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Kart. VII a, Erkenntnistheorie I, 1897–98.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Kart. VII, Leaf 3.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid., Leaf 4.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid, Leaf 5.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ges.Ausg.Vol. V, “Erf.;” pp. 382ff.

    Google Scholar 

  6. R. Kindinger, “Das Problem der unvollkommenen Erkenntnisleistung in der Meinongischen Wahrnehmungslehre” in Meinonggedenkschrift; compare ibid.; also Weinhandl, “Das Aussenweltproblem bei A. Meinong: The causal relationship between external objects and perception is simply accepted by Meinong because it cannot be proven.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ges. Ausg, Vol. I, “Üb. Begr. u. Eigensch. der Empfindung” p. 182: Sensation is a simple perceptual idea from peripheral stimulation, p. 183: The sensation of blue never occurs by itself. Any idea of the sensation of blue is abstract, the sensation of blue itself is not. p. 184: The contrast between concrete and abstract has no natural use in connection with the concept of sensation. Note [4]: Only in connection with complex ideas can we speak of concrete and perceptual.

    Google Scholar 

  8. In none of the works on Meinong which I read (except Findlay’s) were pseudo-objects discussed. Perhaps this can be explained with the general fear of Meinong’s alleged overpopulated universe and its consequences.

    Google Scholar 

  9. For example, Twardowski in Inhalt und Gegenstand der Vorstellungen still speaks of ideas where Meinong speaks of perception. I agree with Weinhandrs interpretation in Meinong Gedenkschrift, p. 133: “In each perception the existence of the whole thing is given.” On page 134 he compares the object which is given in perception with Kant’s Ding-an-sich, with which I am not quite in agreement as will be seen in the following. Hugo Bergmann states in Untersuchungen zum Problem der inneren Wahrnehmung (p. 60) that perception is at first a pure judgment of existence. He who otherwise is very polemical toward Meinong concurs with him in these matters.

    Google Scholar 

  10. For the following, especially judgments of being and judgments of being thus-and-so, compare Em. Pres. Introduction with footnotes; Ges. Ausg. Vol. V. “Erf.” pp. 16–30, (371) – (481), (617) –(628).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ges. Ausg. Vol. V. “Erf” compare the previous footnote. Ad objecta and complexes see Ges. Ausg. Vol. IV, Ann. II, chapter 8, and Kalsi, M. on O. of H. O., 12–19; ad objecta and analyzing judgments into ideas, Em. Pres. XXXII — LI; ad properties, Ges. Ausg. Vol. IV, Ann. II, 226, 235; and Vol. V. “Erf.” 28ff, (617); M. on O. of H. O., pp. 94ff.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ges. Ausg. Vol V, “Erf.,” p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Compare Introductions to Em. Pres, and M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ges. Ausg. Vol. IV, Ann. II, p. 281: the example of the red cross.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ges. Ausg., Vol. IV, Ann. II, pp. 25, 208, 226, 235, 237.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Karin Hermann, Dissertation, Einige Grundprobleme der Meinongischen Gegenstandstheorie, is important for Meinong’s ontology and theory of objects. Up to page 29, she discusses objectives, manners of being, objects of higher order, relati, relations, complexions, existence, and subsistence. Her discussion of relations (p. 94) seems problematical to me. Her interpretation follows Findlay’s interpretation too closely. On page 99 it contains a critique of real relati which uses Meinong’s unfortunate example of a real complex consisting of color and local determinations. (Our discussion will return to that.) Also page 107 relies too much on Findlay’s interpretation. However, the discussion of Russell’s argument against Meinong is excellent (p. 120). All in all, it seems to me that the author lacks the proper understanding of relate-complex/relation-complexion. Amazingly, pseudo-objects are completely ignored, only aussersein is mentioned.

    Google Scholar 

  17. M.on O.of H.O., pp.12ff.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  19. M. on O. of H. O., pp. 185–193; compare Karin Hermann: existing unfolding objects, pp. 48–51, especially on the timelessness of subsisting objects, a good and interesting chapter. Many references to Ernst Mally.

    Google Scholar 

  20. M.on O.of H.O.,p.17.

    Google Scholar 

  21. On the other hand, see Hermann, pp. 48, 51, 94, 99.

    Google Scholar 

  22. The following is based mainly on M. on O. of H. O., pp. 24ff.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Compare Hermann, p. 24, “Fremd- und Selbstpräsentation” The author gives an excellent and correct description of these modes of presentation.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Compare Em. Pres., Chapter I and p. XLVIII.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “Üb. Gegst. Höh. Ord.” pp. 410f, Ges. Ausg., Vol. IV, Ann. II, pp. 138,264.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Compare Ges. Ausg., Vol. II “Gedächtnis” p. 192; “G.h.O.” pp. 412f; Vol. IV, Ann. II, p. 264 and Chapter I.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, pp. 403f.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Compare M. on O. of H. O., pp. 36ff for further discussion of this subject matter.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” pp. 382f, 403f.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Compare Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.;” pp. 406ff.

    Google Scholar 

  31. I refer again to Karin Hermann’s discussion of existence and subsistence, of the apriori and aposteriori, and the apprehension of subsisting objectives on the first pages of her dissertation. I do not accept unconditionally the beliefs of the author, but they deserve our attention.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ges. Ausg.,Vol. IV, Ann. II, p.229.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Analyse,” p. 313, in connection with psychic analysis (also translated in M. on O.of H.O.).

    Google Scholar 

  34. Compare Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” p. 435 (also in M. on O. of H. O.).

    Google Scholar 

  35. Compare discussion of aussersein in Em. Pres., p. XXXVIf.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Kaki, “On Meinong’s Pseudo-Objects”; Ges. Ausg.,t Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” pp. 403f, 415f (also in M.on O.of H.O.).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” chapter 9 and pp. 414f; also M. on O. of H.O.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ges. Ausg., Vol. V, “Erf.,” p. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Concerning other-presentation, compare Em. Pres., Introduction.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II; “G.h.O.; pp. 409–415; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Ges. Ausg., Vol. V, “Erf.; pp. (425)ff, 433.

    Google Scholar 

  42. For further information concerning pseudo-objects, see Ges. Ausg., Vol. II “G.h.O.,” p. 440 to the end of the paper; M. on O. of H. O., p. 33; and Kalsi “On Mekong’s Pseudo-Objects.”

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II “G.h.O.,” pp. 415ff; also in M. on O. of H.O.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Compare Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” pp. 415ff; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” pp. 411f; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid., pp. 477, 59.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Compare Ges. Ausg., Vol. IV, Ann. II, chapter 8.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” pp. 412f; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ad sphere of ideas: M on O. of H. O., pp. 33ff; Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Psy. An.,” pp. 317f, 335ff, 388; ad sphere of judgments: M. on O. of H. O., pp. 33ff; Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, pp. 317f, 335ff, 342ff, 345, 353f, 356f, 361, 383, 392 and M. on O. of H. O.; Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” pp. 440, 479 and M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Witasek would have called them “dispositions,” compare 276ff.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Em.Pres., p.XXXVII.

    Google Scholar 

  52. For the following, compare M. on O. of H. O., pp. 32ff with footnotes; Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Psy. An.,” pp. 309–367 and also in M. on O. of H. O. In M. Gedenkschrifi, p. 138, Weinhandl demonstrates a very good understanding of Meinong’s theory of perception: The object of the perceptual idea is the concretum which is given in the judgment of existence. Objects of sensation as color, warmth, etc. are properties which are abstracted from the concretum.”

    Google Scholar 

  53. M.on O.of H.O., pp.32ff.

    Google Scholar 

  54. M. on O. of H. O., p. 32 and footnotes.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Psy. An.,” p. 333; and in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Ibid., p. 308.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Ibid., p. 409; and also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, pp. 333f, 360f; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Ibid., “Psy. An.,” pp.344ff.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Compare “On Meinong’s Pseudo-Objects,” p. 116.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Psy. An.; pp. 338f; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Ibid., pp. 314f, 317f.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Ibid., pp. 352f.

    Google Scholar 

  64. The reader is referred to M. on O. of H. O., p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Psy. An.,” pp. 347f, also in M. on O. of H. O.; but compare Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” chapter 19, also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Compare example in Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Psy. An.,” p. 347; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  67. M. on O. of H. O., p. 16 and footnotes; Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.” chapter 6; also in M. on O. of H. O. In her dissertation Karin Hermann discusses also Meinong’s theory of relations and real relates (p. 99). Unfortunately she criticizes only this unlucky example and does not pay any attention to the theory which the example is supposed to illustrate. Thus her interpretation, which follows Findlay closely, is full of misunderstandings. All in all, however, her book is important, but must be read with care.

    Google Scholar 

  68. M. on O. of H. O., pp. 32ff; Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Psy. An.” chapters 1–4; also in M. on O.of H.O.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Ges. Ausg., Vol. V, pp. (394), (405)ff, 21.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” third section; also in M. on O. of H. O.; see Hans Schermann, Meinong und Husserl Eine vergleichende Studie, pp. 263ff, concerning Meinong’s theory of the perception of temporally extended objects. My understanding of these matters differs considerably from Schermann. But his dissertation discusses mainly the thematic relationships between Husserl and Meinong.

    Google Scholar 

  71. For a detailed description of idea production, see M. on O. of H. O., pp. 30ff; Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Kompl. u. Rel.,” pp. 293ff; also in M. on O. of H. O.; Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” chapter 7, pp. (397)ff; also in M. on O. of H. O.; Vol. IV, Ann. II, pp. 279f.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Ad objects of higher order compare M. on O. of H. O., Introduction, Section III.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.;” Chapter 7, pp. 397ff; also in M. on O. of H. O.; Ges. Ausg., Vol IV, Ann. II, p.279.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Compare Ges. Ausg., Vol. IV, Ann. IV, p. 279; Vol. II, p. 398; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Weinhandl writes in Meinonggedenkschrifi, p. 139, that foundation accomplishes the same for objects of higher order as does perception for the ideas of real objects. The idea of the thing is not founded but is given in perception. P. 143: “After the causal connection the cognitive achievement follows.” — A very good understanding of Meinong’s perceptual theory.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, p. 398; also in M. on O. of H. O.; Vol. IV, Ann. II, p. 279f.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  78. M.on O.of H.O., pp.30f.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Ibid., pp 397ff.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Kompl. und Rel.,” p. 293; also in M. on O. of H. O., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” p. 398; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” p. 399; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Kompl. und. Rel,” pp. 296f; also in M. on O. of H. O.; Vol. V, “Erf.;” pp. 25ff.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Ges. Ausg., Vol. V, “Erf.; pp. 19, 20, 22ff!!, 29, (406).

    Google Scholar 

  84. Ges. Ausg., Vol. H, “G.h.O.,” p. 445; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  85. M. on O. of H. O., paragraphs 19 and 21.

    Google Scholar 

  86. See M. on O. of H. O.: Complexions, Complexes; Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” p. 448, example on p. 461 of the train and the bird call; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, p. 460; Vol. I, pp. 443ff; both in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Ges. Ausg., Vol. V, “Erf.,” pp. 20ff, 29!, (478), 64,66; Vol. II, “Humest. II,” p. 128.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Husserl writes very critically about the example of the rolling ball, but he does not contribute to the understanding of Meinong’s example. In Husseriiana, Vol. X (p. 223), perception is taken as a continuous event. Husserl believes in “Kontinuierlich aufeinanderfolgende Jetztwahmehmungen” (p. 226). We cannot have ideas of distributed objects by means of indistributed contents. That is mathematical abstraction, he says (p. 227). In the perception of a melody, the perception of the last note is the perception of the melody. Husserl ignores idea production completely (p. 226). His remarks are critical and polemical.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” (also in M. on O. of H. O.) pp. 443ff, 448f, 450, 455, 457f, 459, 461, 465; Vol. V, “Erf.,” p. 66; Vol. IV, Ann. II, p. 76f; Vol. I, p. 443ff; also in M. on O. of H.O.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” p. 461.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Compare Ges. Ausg., Vol. II, “G.h.O.,” p. 421; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Ges. Ausg., Vol. I, “Psy. An.,” p. 354; also in M. on O. of H. O.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1987 Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kalsi, ML.S. (1987). Perception. In: Meinong’s Theory of Knowledge. Martinus Nijhoff Philosophy Library, vol 28. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-3641-6_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-3641-6_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-8129-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-3641-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics