Advertisement

On Experimental Questions

  • Risto Hilpinen
Chapter
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 195)

Abstract

According to R. G. Collingwood, “every statement that anybody ever makes is made in answer to a question”.2 Collingwood takes this to be an important characteristic of scientific thinking:

In proportion as a man is thinking scientifically when he makes a statement, he knows that his statement is the answer to a question and knows what that question is. In proportion as he is thinking unscientifically he does not know these things.3

Philosophers have studied science both as a product and as a process. The investigation of “the language of science”, the structure of theories, and the conditions of their justification has been mainly concerned with science as a product; this line of investigation dominated the philosophy of science of the 1930’s and 1940’s. When philosophers became interested in questions of discovery, theory change and scientific progress, scientific rationality, and the interplay of theory and observation (or experiment) in science, they began to look at science as activity, viz. as a process of inquiry. In this context questions about the values and aims of science are unavoidable, and it is natural to adopt Collingwood’s general standpoint: the purpose of inquiry is to find satisfactory answers to the questions in which scientists are interested.

Keywords

Belief System Rational Belief Complete Answer Primary Question Satisfactory Answer 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. 2.
    R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Metaphysics ,Clarendon Press, Oxford 1940, p. 23.Google Scholar
  2. 6.
    C. G. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation ,Collier-Macmillan Ltd., London 1965.Google Scholar
  3. 7.
    Isaac Levi, The Enterprise of Knowledge ,MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. and London, 1980, ch. 2.Google Scholar
  4. 8.
    Frank P. Ramsey in ‘Knowledge’, in F. P. Ramsey, The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays ,ed. by R. B. Braithwaite, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London 1931, pp. 258–259.Google Scholar
  5. 8a.
    David Makinson in ‘The Paradox of the Preface’, Analysis 25 (1964), pp. 205–207CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. 8b.
    Henry E. Kyburg, Probability and the Logic of Rational Belief ,Wesleyan University Press, Middletown, Conn., 1961, p. 197.Google Scholar
  7. 9.
    Risto Hilpinen, ‘Approximate Truth and Truthlikeness’, in Formal Methods in the Methodology of Empirical Sciences ,ed. by M. Przelecki, K. Szaniawski, and R. Wojcicki, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1976, pp. 19–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. 9a.
    Graham Oddie, Likeness to Truth ,D. Reidel, Dordrecht 1986,Google Scholar
  9. 10.
    David Miller, ‘On the Accuracy of Predictions’, Synthese 30 (1975), pp. 159–191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. 11.
    Miller’s result has been interpreted in this way be Roger Rosenkrantz in his comment on Miller’s paper, Truth-likeness: Comment on David Miller’, Synthese 30 (1975), pp. 193–197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. 12.
    Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce ,Vol. V, ed. by C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. 1934, paragraph 5.584.Google Scholar
  12. 13.
    See Lennart Aqvist, A New Approach to the Logical Theory of Interrogatives, Part I: Analysis ,Filosofiska Föreningen i Uppsala, Uppsala 1965Google Scholar
  13. 13a.
    Jaakko Hintikka, The Semantics of Questions and the Questions of Semantics ,Acta Philosophica Fennica 28:4, North-Holland, Amsterdam 1976; ‘Answers to Questions’, in Questions ,ed. by Henry Hiz, D. Reidel, Dordrecht 1975. pp. 279 -300;Google Scholar
  14. 15.
    Robert K. Shope, The Analysis of Knowing: A Decade of Research ,Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J. 1983, pp. 5–19.Google Scholar
  15. 18.
    Cf. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason ,transl. by Norman Kemp Smith, Macmillan, London 1964, p. 20 (B: xiii); Jaakko Hintikka, ‘On the Logic of an Interrogative Model of Scientific Inquiry’, p. 69; Lisa Jardine, Francis Bacon: Discovery and the Art of Discourse ,Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1974, pp. 136–137.Google Scholar
  16. 21.
    Lennart Åqvist, ‘Scattered Topics in Interrogative Logic’, in Philosophical Logic ,ed. by J. W. Davis et al., D. Reidel, Dordrecht 1969, pp. 114–121Google Scholar
  17. 22.
    Risto Hilpinen, ‘On the Information Provided by Observations’, in Information and Inference ,ed. by Jaakko Hintikka and P. Suppes, D. Reidel, Dordrecht 1970, pp. 97–122 (cf. pp. 115–116).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. 24.
    Allan Franklin, ‘What Makes a ‘Good’ Experiment?’, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 (1981), pp. 367–374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 25.
    See Herbert A. Simon et al., ‘Scientific Discovery as Problem Solving’, Synthese 47 (1981), p. 7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. 26.
    Ian Hacking, Representing and Intervening ,Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1983, pp. 155–156.Google Scholar
  21. 26a.
    Allan Franklin, ‘The Epistemology of Experiment’ (Review of I. Hacking, Representing and Intervening), The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35 (1984), pp. 381–401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© D. Reidel Publishing Company 1988

Authors and Affiliations

  • Risto Hilpinen
    • 1
    • 2
  1. 1.University of TurkuFinland
  2. 2.University of MiamiUSA

Personalised recommendations