Skip to main content

Linguistic Reflexivity and ‘Pseudorationalism’

  • Chapter
Reflexive Epistemology

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 118))

Abstract

The Vienna Circle’s 1929 ‘manifesto’ was dedicated to Schlick and involved, as we have noted, the participation of Carnap. Little more than a year later Neurath opened his philosophical attack on each of these two. Earlier than this, however, in 1928, he had published in the journal of the Austrian Social Democratic Party, ‘Der Kampf, a joint review of two works by Carnap: Der logische Aufbau der Welt and Scheinprobleme in der Philosophie.1 There he portrayed Carnap as an exponent of Viennese ‘empirical rationalism’ fighting a minority battle against theology and metaphysics (and especially Kantianism) in the university schoolrooms, a battle initiated by the adherents of French enlightenment and materialism and more recently taken further by such scientists as Mach, Avenarius, Poincaré, Russell, Reichenbach and Schlick.2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Cf. Der Kampf, 21 (1928), pp. 624–6, now in GpmS, pp. 295–7.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ibid., GpmS, pp. 295–6.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid., p. 296. On the relationship between Carnap’s Konstitutionssystem and Neurath’s physicalism see E. Runggaldier, ‘Das Problem der ‘Darstellung’ bei Neurath und Carnap’, in Wittgenstein, der Wiener Kreis und der Kritische Rationalismus, pp. 245–7.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cf. O. Neurath, Review of R. Carnap, Der logische Aufbau der Welt, [1928a], GpmS, p. 296.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Erkenntnis, 1 (1930–31), pp. 106–25, English trans. PP, pp. 32–47.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cf. R. Haller, ‘Geschichte und wissenschaftliches System bei Otto Neurath’, in Wittgenstein, der Wiener Kreis und der Kritische Rationalismus, p. 306.

    Google Scholar 

  7. O. Neurath, ‘Wege der wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung’, Erkenntnis, 1 (1930–31), pp. 107–8, 116, English trans. PP, p. 33.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., p. 108, PP, pp. 33–4;

    Google Scholar 

  9. cf.: O. Neurath, Empirische Soziologie, Wien: Julius Springer, 1931, now in GpmS, pp. 426–35, English trans. ES, pp. 319–421

    Google Scholar 

  10. O. Neurath, ‘Magie und Technik’, Erkenntnis, 2 (1931), pp. 529–31.

    Google Scholar 

  11. O. Neurath, ‘Wege der wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung’, [1930/31], pp. 108–10, PP, pp. 33–5.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., p. 111, PP, p. 36.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid., p. 123, PP, p. 46.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., p. 118, PP, p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid., p. 117, PP, p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid., p. 123, PP, p. 46.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid., p. 108, PP, p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid, loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  19. cf. O. Neurath, ‘Physicalism: The Philosophy of the Viennese Circle’, The Monist, 41 (1931), p. 621, now also in PP, pp. 49–50.

    Google Scholar 

  20. O. Neurath, ‘Wege der wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung’. [1930/31], p. 119, PP, p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., p. 122, PP, p. 45

    Google Scholar 

  23. cf. O. Neurath, Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener Kreis, [1929], GpmS, p. 310, ES, p. 312.

    Google Scholar 

  24. O. Neurath, ‘Wege der wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung’, [1930/31], p. 122, PP, p. 45. On causationism, and the need for overcoming it, see the lively debate in Erkenntnis, 1 (1930–31), with essays of H. Reichenbach, R. von Mises, P. Hertz, F. Waismann, H. Feigl.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See also A. Pannekoek, ‘Das Wesen der Naturgesetzes’, ibid., 3 (1932–33), pp. 389–400.

    Google Scholar 

  26. O. Neurath, ‘Wege der wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung’, [1930/31], p. 122, PP, p.45.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid.,p. 123, PP,p.45.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., p. 107, PP, p. 33.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., p. 125, PP, p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Cf.: J. Passmore, ‘Logical Positivism’, in Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 5, p. 56; J. Passmore, A Hundred Years of Philosophy, London: Duckworth, 1966, pp. 367–93; K.R. Popper, ‘Autobiography’, pp. 69–71. See in addition R. Haller, ‘New Light on the Vienna Circle’, pp. 25 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Cf. K.R. Popper, ‘Autobiography’, pp. 69–70.

    Google Scholar 

  33. O. Neurath, ‘Physikalismus’, Scientia, 50 (1931), now also in GpmS, pp. 417–8, English trans. PP, p. 52;

    Google Scholar 

  34. cf. O. Neurath, ‘Soziologie im Physikalismus’, Erkenntnis, 2 (1931), p. 394, English trans. PP, p. 59.

    Google Scholar 

  35. O. Neurath, ‘Wege der wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung’, [1930/31], p. 116, PP, p. 40

    Google Scholar 

  36. O. Neurath, Lebensgestaltung und Klassenkampf, Berlin: E. Laub, 1928, now in GpmS, pp. 287–93, English trans. ES, pp. 290–8

    Google Scholar 

  37. O. Neurath, ‘Soziologie im PhysikaHsmus’, [193lf], p. 393 (“alle sinnvollen Aussagen sind in den Wissenschaften enthalten”), PP, p. 58.

    Google Scholar 

  38. O. Neurath, ‘Physikalismus’, [1931d], GpmS, p. 418, PP, p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  41. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’’, Erkenntnis, 4 (1934), p. 354, English trans. PP, p. 107

    Google Scholar 

  42. O. Neurath, ‘Pseudo’, [1935a], pp. 354,364, English trans. PP, pp. 122, 130.

    Google Scholar 

  43. O. Neurath, ‘Physikalismus’, [1931d], GpmS, p. 418, PP, p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  44. O. Neurath, ‘Soziologie im Physikalismus’ [1931f], p. 397, PP, p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid., p. 396 (“man kann sich nicht über die Sprache als Ganzes sozusagen von einem ‘noch-nicht-sprachlichen’ Standpunkt aus äußern”), PP, pp. 60–1

    Google Scholar 

  46. O. Neurath, ‘Physikalismus.’ [1931d], GpmS, p. 418, PP, p. 52.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Ibid., GpmS, p. 419, PP, p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid., GpmS, p. 418 (“So werden immer Aussagen mit Aussagen verglichen, nicht etwa mit einer ‘Wirklichkeit’, mit ‘Dingen’ wie es bisher auch der Wiener Kreis tat”), PP, p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  49. O. Neurath, Einheitswissenschaft und Psychologie, Wien: Gerold & Co, 1933, now in GpmS, p.594.

    Google Scholar 

  50. O. Neurath, ‘Soziologie im Physikalismus’, [193lf], p. 397 (“Aussagen [sind] Ausgangspunkt und Ende der Wissenschaft”), PP, p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  51. O. Neurath, ‘Physikalismus’, [193ld], GpmS, p. 419, PP, p. 53

    Google Scholar 

  52. O. Neurath, ‘Soziologie im Physikalismus’, [193lf], p. 403, PP, p. 66.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ibid., loc. cit. (“Die hier aufgestellte Definition von ‘richtig’ und ‘unrichtig’ entfernt sich von der im ‘Wiener Kreis’ üblichen, die aus ‘Bedeutung’ und ‘Verifikation’ rekurriert”).

    Google Scholar 

  55. Cf.: O. Neurath, ‘Pseudo’, [1935a], pp. 362–3, PP, p. 129

    Google Scholar 

  56. O. Neurath, ‘Universal Jargon and Terminology’, in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 41, 1941, pp. 144–8, now in PP, pp. 226–9 (“Our proposals lead to history and sociology of the sciences and to a stressing of the social implications of language”, ibid., p. 229)

    Google Scholar 

  57. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’’, [1934], p. 356 (“Die Termini ‘Satz’, ‘Sprache’ usw. müssen historisch-soziologisch definiert werden”), PP, p. 108.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Cf. R. Carnap, ‘Intellectual Autobiography’, pp. 60–2. At the First International Congress for the Unity of Science, organised by Neurath in Paris (1935), Carnap took sides with Tarski’s against Neurath, who together with Årne Naess had criticized Tarski’s paper ‘Grundlegung der wissenschaftlichen Semantik’ (see Actes du Congrés International de Philosophie Scientifique, Paris, 1935, Actualités Scientifiques et Industrielles, no. 290, Paris: Hermann & Cie Editeurs, 1936, III, pp. 1–8; cf.: R. Carnap, ‘Wahrheit und Bewährung’, ibid., IV, pp. 18–23; R. Carnap, ‘Intellectual Autobiography’, p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Cf.: C.G. Hempel, ‘Studies in the Logic of Confirmation’, Mind, 54 (1945), p. 115

    Google Scholar 

  60. C.G. Hempel, ‘Le problème de la vérité’, Theoria, 3 (1937), pp. 225–8.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Cf. K.R. Popper, ‘Autobiography’, pp. 70, 78, 114; K.R. Popper, ‘Truth, Rationality, and the Growth of Scientific Knowledge’, in Conjectures and Refutations, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969, pp. 223–7. Popper’s interpretation of Tarski’s semantic theory of truth has been criticized by S. Haack, in Philosophy of Logics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978; see also T.S. Kuhn, ‘Reflections on My Critics’, in I. Lakatos, A. Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, p. 265.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Cf. O. Neurath, ‘Erster Internationaler Kongreß für Einheit der Wissenschaft in Paris 1935’, Erkenntnis, 5 (1935), pp. 395–402; A. Tarski, ‘The Semantic Conception of Truth’, in H. Feigl, W. Sellars (eds.), Readings in Philosophical Analysis, p. 80, note 3 (with reference to Neurath’s criticism). Many others after Neurath have criticized Tarski’s formalization of the semantic concept of truth: for instance F. Gonseth, H. Reichenbach, F. Kaufmann, M. Black, G.C. Field and, more recently

    Google Scholar 

  63. , H. Putnam, in Meaning and the Moral Sciences, Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978, pp.vii, 1–6, 9–17, 28–32.

    Google Scholar 

  64. O. Neurath, ‘Einzelwissenschaften, EinheitsWissenschaft, Pseudorationalismus’, in Actes du Congrès International de Philosophie Scientifique, Sorbonne, Paris 1935, I, Actualités Scientifiques et Industrielles, no. 388, Paris 1936, now in GpmS, pp. 706–7, English trans. PP, pp. 135–6

    Google Scholar 

  65. O. Neurath, ‘Zu den Vortragen von Black, Kokoszynska, Williams’, Erkenntnis, 7 (1937–38) (“[...] ehe noch die Frage entschieden ist, innerhalb welcher Kalküle der ‘Wahrheitsbegriff, wie ihn Tarski und andere jetzt vertreten, wertfoll ist, und ob er vielleicht gewisse absolutistische Existenzbehauptungen in verschleierter Form nahelegt’, ibid., p. 374), English trans. PP, p. 208;

    Google Scholar 

  66. O. Neurath, ‘Physikalismus und Erkenntnisforschung’, I, Theoria, 2 (1936), now in GpmS, pp. 753–4, English trans. PP, p. 163

    Google Scholar 

  67. O. Neurath, Foundations, [1944a], pp. 12–3.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Ibid., loc. cit. This aspect has been particularly emphasised by F. Kaufmann; see Carnap’s reply to Kaufmann’s criticism in Introduction to Semantics, Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press, 1942; cf. H. Putnam, Meaning and the Moral Sciences, pp. 2–3.

    Google Scholar 

  69. O. Neurath, ‘Physikalismus und Erkenntnisforschung’, [1936f] I, GpmS, p. 754, PP, p. 163.

    Google Scholar 

  70. O. Neurath, Foundations, [1944a], pp. 12–3,48, note 19.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Cf. L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus logico-philosophicus, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1961, 4.25, 4.26, 4.3.

    Google Scholar 

  72. See C.G. Hempel, ‘Schlick und Neurath: Fundierung versus Kohärenz in der wissenschfatlichen Erkenntnis’. See in addition: H. Rutte, ‘Neurath kontra Schlick. Zur Wahrheitsdiskussion im Wiener Kreis’, in Wittgenstein, der Wiener Kreis und der Kritische Rationalismus, pp. 248–51; T. Oberdan, ‘Neurath’s Complaint’, ibid., pp. 241–3; H. Rutte, Wahrheit und Basis empirischer Erkenntnis, Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Cf. M. Schlick, ‘Positivismus und Realismus’, Erkenntnis, 3 (1932–33), pp. 7, 29.

    Google Scholar 

  74. In Erkenntnis, 2 (1931), pp. 432–65; ibid., 3 (1932–33), pp. 107–42.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Cf. B. Russell, Our Knowledge of the External World, London: George Allen & Unwin, 1926. W.V.O. Quine has pointed out the relationship between the two books

    Google Scholar 

  76. cf.: W.V.O. Quine, ‘Russell’s Ontological Development’, Journal of Philosophy, 63 (1966), pp. 107–42; W.V.O. Quine, Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, p. 74. For a recent reinterpretation of Carnap’s Aufbau, with references to Neurath and Quine’s ontological relativism

    Google Scholar 

  77. see A. Coffa, ‘Idealism and the Aufbau’, in N. Rescher (ed.), The Heritage of Logical Positivism, Lanham (Md.): University Press of America, 1985, pp. 133–55.

    Google Scholar 

  78. R. Carnap, Der logische Aufbau der Welt, Berlin and Schlachtensee: Weltkreis Verlag, 1928, p. 105, English trans. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  79. R. Carnap, ‘Die physikalische Sprache als Universalsprache der Wissenschaft’, Erkenntnis, 2 (1931), pp. 437, 438.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Ibid., p. 438.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Cf. K.R. Popper, Logik der Forschung, pp. 51–55, English trans, pp. 93–7. See also G. Andersson, ‘How to Accept Fallible Test Statements? Popper’s Criticist Solution’, in G. Andersson (ed.), Rationality in Science and Politics, Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel, 1985, pp. 47–65.

    Google Scholar 

  82. O. Neurath, ‘Protokollsätze’, Erkenntnis, 3 (1932–33), p. 206 (“Es gibt kein Mittel, um endgültig gesicherte saubere Protokollsätze zum Ausgangspunkt der Wissenschaften zu machen. Es gibt keine tabula rasa”), English trans. PP, p. 92.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Cf. R. Carnap, ‘Intellectual Autobiography’, p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Cf.: W.V.O. Quine, ‘Identity, Ostension, and Hypostasis’, now in W.V.O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View, p. 79 (“The philosopher’s task was well compared by Neurath to that of a mariner who must rebuild his ship on the open sea”); W.V.O. Quine, The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, p. 210 (“As Neurath has said, we are in the position of a mariner who must rebuild his ship plank by plank while continuing to stay afloat on the open sea”), pp. 212–3 (“Epistemologists have wanted to posit a realm of sense data, [...] for fear of circularity [...]. But if with Neurath we accept this circularity, simply recognizing that the science of science is a science, then we dispose of the epistemological motive for assuming a realm of sense data”); W.V.O. Quine, Word and Object, p. 3 (“Neurath has likened science to a boat which, if we are to rebuild it, we must rebuild plank by plank while staying afloat in it. The philosopher and the scientist are in the same boat.”), pp. 123–4 (“The interlocked conceptual scheme of physical objects, identity and divided reference is part of the ship which, in Neurath’s figure, we cannot remodel save as we stay afloat on it. The ontology of abstract objects is part of the ship too, if only a less fundamental part. The ship may owe its structure partly to blundering predecessors who missed scuttling it only by fools’ luck. But we are not in a position to jettison any part of it, except as we have substitute devices ready to hand that will serve the same essential purposes”), p. 210; W.V.O. Quine, Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, pp. 83–4 (“This interplay is reminiscent again of the old threat of circularity, but it is all right now that we have stopped dreaming of deducing science from sense data. We are after an understanding of science as an institution or process in the world, and we do not intend that understanding to be any better than the science which is its object. This attitude is indeed one that Neurath was already urging in Vienna Circle days, with his parable of the mariner who has to rebuild his boat while staying afloat in it”), pp. 126–7 (“I see philosophy and science as in the same boat — a boat which, to revert to Neurath’s figure as I so often do, we can rebuild only at sea while staying afloat in it. There is no external vantage point, no first philosophy”).

    Google Scholar 

  85. O. Neurath, ‘Protokollsätze’, [1932/33], p. 206 (“Wie Schiffer sind wir, die ihr Schiff auf offener See umbauen müssen, ohne es jemals in einem Dock zerlegen und aus besten Bestandteilen neu errichten zu können”), PP, p. 92.

    Google Scholar 

  86. O. Neurath, ‘Protokollsätze’, [1932/33], p. 208, PP, p. 94.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Ibid., loc. cit. This thesis has been developed by I. Lakatos with reference to fundamental concepts of mathematics in Proofs and Refutations. The Logic of Mathematical Discovery, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  88. O. Neurath, ‘Protokollsätze’, [1932/33], pp. 209–10, PP, pp. 95–6. Cf. R. Haller, ‘Das Neurath-Prinzip. Grundlagen und Folgerungen’, passim. C.G. Hempel, in ‘Schlick und Neurath: Fundierung versus Kohärenz in der wissenschaftlichen Erkenntnis’, pp. 8–9, emphasises the importance of this ‘principle’ and recognizes its historical primacy with respect to Carnap and Popper’s similar theses.

    Google Scholar 

  89. O. Neurath, ‘Protokollsätze’, [1932/33], p. 210, PP, p. 95.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  91. According to J. Passmore “Reichenbach once wrote of Carnap that ‘his theory may be regarded, after a fashion, as a modern fulfilment of Descartes’ quest for an absolutely certain basis of science’. In so far as that was his ambition, most logical positivists would now admit, he certainly failed to fulfil it” (A Hundred Years of Philosophy, p. 393).

    Google Scholar 

  92. O. Neurath, ‘Protokollsätze’, [1932/33], pp. 211–2, PP, pp. 96–7. “If someone makes predictions and wants to check them himself, he must count on changes in the system of his senses, he must use clocks and rulers; in short the man who supposedly is in isolation already makes use of the ‘intersensual’ and ‘intersubjective’ language. The forecaster of yesterday and the controller of today are, so to speak, two persons” (O. Neurath, ‘Physikalismus’, [1931d], GpmS, p. 420, PP, p. 55).

    Google Scholar 

  93. O. Neurath, ‘Protokollsätze’, [1932/33], pp. 211–2, 213, PP, pp. 96–7, 98; cf. E. Stiffler, ‘The Vienna Circle and the Pragmatic Conception of Scientific Protocols’, in Wittgenstein, der Wiener Kreis und der Kritische Rationalismus, pp. 252–5.

    Google Scholar 

  94. O. Neurath, ‘Protokollsätze’, [1932/33], pp. 206–8, 210–1, PP, pp. 93–4, 95–6.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Ibid., p. 210, PP, p. 96.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Ibid., pp. 210–2, PP, pp. 96–7.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Ibid., p. 210, PP, p. 96.

    Google Scholar 

  99. O. Neurath, ‘Physikalismus’, [1931d], GpmS, p. 418, PP, p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Cf. W.V.O. Quine, ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’, Philosphical Review, 60 (1951), pp. 20–43, now in W.V.O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View, pp. 20–46. And yet Quine seems not to recognise the importance of Neurath’s contribution on this subject: cf. W.V.O. Quine, Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, p. 85.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Cf.: R. Carnap, ‘Die neue und die alte Logik’, Erkenntnis, 1 (1930–31), pp. 12–26

    Google Scholar 

  102. R. Carnap, ‘Überwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache’, ibid., 2 (1931), pp. 219–41. On the relationship between Wittgenstein’s philosophy and Neurath’s thought see F. Wallner, ‘Wittgenstein und Neurath. Vergleich von Intentionen und Denkstil’, in Schlick und Neurath. Ein Symposion, ed. by R. Haller, pp. 419–23.

    Google Scholar 

  103. O. Neurath, Le développement du Cercle de Vienne et l’avenir de l’empirisme logique, Actualités Scientifiques et Industrielles, no. 290, Paris: Hermann & Cie Editeurs, 1936, pp. 10–2

    Google Scholar 

  104. O. Neurath, Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener Kreis, [1929], GpmS, pp. 305–8, ES, pp. 305–10.

    Google Scholar 

  105. R. Camap, ‘Die neue und die alte Logik’, pp. 21–3; see the discussion between Carnap and Quine in the Fifties: W.V.O. Quine, ‘Carnap and Logical Truth’, in P. A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, pp. 385–406; R. Carnap, ‘W.V.O. Quine on Logical Truth’, ibid., pp. 915–22. See also W.V.O. Quine, ‘On Carnap’s Views on Ontology’, Philosophical Studies, 2 (1951), n. 5, pp. 65–72.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Cf. K.R. Popper, ‘The Demarcation between Science and Metaphysics’, in P.A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, pp. 183–226, and Carnap’s reply ‘K.R. Popper and the Demarcation between Science and Metaphysics’, ibid., pp. 877–81.

    Google Scholar 

  107. R. Carnap, ‘Die neue und die alte Logik’, pp. 15, 23–6; R. Carnap, ‘Überwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache’, pp. 221–33; R. Carnap, ‘Die physikalische Sprache als Universalsprache der Wissenschaft’, pp. 432–3.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Cf. W.V.O. Quine, ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’; see also M.G. White, ‘The Analytic and the Synthetic: An Untenable Dualism’, in L. Linsky (ed.), Semantics and the Philosophy of Language, Urbana: The University of Illinois Press, 1952, pp. 272–86.

    Google Scholar 

  109. O. Neurath, Anti-Spengler, [1921], GpmS, p. 192, ES, p. 208

    Google Scholar 

  110. O. Neurath, ‘Protokollsätze’, [1932/33], p. 205, PP, pp. 91–2

    Google Scholar 

  111. O. Neurath, Einheitswissenschaft und Psychologie, [1933], GpmS, p. 506.

    Google Scholar 

  112. O. Neurath, Le développement du Cercle de Vienne et l’avenir de l’empirisme logique, [1936], pp. 56–7.

    Google Scholar 

  113. O. Neurath, ‘Protokollsätze’, [1932/33], p. 204, PP, p. 91.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Ibid., p. 205, PP, p. 91.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Cf. A. Gargani, Introduzione a Wittgenstein, Roma and Bari: Laterza, 1973, pp. 79–91.

    Google Scholar 

  117. O. Neurath, ‘Protokollsätze’, [1932/33], p. 206 (“Wird die Unpräzision an einer Stelle verringert, kann sie wohl gar an anderer Stelle verstärkt wieder auftreten”), PP, pp. 92 f.

    Google Scholar 

  118. O. Neurath, ‘L’encyclopédie comme ‘modèle’, Revue de Synthèse, 12 (1936), n. 2, p. 188, English trans. PP, p. 146

    Google Scholar 

  119. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’’, [1934], pp. 350–1, PP, pp. 103–4.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Ibid., p. 351, PP, p. 104

    Google Scholar 

  121. O. Neurath, ‘L’encyclopédie comme ‘modèle’, [1936d], pp. 188–9, PP, pp. 146–7.

    Google Scholar 

  122. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’’, [1934], p. 351, PP, p. 104.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Neurath quotes Karl Menger’s essay ‘Die neue Logik’, in K. Menger, Krise und Neuaufbau in den exacten Wissenschaften, Leipzig und Wien: Deutike, 1933, pp. 107, 119.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Cf.: A. Gargani, Introduzione a Wittgenstein, pp. 44–7; R. Haller, ‘Rede zur Eröffnung des Schlick-Neurath-Symposion 1982’, in R. Haller (ed.), Schlick und Neurath. Ein Symposion, p. xx.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Neurath quotes L.E.J. Brouwer’s essay Mathematik, Wissenschaft und Sprache, Wien, Wiener Gastvorträge 1928, also in Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 36 (1929), pp. 153–264. For a criticism of Carnap, Hempel and Reichenbach’s philosophy of mathematics see S.F. Barker, ‘Logical Positivism and the Philosophy of Mathematics’, in P. Achinstein and S.F. Barker (eds.), The Legacy of Logical Positivism, pp. 229–57.

    Google Scholar 

  126. Popper and Agassi critically emphasize this aspect of Carnap’s intellect; see: K.R. Popper, ‘The Demarcation between Science and Metaphysics’, in P.A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, p. 184; J. Agassi, Review of J. Hintikka (ed.), The Secret of Carnap: Rudolf Carnap, Logical Empiricist, Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel, 1975, in Philosophia, 10 (1981), pp. 57–63.

    Google Scholar 

  127. R. Carnap, ‘Über Protokollsätze’, Erkenntnis, 3 (1932–33), pp. 215–8.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Ibid., p. 224.

    Google Scholar 

  129. In ‘Über Protokollsätze’ Carnap refers to Popper’s opinions and theses, which he knew thanks to some private conversations he had with Popper during common holidays in the Tyrol, and also through his knowledge of Popper’s unpublished typescript Die beiden Grundprobleme der Erkenntnistheorie; cf. K.R. Popper, ‘Autobiography’, pp. 65–7.

    Google Scholar 

  130. R. Carnap, ‘Über Protokollsätze’, p. 228.

    Google Scholar 

  131. Ibid., pp. 223–4. Cf.: K.R. Popper, ‘Replies to My Critics’, in P.A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Karl Popper, p. 969; K.R. Popper, ‘Autobiography’, p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Ibid., pp. 969–70; K.R. Popper, ‘The Demarcation between Science and Metaphysics’, p. 211, note 60.

    Google Scholar 

  133. R. Carnap, ‘Robert S. Cohen on the Relationship between Dialectical Materialism and Empiricism’, in P.A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, p. 864.

    Google Scholar 

  134. For Carnap’s implicit epistemological realism see F. Barone, Il neopositivismo logico, pp. 217–23.

    Google Scholar 

  135. Cf. Erkenntnis, i (1934), pp. 79–99.

    Google Scholar 

  136. Ibid., pp. 84 ff. On the relationship between Schlick and Neurath see: K. Lehrer, ‘Schlick and Neurath: Meaning and Truth’, in R. Haller (ed.), Schlick und Neurath, Ein Symposion, pp. 49–61; R. Hilpinen, ‘Schlick on the Foundation of Knowledge’, ibid., pp. 63–78; W. Leinfellner, ‘Schlicks kognitive Erkenntnistheorie als Wissenschaftstheorie’, ibid., pp. 103–27; H. Lauener, ‘Neurath’s Protocol Sentences and Schlick’s ‘Konstatierungen’ versus Quine’s Observation Sentences’, ibid., pp. 129–48; H. Tennessen, ‘Qualms about Otto Neurath’s Cabby Language’, ibid., pp. 385–98; J. Dvorak, ‘Wahrscheinlichkeit, Logik und Empirie: Neurath, Schlick, und Zilsel’, ibid., pp. 465–70; D. Davidson, ‘Empirical Content’, ibid., pp. 471–89; O. Hänfling, Logical Positivism, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1981, pp. 82–6.

    Google Scholar 

  137. Cf. Erkenntnis, 4 (1934), pp. 91–9.

    Google Scholar 

  138. Ibid., pp. 86–7.

    Google Scholar 

  139. Cf.: C.G. Hempel, ‘On the Logical Positivists’ Theory of Truth’, Analysis, 2 (1935), pp. 49–59;

    Google Scholar 

  140. C.G. Hempel, ‘Some Remarks on ‘Facts’ and Propositions’, ibid., pp. 93–6

    Google Scholar 

  141. C.G. Hempel, ‘Some Remarks on Empiricism’, ibid., 3 (1936), pp. 30–40

    Google Scholar 

  142. see also: B. Juhos, ‘Kritische Bemerkungen zur Wissenschaftstheorie des Physikalismus’, Erkenntnis, 4 (1934), pp. 397–418

    Google Scholar 

  143. T. Vogel, ‘Bemerkungen zur Aussagentheorie des Radikalen Physikalismus’, ibid., pp. 160–4. In his recent essay, ‘Schlick und Neurath: Fundierung versus Kohärenz in der wissenschaftlichen Erkenntnis’, p. 17, Hempel recognises that Neurath’s thesis cannot be understood as ‘eine reine Kohärenzauffassung’.

    Google Scholar 

  144. Cf.: A.J. Ayer, ‘Verification and Experience’, in A.J. Ayer (ed.), Logical Positivism, Glencoe (Ill): The Free Press, 1959

    Google Scholar 

  145. A.J. Ayer, The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge, London: Macmillan, 1940.

    Google Scholar 

  146. Cf. B. Russell, An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, London: Allen & Unwin, 1950.

    Google Scholar 

  147. K.R. Popper, Logik der Forschung, pp. 54–5, English trans, pp. 95–7.

    Google Scholar 

  148. Cf. V. Kraft, ‘Popper and the Vienna Circle’, in P.A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Karl Popper, pp. 185–201, particularly p. 194.

    Google Scholar 

  149. Cf. I. Scheffler, Science and Subjectivity, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1967, pp. 91–123.

    Google Scholar 

  150. Cf. J. Passmore, A Hundred Years of Philosophy, p. 376 (“Thus Neurath’s attack on metaphysics leads him back to that coherence theory of truth already familiar to us in the writings of the Absolute Idealists — not surprisingly, since for them, too, ‘transcendence’ was the great enemy”).

    Google Scholar 

  151. Cf. I. Lakatos, ‘Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes’, pp. 113–4.

    Google Scholar 

  152. In his reply to R.S. Cohen’s criticism (‘Robert S. Cohen on the Relationship between Dialectical Materialism and Empiricism’) Carnap maintains that Neurath’s formulation of the theory of non-transcendability of linguistic propositions was ‘misleading’, but it did not imply any ‘coherence theory’ of truth. (It is, by the way, worth mentioning that, while defending Neurath from the charge of nominalism, Carnap seems to be inclined to attribute to him a sort of epistemological realism, precisely akin to his own implicit realism). According to Carnap Neurath’s formulations “were indeed repeatedly interpreted in this sense, not only by outsiders like Russell and Ayer, but also by Schlick. Neurath vehemently rejected this interpretation in the discussions of the Vienna Circle, and also in a remark in his report on the Paris Congress of 1935 (Erkenntnis, 5, 1936, p. 400). At any rate, there cannot be any doubt that Neurath never held this conception” (P.A. Schilpp, ed., The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, p. 864). As to Neurath’s remark mentioned by Carnap, cf. O. Neurath, ‘Erster Internationaler Kongress für Einheit der Wissenschaft in Paris 1935’, [1935c], p. 400;

    Google Scholar 

  153. see also O. Neurath, Foundations, [1944a], p. 47, note 16.

    Google Scholar 

  154. A.J. Ayer, ‘Verification and Experience’, pp. 230–1.

    Google Scholar 

  155. Ibid., p. 231.

    Google Scholar 

  156. B. Russell, An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, p. 148.

    Google Scholar 

  157. Ibid., pp. 148–9.

    Google Scholar 

  158. According to Lakatos Neurath’s reply (in ‘Pseudorationalismus der Falsifikation’) to Popper’s criticism shows that Neurath “never grasped Popper’s simple argument” (cf. I. Lakatos, ‘Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes’, p. 114).

    Google Scholar 

  159. In Einheitswissenschaft und Psychologie, GpmS, p. 591, Neurath openly maintains the identity between ‘Physikalismus’ and ‘räumlichzeitliche Terminologie’.

    Google Scholar 

  160. Cf. F. Barone, Il neopositivismo logico, pp. 310–1, 314; G. Statera, Logica, linguaggio e sociologia. Studio su Otto Neurath e il neopositivismo, pp. 48–9.

    Google Scholar 

  161. Cf. L. Fleck, Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache. Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv, Basel: Benno Schwabe, 1935

    Google Scholar 

  162. see also: T.S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970, p. x

    Google Scholar 

  163. T.S. Kuhn, ‘Foreword’ to L. Fleck, Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1979, pp. vii–xi; L. Schäfer and T. Schnelle, ‘Einleitung’ to L. Fleck, Erfahrung und Tatsache, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp Verlag, p. 347; R.S. Cohen and T. Schnelle (eds.), Cognition and Fact. Materials on Ludwik Fleck.

    Google Scholar 

  164. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’’, [1934], p. 347, PP, p. 101.

    Google Scholar 

  165. Ibid., p. 348, PP, pp. 101–2

    Google Scholar 

  166. O. Neurath, ‘Physikalismus’, [1931d], GpmS, pp. 418–9, PP, pp. 52–4

    Google Scholar 

  167. O. Neurath, ‘Einheit der Wissenschaft als Aufgabe’, Erkenntnis, 5 (1935), p. 17, English trans. PP, p. 116.

    Google Scholar 

  168. Cf.: B. Russell, An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, p. 139; O. Neurath, ‘Universal Jargon and Terminology’, [1941], pp. 146–8, PP, pp. 228–9.

    Google Scholar 

  169. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’’, [1934], pp. 351, 359, PP, p. 104, 110.

    Google Scholar 

  170. Ibid., p. 348, PP, p. 102.

    Google Scholar 

  171. Ibid., p. 352 (“Unter den miteinender konkurrierenden Satzsystemen wählen wir ein aus. Dies so ausgewählte Satzsystem ist aber nicht logisch ausgezeichnet”), PP, p. 105; O. Neurath, ‘Einheit der Wissenschaft als Aufgabe’, [1935], p. 20 (“Aber solche Eindeutigkeit des Entschlusses und der Tat ist nicht logisches Ergebnis aus irgendwelchen Prämissen, die zu einer einzigen Prognose über den Erfolg der Tat führen”), PP, p. 118.

    Google Scholar 

  172. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’’, [1934], p. 352, PP, p. 105.

    Google Scholar 

  173. O. Neurath, Le développement du Cercle de Vienne et l’avenir de l’empirisme logique, [1936], p. 57.

    Google Scholar 

  174. Cf.: O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkilche Welt’’, [1934], p. 353 (“Aber ‘unserer Standpunkt’ ist dennoch nur historisch bestimmt”), PP, p. 106;

    Google Scholar 

  175. ibid., p. 356 (“Die Termini ‘Satz’, ‘Sprache’ usw. müssen historisch-soziologisch definiert werden”), PP, p. 108

    Google Scholar 

  176. O. Neurath, ‘Unified Science and Its Encyclopedia’, Philosophy of Science, 4 (1973), p. 276, now also in PP, p. 181.

    Google Scholar 

  177. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  178. Cf. V. Kraft, ‘Popper and the Vienna Circle’, p. 194.

    Google Scholar 

  179. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’’, [1934], p. 352, PP, p. 105

    Google Scholar 

  180. O. Neurath, ‘Einheit der Wissenschaft als Aufgabe’, [1935], p. 19, PP, p. 117.

    Google Scholar 

  181. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’’, [1934], p. 352, PP, p. 105

    Google Scholar 

  182. O. Neurath, ‘Einheit der Wissenschaft als Aufgabe’, [1935], p. 20, PP, pp. 117–8.

    Google Scholar 

  183. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’’, [1934], p. 353, PP, p. 106

    Google Scholar 

  184. O. Neurath, ‘Einheit der Wissenschaft als Aufgabe’, [1935], pp. 18–9, PP, pp. 116–7.

    Google Scholar 

  185. Ibid., p. 19, PP, p. 117. The analogy between these elements of sociology of science and some central theses of Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions may be found surprising; cf. R. Hegselmann, ‘Otto Neurath. Empiristischer Aufklärer und Sozialreformer’, pp. 40–1.

    Google Scholar 

  186. O. Neurath, ‘Einheit der Wissenschaft als Aufgabe’, [1935], p. 19, PP, p. 117.

    Google Scholar 

  187. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  188. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt’’, [1934], p. 352, PP, p. 105.

    Google Scholar 

  189. O. Neurath, ‘Einheit der Wissenschaft als Aufgabe’, [1935], pp. 20, 21, 19, PP, pp. 117–8, 119, 117.

    Google Scholar 

  190. Ibid., p. 17, PP, p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  191. Ibid., p. 21, PP, p. 119.

    Google Scholar 

  192. O. Neurath, ‘Unified Science and Its Encyclopedia’, [1937a], p. 276, PP, pp. 180–1.

    Google Scholar 

  193. O. Neurath, Empirische Soziologie, [1931e], GpmS, p. 426, ES, p. 319.

    Google Scholar 

  194. O. Neurath, Anti-Spengler, [1921], GpmS, p. 140, ES, p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  195. O. Neurath, ‘Pseudo’, [1935a], p. 360, PP, p. 127.

    Google Scholar 

  196. O. Neurath, Empirische Soziologie, [1931e], GpmS, p. 517, ES, p. 407.

    Google Scholar 

  197. O. Neurath, ‘Einheit der Wissenschaft als Aufgabe’, [1935], p. 20, PP, p. 118.

    Google Scholar 

  198. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  199. O. Neurath, ‘Universal Jargon and Terminology’, [1941], p. 145, PP, p. 227.

    Google Scholar 

  200. Ibid., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  201. O. Neurath, ‘The Danger of a Careless Terminology’, The New Era, 22 (1941), no. 7, p. 148.

    Google Scholar 

  202. O. Neurath, ‘Universal Jargon and Terminology’, [1941], p. 147, PP, pp. 228–9.

    Google Scholar 

  203. O. Neurath, ‘Radikaler Physikalismus und Wirkliche Welt’, [1934], pp. 356–7 (“So reduziert sich für uns das Streben nach Wirklichkeitserkenntnis auf das Streben, die Sätze der Wissenschaft in Übereinstimmung zu bringen mit möglichst vielen Protokollaussagen. Das ist aber sehr viel: hierin ist der Empirismus begründet”), PP, p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Zolo, D. (1989). Linguistic Reflexivity and ‘Pseudorationalism’. In: Reflexive Epistemology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 118. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2415-4_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2415-4_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7588-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2415-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics