Skip to main content

Storyability and Eventfulness

Beyond Referential Theories of Narrative

  • Chapter
  • 154 Accesses

Part of the book series: Martinus Nijhoff Philosophy Library ((MNPL,volume 16))

Abstract

The relationship between the Storyrealm and the Taleworld is commonly presumed to be referential. The presumption of referentiality is enhanced in anecdotes whose Taleworlds can easily be supposed to be real. The story is then understood to be shaped by, and in turn to direct attention to, aspects of reality. The fallacy of this presumption can be brought out by examining the relationship between Storyrealm and Taleworld where the Taleworld is not real but fictive. The sense in which fictions refer to anything at all is unclear. In considering the relationship between the Storyrealm and the Taleworld, then, it will be revealing to see whether the constitution of the Taleworld, the relationship between the Taleworld and the Storyrealm, and the relationship between the Taleworld and the real are the same or different for fictions and true stories. The traditional move in narrative theory has been to locate the difference between the fictive and the real in the constitution of the Taleworld: imaginary realms yield fictions; real ones yield true stories. This move is confounded by two difficulties: one, the sense in which realities do not yield true stories; and the other, the sense in which imaginary realms do not yield fictions.

A story is made out of events to the extent that plot makes events into a story. Paul Ricoeur

The argument for stories as reconstitutions was first given as a paper called “Against Referentiality in Storytelling” at the 1977 California Folklore Society Meetings, Pitzer College, California. This became part of a later version called “Storyability and Eventfulness,” given at the 1981 American Folklore Society Meetings, San Antonio, Texas.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Paul Ricoeur, “Narrative Time”, Critical Inquiry 7, #1, (Autumn 1980), pp. 169–190, p. 171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Marie-Laure Ryan, “Fiction, Non-factuals, and the Principle of Minimal Departure,” Poetics 9 (1980) pp. 403–422, p. 406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Schutz, p. 253.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Jason, p. 210.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Goffran, p. 256.

    Google Scholar 

  6. The notion of interstitial categories has been extended from Arnold Van Gennep’s work by such practicioners as Mary Douglas and Victor Turner. Arnold Van Gennep, The Rites of Passage (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960);

    Google Scholar 

  7. Mary Douglas, Purity and Danger (Middlesex, England: Pelican, 1970);

    Google Scholar 

  8. Victor Turner, The Forest of Symbols (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  9. See Jason, p. 208 and elsewhere.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Natanson, The Journeying Self (Reading, Massachusetts; Menlo Park, California; London; Don Mills, Ontario: Addison-Wesley, 1970), p. 37.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Alfred Schutz, On Phenomenology and Social Relations, Helmut R. Wagner, Tr. (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1973) p. 254.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See also Nelson Goodnan, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis: 1978) p. x, on the general intellectual movement away from assumptions of “a world fixed and found” to the recognition of “a diversity of…. versions or worlds in the making.”

    Google Scholar 

  13. Barbara Herrnstein Smith, On the Margins of Discourse (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1978), p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Smith, p. 84.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Smith, p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Smith, p. 29. Another and powerful readering of this argument is Ryan’s, adapted from John Searle: people telling fictious are people pretending to be people telling true stories, in what Searle distinguishes as pretending to refer as opposed to referring seriously. Both intend to move away from supposing that fictions refer to imaginery events and both run into similar difficulties with, among other things, the proliferation of theoretical entities and the ontological ambiguity of anecdotes. They make a move toward the theory I propose, though, in shifting the locus of the distinction between the fictive and the real from the Storyrealm to the intentionality of the tellers or hearers: the notion of pretending to be somebody else, or what Ryan calls substitute speakers. Ryan, pp. 412–413; John Searle, “The Logical/Status of Fictions,” New Literal History 6 (1975). pp. 319–332.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See Raymond Williams, Marxism and Literature (Oxford: Oxford university Press, 1977), pp. 147–148: “there was a falsification--a false distancing--of ‘fictional’ or the ‘imaginary’ (and connected with these the ‘subjective’). And there was a related suppression of the fact of writing--active signifying composition--in what was distinguished as the ‘practica,’ the ‘factual’ or the ‘discoursive.’ These consequences are profoundly related. To move, by defintion, from the ‘creative’ to the ‘fictional’, or from the ‘imaginative’ to the ‘imaginary’, is to deform the real practices of writing under the pressure of the interpretation of certain specific forms. The extreme negative definition of ‘fiction’ (or of ‘myth’)--an account of ‘what did not (really) happen’--depends, evidently, on a pseudo-positive isolation of the contrasting definition, ‘fact.’”

    Google Scholar 

  18. Roger Abrahams, “The Play of Worlds in Story and Storytelling”, chapter of unpublished work-in-progress tentatively titled Goings On: Between Acts and Enactments (university of Texas, Austin), p. 41

    Google Scholar 

  19. Maurice Natanson, Literature. Philosophy and the Social Sciences (The Hague: Mouton, 1962), p. 193.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Samuel Butler is supposed to have remarked that God can’t change history, historians can.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Contrast John Austin, How to do Things with Words (New York: Oxford Uuniversity Press, 1965), p. 22 on etiolations of language.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See Jonathan Culler, “Fabula and Sjuzhet in the Analysis of Narrative”, Poetics Today 1 #3 (1980), pp. 27–37, p.33, on the recurrent opposition between “the priority and determining power of events and the determination of events by structures of significantion”.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. William Labov and Joshua Waletzky, “Narrative Analysis: Oral Versions of Personal Experience: in June Helm, ed., Essays in the Verbal and Visual Arts (Seattle and London: University of Washington Press, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  24. See Goffman, pp. 156–157.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Labov has been exploring the legal notions of eye-witness and hearsay evidence with respect to narrative. unpublished Lectures (University of Pennsylvania: 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Labov, “The Transformation of Experience in Narrative Syntax” in his Language in the Inner City (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1972), p. 371.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Harvey Sacks, Upublished Lecture Notes (University of California, Irvine: 1970), Lecture III, p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Sacks (1970), I, p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See Natanson, The Journeying Self, p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Natanson, The Journeying Self, p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Natanson, The Journeying Self, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Sacks (1970) I, p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Sacks (1970) III, p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  34. See Sacks (1970) III, p. 20.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Labov, Language in the Inner City, p. 359.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Goffman, pp. 506–507.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Sacks (1971) VI, p. 5: “So in a way a present is designedly isolated. By ‘designedly’ again, I mean to point up that the pasts before that present are set up to arrive at that as a present, and that present is used, then, to project futures. So it has this fine temporal organization to it, in which a range of tenses are manipulated to isolate a present. The present that’s isolated is itself used as a platform for projecting futures.”

    Google Scholar 

  38. Sacks (1968) Topic, p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Sacks (1970) III, p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Hayden White, “The Value of ISferrativity in the Representation of Reality”, Critical Inquiry 7, #1 (Autumn 1980), p. 14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. See Amy Shuman, “Retellings: Storytelling and Writing among Urban Adolescents” (Philadelphia: Ph.D. Thesis, University of Pennsylvania, 1981), p. 246. She distinguishes between events and experiences, arguing that “events are categories of experience, not to be confused with the experiences themselves.”

    Google Scholar 

  42. See White, p. 26, on closure.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, ed. Bertrand Russell (London: Routledge and Paul, 1933).

    Google Scholar 

  44. Abraham Kaplan, The Conduct of Inquiry (San Francisco: Chandler, 1964), p. 265.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Gregory Bateson, Steps to an Ecology of Mind (New York: Ballantine, 1972), p. 180.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, G.E.M. Anscombe, tr. (New York: Macmillan, 1953).

    Google Scholar 

  47. Benjamin Lee Whorf, Language, Thought and Reality (Cambridge: M.I.T. Press, 1969), p. 214: “We are thus introduced to a new principle of relativity, which holds that all observers are not led by the same physical evidence to the same picture of the universe, unless their linguistic backgrounds are similar, or can in some way be calibrated.”

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ryan, “The Pragmatics of Personal and Imperrsonal Fiction,” Poetics 10 (1981), pp. 517–531, p. 530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Ricoeur, p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  50. White, p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Sacks (1971) IX, p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Goffman, pp. 550 and 557.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Goffman, unpublished Lecture (University of Pennsylvania, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  54. Dell Hymes and Courtney Cazden, “Narrative Thinking and Storytelling Rights: A Folklorist1s Clue to a Critique of Education”, Keystone Folklore 22 #1 and 2 (1978), p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  55. White, pp. 8 and 27.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Ricoeur, p. 184.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Victor Turner, “Social Dramas and Stories about them,” Critical Inquiry 7 #1 (1980), p. 161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. Ricoeur, p. 178.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Richard Vfollheim, Art and Its Objects (New York, Evanston, London: Harper and Row, 1968), p. 75.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1987 Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Young, K.G. (1987). Storyability and Eventfulness. In: Taleworlds and Storyrealms. Martinus Nijhoff Philosophy Library, vol 16. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-3511-2_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-3511-2_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-247-3456-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-3511-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics