Skip to main content

Reasoning about Knowledge in Philosophy: The Paradigm of Epistemic Logic

  • Chapter
The Logic of Epistemology and the Epistemology of Logic

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 200))

Abstract

The main vehicle of speaking and reasoning about knowledge in philosophy has recently been epistemic logic.1 Even though epistemic logic is not the only relevant language-game in town, it offers a useful perspective here, for certain other approaches can be thought of as improvements on epistemic logic. In its axiomatic-deductive forms, epistemic logic is normally considered a branch of modal logic, and its semantics is usually subsumed under the misleading heading of “possible-worlds semantics”. I will not attempt here a survey of the existing literature on epistemic logic.2 Most of this literature is focused on syntactical (e.g., deductive and axiomatic) methods of dealing with knowledge representation and reasoning about knowledge. This is in my view a serious defect in much of the current work on epistemic logic. For typically the most interesting problems and solutions are found by considering the model-theoretical (semantical) situation. For this reason, I will not attempt here a survey of existing literature, but a review of some of the central conceptual problems arising in epistemic logic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. The idea of epistemic logic goes back at least to G.H. von Wright: 1951, An Essay in Modal Logic, North-Holland, Amsterdam. The first book-length treatment was my: 1962, Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions, Cornell U.P., Ithaca.

    Google Scholar 

  2. For a partial survey of earlier work, see Wolfgang Lenzen: 1978, Recent Work in Epistemic Logic (Acta Philosophica Fennica 30, no. 1), Societas Philosophica Fennica, Helsinki.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See here, e.g., Melvin Fitting: 1969, Intuitionistic Logic, Model Theory, and Forcing, North-Holland, Amsterdam;

    Google Scholar 

  4. Kenneth A. Bowen: 1979, Model Theory for Modal Logic, D. Reidel, Dordrecht. These treatises are not addressed to the specific problems of epistemic logic, however.

    Google Scholar 

  5. In the earlier literature, the knower used to be indicated by a subscript. This is misleading, however, for the term referring to the knower is not within the scope of the epistemic operator.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Some philosophers have tried to find a difference in principle between the two kinds of applications. It is nevertheless clearer in epistemic logic than in some of the parallel theories that the intended applications have always been to “small worlds”, to use L.J. Savage’s phrase.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See Jon Barwise and John Perry: 1983, Situations and Attitudes, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass..

    Google Scholar 

  8. See here Jaakko Hintikka: 1976, The Semantics of Questions and the Questions of Semantics (Acta Philosophica Fennica, 28, no. 4), Societas Philosophica Fennica, Helsinki.

    Google Scholar 

  9. The question here is under what conditions existential generalization is valid in epistemic logic. The conditions are of course the same as the conditions on valid universal instantiation dealt with in sec. 2, part ii, below.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cf. here chapter 1 of my book: 1974, The Intentions of Intentionality, D. Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  11. I am assuming that a distinction is made between those name-like free singular terms which pick out the same individual from different worlds and those that might refer to different individuals in different worlds. Here “z” is assumed to be of the former kind.

    Google Scholar 

  12. This matter will be dealt with in a greater detail in a projected monograph of mine.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See here chapters 3–4 of my book: 1974, The Intentions of Intentionality, D. Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Bertrand Russell: 1917, ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description’, in Mysticism and Logic, George Allen & Unwin, London;

    Google Scholar 

  15. chapter 5 of: 1912, The Problems of Philosophy, Home University Library, London, and cf. Jaakko Hintikka, Knowledge by Acquaintance - Individuation by Acquaintance, in D.F. Pears (ed.): 1972, Bertrand Russell (Modern Studies in Philosophy), Doubleday, Garden City, N.J., 52–79.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See Endel Tulving: 1983, Elements of Episodic Memory, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See Lucia Vaina, From Vision to Cognition: A Computational Theory of Higher-Level Visual Functions, Kluwer, Dordrecht, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf., e.g., Noam Chomsky: 1982, The Generative Enterprise, Foris, Dordrecht. From what is reported in the rest of this section, this objection against possible-worlds analysis of knowledge was effectively disposed of more than ten years ago.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Jaakko Hintikka: 1973, Logic, Language-Games, and Information, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See Jaakko Hintikka: 1986, ‘Mental Models, Semantical Games, and Varieties of Intelligence’, in Lucia Vaina, ed., Varieties of Intelligence, D. Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  21. The so-called paraconsistent logics have never been given any realistic model-theoretical and pragmatic interpretation, and hence have in their present form little interest. Cf. here Nicholas Rescher and Robert Brandom: 1979, The Logic of Inconsistency, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See Veikko Rantala: 1975, ‘Urn Models: A New Kind of Non-Standard Model for First-Order Logic’, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4, 455–474, reprinted in Esa Saarinen (ed): 1979, Game-Theoretical Semantics, D. Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. The first time this interesting phenomenon was pointed out in the literature is in Lauri Carlson and Alice ter Meulen: 1972, ‘Informational Independence in Intensional Context’, in Esa Saarinen et al., (eds.): 1979, Essays in Honour of Jaakko Hintikka, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 61–72.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See here Esa Saarinen (ed.), Game-Theoretical Semantics,

    Google Scholar 

  25. Jaakko Hintikka and Jack Kulas: 1983, The Game of Language, D. Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  26. For branching quantifier structures, there exists a growing body of studies. For references, see the bibliography of Jaakko Hintikka and Jack Kulas: op. cit. Independences between other kinds of concepts have scarcely been studied, except for the papers referred to here.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See here Jaakko Hintikka: 1982, ‘Questions with Outside Quantifiers’, in R. Schneider, K. Tuite and R. Chametzky (eds.), Papers from the Parasession on Nondeclaratives, Chicago Linguistic Society, Chicago, 83–92.

    Google Scholar 

  28. See here Jaakko Hintikka: 1974, ‘Quantifiers vs. Quantification Theory’, Linguistic Inquiry, 5, 153–77, reprinted in Esa Saarinen (ed).:1979, Game-Theoretical Semantics, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 367–379.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See, e.g., Danny Dolev, Joseph Y. Halpern and Yoram Moses: 1985, ‘Cheating Husbands and Other Stories: A Case Study of Knowledge, Action and Communication’, preprint.

    Google Scholar 

  30. The model sketched here has been studied in a number of papers of mine. See, e.g., Jaakko Hintikka and Merrill B. Hintikka: 1982,‘Sherlock Holmes Encounters Modern Logic: Towards a Theory of Information-Seeking by Questioning’, in E.M. Barth and J.L. Martens, Argumentation: Approaches to Theory Formation, Benjamins, Amsterdam, 55–76; ‘The Logic of Science as a Model-Oriented Logic’, in RD. Asquith and P. Kitcher (eds.): 1984, PSA 1984, 1, Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, MI, 177–85.

    Google Scholar 

  31. As a book-keeping device we can use a Beth-type semantical tableau. (For them, see W. Beth: 1955, ‘Semantic Entailment and Formal Derivability’, Mededelingen van de Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen, Afd. Letterkunde, N.R. 18, no. 13, Amsterdam, 309–42.) Then we can use all the usual terminology of the tableau method, and the deductive “moves” will be simply tableau-building rules. (We shall minimize movements between the left and the right column, however, and restrict the rules to those in keeping with the subformula principle.) Each application of the game rules is then relative to a given stage of some one subtableau. As is well known, the tableau method is simply the mirror image of a Gentzen-type sequent calculus. The only novelty here is that Nature’s answers are centered into the left column of a subtableau as additional premises.

    Google Scholar 

  32. For the concept of presupposition presupposed here, see Jaakko Hintikka: 1976, The Semantics of Questions and the Questions of Semantics (Acta Philosophica Fennica, 28, no. 4), Societas Philosophica Fennica, Helsinki.

    Google Scholar 

  33. An excellent example of what can be done in this direction is Lauri Carlson: 1982, Dialogue Games, D. Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  34. This observation has important consequences for the contemporary philosophy of science, where it has generally been assumed that only questions concerning the truth of falsity of atomic sentences are answered by Nature. In reality, the logic of experimental inquiry is an AE logic, not the logic of the atomistic case.

    Google Scholar 

  35. The notions of subformula principle, cut elimination, Gentzen’s Hauptsatz, etc. are explained in any decent introduction to proof theory. For Gentzen’s classical papers, see M.E. Szabo (ed.): 1969, The Collected Paper of Gerhard Gentzen, North-Holland, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hintikka, J., Hintikka, M.B. (1989). Reasoning about Knowledge in Philosophy: The Paradigm of Epistemic Logic. In: The Logic of Epistemology and the Epistemology of Logic. Synthese Library, vol 200. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2647-9_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2647-9_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-7923-0041-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2647-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics