Skip to main content

Dialectic, Rhetoric and Critique in Aristotle

  • Chapter
Book cover From Metaphysics to Rhetoric

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 202))

  • 168 Accesses

Abstract

The term “dialectic” is one of those words which philosophers have not stopped making use of since Antiquity, enriching it with such a variety of meanings that today, when we go to use it, we are deeply troubled. In Aristotelian terminology, it has become a plurivocal or equivocal term, a pollachôs legomenon. It is henceforth easy to understand that at the moment when contemporary philosophy undertook a spectacular return to Aristotelian methodology, it was very scrupulous in its use of it. These scruples are most clearly exemplified by Chaïm Perelman who, when he introduced the “new rhetoric” with L. Olbrechts-Tyteca, preferred to eliminate it from the theory of argumentation.1 Moreover, it is in this context that argumentation subsequently developed, claiming, as it did, to go beyond the field of rhetoric.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Ch. Perelman and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca, La nouvelle rhétorique. Traité de l’argumentation, Vol. 1, Paris, 1958, pp. 1–13, esp. pp. 6–8.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ch. Perelman, «La methode dialectique et le rôle de l’interlocuteur dans le dialogue», Entretiens philosophiques d’Athènes, Athens, 1955, pp. 179–183.

    Google Scholar 

  3. And when it does appear, it does so in an altogether different context.

    Google Scholar 

  4. The New Rhetoric, p.7

    Google Scholar 

  5. This absence is already significant on its own, and allows us to understand, at least partially, the orientation that the “new rhetoric” takes: dissimulating, as we shall see, the critical part of the Aristotelian dialectic.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Once again the use of the term antistrophos registers a distance in the correspondence (Rhet. I.1.1354a.1) — which is limited, as we shall see, to the syllogistic character of rhetoric and by which Aristotle’s rhetoric ensures its difference with the preceding rhetorics.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Cf. Top. I.12.105a.10–19. See also our study «Y a-t-il une intuition des principes chez Aristote», Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 133–134, 1980, pp. 440–471.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Rhet., I.2.1356a.34–b27.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid., 1357b.26–36.

    Google Scholar 

  10. On this question, Aristotle sometimes speaks of a difference governed by proairésis.

    Google Scholar 

  11. On the meaning to assign to the endoxon, see our study «Dialectique et philosophic chez Aristote», πιλοσοϕια, 8–9, 1978–1979, pp. 229–256, 231–232, where we speak of a “statement containing some value” or of a “generally accepted consideration”.

    Google Scholar 

  12. On this question, see Pierre Hadot, «Philosophic, Dialectique, Rhétorique dans l’antiquité«, Stadia Philosophica, 39, 1980, pp. 139–166, 140–146, who nonetheless loses sight, as moreover most interpreters of Aristotle do, of the “critical” aspect of dialectic.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Cf. our study «Dialectique et philosophic chez Aristote», cited above, pp. 231–235.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See our study «Le problème de la proairisis chez Aristote», Annales de l’Institut de Philosophie de l’U.L.B., 1972, pp. 7–50.

    Google Scholar 

  15. On the matter of agônistikè see in particular Top. VII.5.

    Google Scholar 

  16. The importance of the learned man was first noted by P. Aubeneque, Le problème de l’être chez Aristote, Paris, 1962, Ch. III. As far as the limits of this interpretation, see our article «Dialectique et Philosophie chez Aristote», op. cit., pp. 238 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Reported thus in the Politique.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. our study «Sophisma et Philosophia chez Aristote», Annales de l’Institut de Philosophie de l’U.L.B., 1978, pp. 7–38.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See our article «Dialectique et philosophie chez Aristote», op. cit., pp. 231 ff., where an analysis of the meaning and scope of this essential passage from Aristotle will be found.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See N°. 11 below.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Here it is a matter of a crucial point in Aristotelian dialectic: which we have established in our «Dialectique et philosophie chez Aristote», op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Indeed, we cannot lose sight of the fact that, for Aristode, refutation is an inference which is contradictory to the beginning argument (Ref. Soph. 2.165a.38ff.; 6.168a.36ff.; 10.171a.195, etc.).

    Google Scholar 

  23. See again «Dialectique et philosophie chez Aristote», op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Here we are paraphrasing the passage between 167b.1 and b.20.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. J. Tricot, In ref. soph. (J. Vrin), p. 20 n.2.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Top.I.1.100b.21–23.

    Google Scholar 

  27. I here paraphrase Ch. Perelman, «La méthode dialectique et le rôle de l’interlocuteur dans le dialogue», op. cit., p. 181.

    Google Scholar 

  28. On this subject, see how he emphasizes his aporetic method in Métaph. B.1.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Cf. E. Berti, «Aristote et la méthode dialectique du Parménide de Platon», Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 133–134, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Cf. L’avènement de la science physique. Essai sur la Physique d’ Aristote, Brussels, 1980, pp. 131 ff., where we develop this problem in a more detailed manner.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid., pp. 139 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  32. This study begins in Phys. I.7, along the lines of an analysis of general becoming and ends in the institution of the principles of becoming according to the ousia. See our book, cited above, pp. 154ff.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid.,pp. 191 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  34. See our study «Dialectique et philosophic chez Aristote», op. cit., pp. 243 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ch. Perelman, «La méhode dialectique et le rôle de rinterlocuteur dans le dialogue», op. cit., p. 181.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Even if this knowledge established by the critique of preceding opinions and by the implementation of new methodological data appears retrospectively to be a new “opinion”.

    Google Scholar 

  37. It is moreover significant that while histories of rhetoric are prevalent today, the history of dialectic is still neglected — in particular with regard to its critical aspect and its dogmatization repeated by various philosophical currents.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Couloubaritsis, L. (1989). Dialectic, Rhetoric and Critique in Aristotle. In: Meyer, M. (eds) From Metaphysics to Rhetoric. Synthese Library, vol 202. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2593-9_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2593-9_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7672-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2593-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics