Skip to main content

Some Aspects of Empiricism and Empirical Knowledge

  • Chapter
  • 161 Accesses

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 43))

Abstract

Though it might seem unusual to postpone a discussion of empiricism until after a discussion of Kant, there is a simple reason for doing so. Hegel himself addresses a, if not the, fundamental presupposition of Modern empiricism in the first chapter of the Phenomenology, “Sense-Certainty”: the thesis that we are capable of non-conceptual cognitive apprehension of objects.1 Section II of this chapter discusses this doctrine along with its two main purposes, indicates some of the twentieth-century adherents of these doctrines, and defers thorough analysis of the topic to an analysis of the “Sense-Certainty” chapter—a project lying beyond the bounds of the present study. Despite this deferral, several reflexive problems for empiricism are implied by the questions (discussed above in Chapter One) Hegel raises in the Introduction to the Phenomenology. The gist of the issue is: Can Empiricism be known to be true on empiricist grounds? This issue is discussed in section III of this chapter after considering several formulations of principles of empiricism. Section IV expounds Carnap’s empiricism, for he offers a direct solution (or dissolution) of the problems posed in sections II and III by adopting a liberalized notion of observation and a syntactical construal of the principle of empiricism, a construal rendering that principle non-cognitive and so avoiding the reflexive challenge posed by Hegel. I argue in section V that Carnap’s program fails to replace epistemology with the logic of science and fails to undercut the issue of epistemological realism and so neither handles nor avoids the problems Hegel addresses.2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes to Chapter Four

  1. Russell, ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description’ (in: Mysticism and Logic [London: George Allen and Unwin, 1959], pp. 202–224). Camap’s epistemological program in the Aufbau (op. cit.) presupposed ‘knowledge by acquaintance’ for the recognition of “part similarity” and hence for the occurrence of memory traces of part similarity. See also §§67–69, where it is presupposed that pair-lists of elementary experiences are given. Carnap renounced this doctrine by 1932 (cf. ‘Über Protokolsätze’ [Erkenntnis 3 |1931–32}], pp. 215–228; hereafter cited as ÜP), and says so while lecturing in London (‘Report of Lectures on Philosophy and Logical Syntax’ [Analysis 2 No. 3 |1934}, pp. 42–48; hereafter cited as RLPLS], p. 47). On Schlick, see ‘The Foundation of Knowledge’ (Erkenntnis 4 |1934}, hereafter cited as FK; rpt. in: A. J. Ayer, ed., Logical Positivism [New York: Free Press, 1959; hereafter cited as “Ayer, ed.”], pp. 209–227), pp. 209–210, and on Ayer see ‘Verification and Experience’ (Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 37 [1936–1937]; rpt. in Ayer, ed., pp. 228–243), p. 299.

    Google Scholar 

  2. C. D. Broad, Examination of McTaggart’s Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1933, 1938). Broad’s account is typical of empiricist theories of concept acquisition.

    Google Scholar 

  3. C. I. Lewis, An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation (LaSalle, Il.: Open Court, 1946), ch. 8, ‘Terminating Judgments and Objective Beliefs.’ Were Lewis not committed to knowledge of “phenomena” by acquaintance, such knowledge would be useless for assessing non-terminating judgments in the way he describes.

    Google Scholar 

  4. For a thorough discussion and refutation of Broad’s theory of concept acquisition, see Robert Turnbull, ‘Empirical and A Priori Elements in Broad’s Theory of Knowledge’ (The Philosophy of C.D. Broad, P. A. Schilpp, ed. [The Library of Living Philosophers; New York: Tudor, 1959], pp. 197–231). A position very like Russell’s “knowledge by acquaintance” was adopted by F. H. Jacobi, with the difference that Jacobi rejected discursivity altogether. Hegel refuted Jacobi by arguing that knowledge is discursive, i.e., conceptual. Hence his criticism of Jacobi bears on Russell as well. I have reconstructed and analyzed Hegel’s critique of Jacobi in ‘Hegel’s Attitude Toward Jacobi in the “Third Attitude of Thought Toward Objectivity”’ (op. cit.). Wilfred Sellars thoroughly analyzes the sources of and the confusions in the notion of the non-conceptual apprehension of objects in ‘Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind’ (Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of Science Vol. 1; rpt. in: Science, Perception, and Reality [London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963], pp. 127–196).

    Google Scholar 

  5. See Carnap, ‘The Old and the New Logic’ (Erkenntnis 1 [1930–31], rpt. in Ayer, ed., pp. 133–146; hereafter cited as “ONL”), p. 139–140.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Carnap, The Unity of Science (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1931; hereafter cited as “US”), p. 23; cf. Hempel, LPTT p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  7. T&M p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  8. ESO pp. 214, 218.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid., pp. 207, 214, 215 note 5.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See §VG below, pp. 64–66.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Logical Syntax of Language, A. Smeaton, tr. (Paterson, N.J.: Littlefield, Adams, 1959).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Carnap, RLPLS p. 42; T&M p. 429; Neurath, PS p. 200.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Carnap, US p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Carnap, US p. 23; ONL pp. 133, 143–144; T&M pp. 26, 429; Hempel, LPTT p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Carnap, US p. 38; ÜP p. 228; RLPLS pp. 45, 47; Hempel, LPTT p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Carnap, ONL pp. 133, 137; ÜP pp. 215, 228; T&M p. 26; Hempel, LPTT p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  17. T&M pp. 2, 420.

    Google Scholar 

  18. T&M pp. 2, 420; MCTC p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  19. MCTC pp. 40, 47.

    Google Scholar 

  20. MCTC pp. 59–60. Here Carnap claims to have used a similar approach in T&M regarding the observation language.

    Google Scholar 

  21. MCTC p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  22. T&M p. 454. 33. T&M p. 455. 34. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  23. T&M pp. 455–456.

    Google Scholar 

  24. T&M p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  25. T&M p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  26. T&M p. 436.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  28. T&M pp. 468–470; cf. US p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See below, pp. 55–60.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Carnap explicitly calls these “test sentences” in T&C p. 124. See also MCTC p. 65 and the texts cited in the next note.

    Google Scholar 

  31. T&M pp. 425, 434.

    Google Scholar 

  32. T&M p. 425. This is part of Black’s complaint against Waismann. See note 7 above.

    Google Scholar 

  33. T&M pp. 9–4. Cf. US pp. 78–79; ‘Psychology in Physicalist Language’ (Erkenntnis 3 [1932–33], rpt. in Ayer, ed., pp. 165–198; hereafter cited as “PPL”), p. 192.

    Google Scholar 

  34. T&M p. 440.

    Google Scholar 

  35. T&M pp. 444–448.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Cf. T&M pp. 440–441.

    Google Scholar 

  37. T&M pp. 434–441.

    Google Scholar 

  38. T&M pp. 33–34.

    Google Scholar 

  39. T&M p. 33.

    Google Scholar 

  40. T&M p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  41. T&M p. 456; cf. pp. 458–459.

    Google Scholar 

  42. T&M p. 456.

    Google Scholar 

  43. See note 58.

    Google Scholar 

  44. MCTC p. 38, T&M p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Schlick, FK pp. 213–216.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Hempel, LPTT pp. 49, 57 note 6. But see §VA below, pp. 56–57, and notes 72 and 119.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Hempel, LPTT pp. 56–57.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Hempel, LPTT p. 57, cf. p. 54; Neurath, RPWW pp. 352–354; SP p. 286. (This is a year before Tarski developed his semantic definition of truth.)

    Google Scholar 

  49. Hempel LPTT p. 57; cf. Carnap ‘Erwiderung auf die Aufsätze von Zisel und Dunker’ (Erkenntnis 3 [1932–33], pp. 177–188; hereafter cited as “Erw.”), p. 177.

    Google Scholar 

  50. ‘Empiricism and Physicalism’ (Analysis 2 No. 6 [1935], pp. 81–92).

    Google Scholar 

  51. Hempel, ‘Some Remarks on Empiricism’ (Analysis 3 No. 3 [1936], pp. 33–40; hereafter cited as SRE), p. 39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Ayer, ‘Verification and Experience’ (Proceedings of the Aristotelian Soceity 37 [1936–37], rpt. in Ayer, ed., pp. 228–243; hereafter cited as VE), p. 234.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Erw. p. 180.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ibid. p. 179.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ibid. pp. 178, 180.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Ibid. p. 179.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Carnap, MCTC p. 38; T&M pp. 14, 454.

    Google Scholar 

  58. PPL pp. 180–181; cf. PPL pp. 184, 185; Erw. p. 177; ÜP p. 221; Hempel, LPTT pp. 54, 57.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Neurath, RPWW p. 359; Carnap, US pp. 43–44; ÜP p. 221; PPL pp. 184, 185; Hempel, SRFP p. 94.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Erw. p. 182.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Carnap PPL pp. 181, 185.

    Google Scholar 

  62. This way of speaking comes from Frederick Dretske, Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Cambridge: M.I.T. Press, 1981). On this view, information is an objective feature of states of affairs, but for anyone to be informed by the receipt of information requires “decoding” that information. There being information does not, of itself, handle this problem.

    Google Scholar 

  63. See note 71.

    Google Scholar 

  64. See Frederick Dretske, ‘Machines and the Mental’ (Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 59 No. 1 [1985], pp. 23–34).

    Google Scholar 

  65. Hempel comes close to this contention (see p. 56 above).

    Google Scholar 

  66. T&C p. 124.

    Google Scholar 

  67. T&C p. 125. Cf. note 45 above.

    Google Scholar 

  68. W. Sellars, ‘Empiricism and Abstract Entities’ (The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, P. A. Schilpp, ed. [Library of Living Philosophers, 1963; hereafter cited as “Schilpp, ed.”], pp. 431–468), p. 435.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Cf. Hempel, LPTT pp. 50–51, 52, 54.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Cf. §IVB above, pp. 51–56.

    Google Scholar 

  71. The Scientific Image (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1980), p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Carnap, T&M p. 420.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Connected with this is another feature of Carnap’s view. He distinguishes sharply between reasons and motives. Reasons are given for assertions and can result in determining their truth value; motives are given in counseling a decision but have no truth value. This echoes the positivist view about the non-cognitive nature of ethics in that it renders motives non-cognitive. The main idea behind restricting the use of the term “reasons” in this way is the view that reasoning is a matter of deduction. Since deduction can only occur within a formally specified framework, reasons can only be given within such a framework. This aspect of Carnap’s view has been pointed out and critically discussed by Frederick Will in ‘Pragmatic Rationality’ (Philosophical Investigations 8 No. 2 [1985], pp. 120–142).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  74. ESO pp. 215 note 5, 221; cf. The Logical Syntax of Language (op. cit.), pp. 51–52.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Such, at least, is the general implication of Carnap’s discussion of mathematical realism (ESO pp. 218–219).

    Google Scholar 

  76. ‘Replies and Systematic Expositions’ (op. cit.; hereafter cited as “Replies”), p. 901.

    Google Scholar 

  77. T&C p. 126.

    Google Scholar 

  78. T&C p. 126. Cf. MCTC p. 51 on scientific “revolutions.”

    Google Scholar 

  79. MCTC p. 46.

    Google Scholar 

  80. ‘The “Political” Philosophy of Logical Empiricism’ (Philosophical Studies 2 No. 4 [1951], pp. 49–57), p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  81. The example is suggested by Paul Feyerabend’s discussion in ‘An Attempt at a Realistic Interpretation of Experience’ (Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society NS 58 [1957–58], pp. 143–170), though I elaborate and use it differently. In that essay Feyerabend attempts a very strong attack on positivism and especially on Carnap. However, his entire argument rests on what he calls the “Stability Thesis,” on the claim that the observation language always was, is, and will be applicable. Both Neurath and Carnap reject this thesis as early as 1932 (cf. PS, ÜP), and so Feyerabend’s objection to them fails. One of the principal issues to be decided is the syntactical form of observation sentences, and that form may be changed as needed. Two other deficiencies of Feyerabend’s attack may be briefly noted. First, he fails to see that although Carnap speaks of partially interpreting theoretical terms by syntactically coordinating them with observation terms, Carnap does not hold that theoretical language can be generated out of observation language. What Carnap’s “partial interpretation” amounts to is a specification of the empirical, that is, scientifically testable, meaning of a theoretical language. It is on the basis of this aspect of meaningfulness that a theory can be confirmed by observations (Erw. p. 177). (The other aspect of “meaning” is that formulated in the logical and nomological principles [the L- and P-rules] of a language, later explicated as “meaning postulates.”) Second, Feyerabend’s charge that positivism surreptitiously relies on a metaphysical ontology while denying the validity of metaphysics ignores Carnap’s efforts in ESO to distinguish between the “ontology” or ontological commitments that are internal to a linguistic framework and the external metaphysical question of the reality of any of the items specified within that framework.

    Google Scholar 

  82. See the quotation on p. 55 above.

    Google Scholar 

  83. See the quotation on pp. 60–61.

    Google Scholar 

  84. W. Wick (op. cit.), pp. 53–54.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Ibid. p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Ibid. pp. 55–56.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Wick does not specify exactly how he thinks that Kant’s practical philosophy is directly relevant to the issue. On Hegel’s practical philosophy, see M. Hardimon, ‘Individual Morality and Rational Social Life; a Study of Hegel’s Ethics’ (Dissertation, University of Chicago: 1985)

    Google Scholar 

  88. Johnathan Robinson, Duty and Hypocrisy in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Mind (Toronto: University of Toronto press, 1977). Some aspects of how Hegel’s social theory relates to the epistemological issues of this study are discussed below in Chapter Eleven.

    Google Scholar 

  89. This is not to forget the very original studies of formal pragmatics by W. Sellars, especially ‘Pure Pragmatics and Epistemology’ (Philosophy of Science 15 No. 3 [1947], pp. 181–202) ‘Concepts as Involving Laws and as Inconceivable Without Them’ (Philosophy of Science 15 No. 4 [1948], pp. 287–315).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  90. Frederick Will, ‘The Concern About Truth’ (in: G. W Roberts, ed., The Bertrand Russell Memorial Volume [London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Humanities Press, 1979], pp. 264–284), p. 263.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Hempel, SRFP p. 94.

    Google Scholar 

  92. LPTT pp. 50–52, 54. Hempel speaks here explicitly about revising the concept of truth.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Will, ‘The Concern About Truth’ (op. cit.), p. 266.

    Google Scholar 

  94. ESO p. 213.

    Google Scholar 

  95. See the references given in notes 13–15.

    Google Scholar 

  96. ESO pp. 207–208, 213. See note 96 above.

    Google Scholar 

  97. ‘Empiricism and Abstract Entities’ (op. cit.), p. 433. As the title indicates, Sellars goes on to discuss the problem of abstract entities, leaving this pithy comment to stand on its own.

    Google Scholar 

  98. ESO p. 208.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Ibid. p. 213.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Carnap, ESO p. 208; cf. MCTC p. 46, Hempel, SRFP pp. 94–95.

    Google Scholar 

  101. MCTC p. 46. Cf. T&M pp. 19, 20, 44–45; ESO pp. 207–208; Hempel, LPTT p. 55; SRFP p. 95.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Carnap thinks it odd to try first to determine whether or not there is a kind of entity in order to decide whether or not to adopt a linguistic framework containing variables ranging over those entities (ESO pp. 213–214). However, it is no less perverse to adopt, as Carnap would have it, a linguistic framework before determining whether or not there is a kind of entity—only to receive a trivial, analytic answer to our question based on the syntax of the framework we’ve adopted! The objections I have made to Carnap’s position all grant (for the sake of discussion) his distinction between what is “internal” and what is “external” to a linguistic framework. For a concise discussion of objections to this distinction, including Quine’s, see Rod Bertolet, ‘Merril and Carnap on Realism’ (Southern Journal of Philosophy 20 No. 3 [1982], pp. 277–287).

    Google Scholar 

  103. These objections to Carnap’s position have been searchingly developed by Barry Stroud, The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism , ‘Merril and Carnap on Realism’ (Southern Journal of Philosophy 20 No. 3 [1982], pp. 191–197.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Will, ‘The Concern About Truth’ (op. cit.), p. 273.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Enz. §22z.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Enz. §28z; cf. §62r.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Enz. §28.

    Google Scholar 

  108. G54.8–9/D9/M47.18–9.

    Google Scholar 

  109. WL II pp. 265–66/SL p. 593.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Westphal, K.R. (1989). Some Aspects of Empiricism and Empirical Knowledge. In: Hegel’s Epistemological Realism. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 43. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2342-3_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2342-3_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7554-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2342-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics