Skip to main content

Thomas Reid on Justice: A Rights-Based Theory

  • Chapter
The Philosophy of Thomas Reid

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 42))

  • 139 Accesses

Abstract

Reid’s account of justice follows the familiar pattern of ad hominem arguments against Hume blended with an exposition of an alternative theory. The reasons for Hume’s treatment of justice as an artificial virtue are well-known. For Hume, being just means to accord to each what is his due, as of right, under the established rules of property. Put crudely, the virtue of justice lies in its utility in maintaining property as a bulwark of stable society; its artificiality lies in its dependence on the man-made conventions which create property rights. Because of the attention it gives to property rights, Hume’s thepry has been classified as rights-based in contrast to theories based on need or some sort of merit or desert.(1) However it is better to regard it as a goal-based rule-utilitarian theory and to take Reid’s theory as an example of a rights-based one. (2) Hume’s goal is the stabi1ity of property and society. Individual rights are thus incidental to that goal.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Cf., e.g., Miller (1976).

    Google Scholar 

  2. For these terms see Dworkin (1977, pp. 171-3).

    Google Scholar 

  3. AP, V, v (Works, pp. 652-3).

    Google Scholar 

  4. AP, V, v (Works, pp. 653-5).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Hume (1975, p. 283).

    Google Scholar 

  6. AP, V, v (Works, p. 657).

    Google Scholar 

  7. AP, V, v (Works, p. 655).

    Google Scholar 

  8. AP, III, Pt. III, v & vi (Works, pp. 586-92).

    Google Scholar 

  9. AP, V, v (Works, p. 655).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Hume (1978), p. 478.

    Google Scholar 

  11. AUL MS 2131/8/IV/3.

    Google Scholar 

  12. AP, V, iii (Works, p. 643).

    Google Scholar 

  13. AP, V, v (Works, p. 656).

    Google Scholar 

  14. AP, V, v (Works, p. 644).

    Google Scholar 

  15. AP, V, v (Works, p. 656).

    Google Scholar 

  16. AUL MS 2131/8/IV/3 (Spelling and punctuation follows the manuscript).

    Google Scholar 

  17. AP, V, v (Works, p. 657).

    Google Scholar 

  18. AP, V, v (Works, p. 656).

    Google Scholar 

  19. Smith (1978, p. 9); Cf., Smith (1976). Reid’s Aberdeen Philosophical Society Paper on Justice was delivered in 1758, prior to the publication of Smith’s ideas.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Cf., AP, III, Pt. II, II (Works, p. 557).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Hume (18978), p. 475.

    Google Scholar 

  22. AP, V, V (Works, p. 657).

    Google Scholar 

  23. AP, V, v (Works, p. 657).

    Google Scholar 

  24. AP, V, v (Works, p. 658). Reid’s right to liberty is clearly then not simply a freedom from confinement as implied on p. 656; it is a freedom to act in gratifying desires, a positive rather than a negative liberty. But, as Reid acknowledges, the right to gratify desires is restricted not simply by what would hurt others but also by the duties of an individual to God and to self.

    Google Scholar 

  25. AP, V, v (Works, p. 658).

    Google Scholar 

  26. AP, V, v (Works, p. 658).

    Google Scholar 

  27. AUL MS 2131/7/VII/1c.

    Google Scholar 

  28. AUL MS 2131/7/VII/1c.

    Google Scholar 

  29. AUL MS 2131/7/VII/II.

    Google Scholar 

  30. AP, V, v (Works, p. 659).

    Google Scholar 

  31. See AUL MS 2131/7/VII/II. For an application of Hohfeld’s ‘Rights’ terminology to Reid’s work, see Dalgarno (1984) and (1985).

    Google Scholar 

  32. AP, V, iii (Works, p. 645).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Hume (1975), p. 194.

    Google Scholar 

  34. AUL MS 2131/7/III/Ib.

    Google Scholar 

  35. AUL MS 3061/6.

    Google Scholar 

  36. AP, V, V (Works, p. 659).

    Google Scholar 

  37. AP, V, v (Works, pp. 659-60). Cf. Hume (1975), p. 186.

    Google Scholar 

  38. AP, V, v (Works, p. 662).

    Google Scholar 

  39. AP, V, v (Works, p. 662).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mackinnon, K. (1989). Thomas Reid on Justice: A Rights-Based Theory. In: Dalgarno, M., Matthews, E. (eds) The Philosophy of Thomas Reid. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 42. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2338-6_22

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2338-6_22

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7552-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2338-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics