Skip to main content

Making Out the Signatures: Reid’s Account of the Knowledge of Other Minds

  • Chapter
The Philosophy of Thomas Reid

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 42))

  • 144 Accesses

Abstract

Reid’s conception of his predecessors as belonging to “the Cartesian system”(1) gives him an up-to-date ring. He means not just Descartes’ immediate disciples but all adherents to the theory of ideas, including Locke, Berkeley and Hume.(2) What unites them to Descartes is more fundamental than what divides them from him. This cuts across the ingrained division of nineteenth-century German historians of philosophy into rationalists and empiricists. Reid’s account of his predecessors’ treatment of the problem of other minds, however, comes across as more traditional, for the traditional problem virtually begins with him. (3) The very words ‘other minds’ first occur extensively in his pages. It is surprising how little his predecessors — Locke(4) for instance — have to say on the subject. It is absent even in Kant. True, Descartes concludes in the haunting words of the Third Meditation that he is ‘not alone in the world’ but he is referring to God, and as an external cause not as a person.(5) Not that Reid thinks there is any problem about other minds; it is a problem, he argues, only for holders of the theory of ideas.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. He himself acknowledges Buffier’s recognition of the issue when he cites one of Buffier’s principles of common sense, namely, “That there are other beings and other men in the universe, besides myself”. IP, VI, vii (Works p. 467).

    Google Scholar 

  2. T.E. Jessop cites the Essay (IV xi 12) — see Luce and Jessop (1949), II, p. 107n.. As Locke does not qualify, ‘finite Spirits’ by ‘other’ it seems he is talking about angels. The absurdity of saying ‘we’ don’t know of their existence if they were part of us would have struck even Locke. Cf. Hutcheson’s reference to ‘Other minds’, (1973), IV, I.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Luce and Jessop (1949), II, p. 108 and III, Fourth Dialogue, 5, 6, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  4. I, V, vii (Works p. 129). Moore evidently had this passage in mind in his first reference to Reid in his 1905 paper, ‘The Nature and Reality of Objects of Perception’ — reprinted in G.E. Moore, (1922), pp. 57–8.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Again, there are some hints; see Hume (1888), I iv 7, paragraphs 2, 8, 10. Hume isn’t denying the self exists, as Reid says IP, II, xii (Works p. 293), only the self conceived as a Cartesian substance distinct from any impressions and ideas.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid. (Works p. 465).

    Google Scholar 

  7. I, VII (Works p. 207); Cf. IP, V, iii (Works p. 432).

    Google Scholar 

  8. IP, II, xi (Works p. 288); Cf. I, VII (Works p. 208). Cf. also Berkeley (1949), II, p. 211.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Kames (1779), p. 270.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Berkeley (1949), II, pp. 44, 51f, 52f, 80.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid. (Works p. 289).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. Berkeley (1949), II, pp. 233–4.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Kames (1779), p. 252.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Berkeley (1940), II, p. 247; Cf. IP, II, x (Works pp. 284–5).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Unlike Kames, Reid does not tar Berkeley with atheism. Berkeley’s doctrine, Karnes charges, “if it should not lead to universal scepticism, affords at least a shrewd argument in favour of Atheism” (1779, p. 252).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid. (Works p. 449).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Berkeley (1949), II, p. 233.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid. (Works p. 459).

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid. (Works p. 482).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid. (Works p. 481).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Hume (1975), IV ii, section 29.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Hume (1975), IV i, section 22.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid. (Works p. 458); Cf. IP, I, v (Works p. 239).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf. the First Dialogue: “the senses perceive nothing which they do not perceive immediately: for they make no inferences” (Berkeley (1949), II, pp. 174–5). See also I, VI, xx (Works pp. 183, 185–6); IP, II, v (Works pp. 259–60); IP, II, xiv (Works p. 303); IP, IV, xx (Works p. 328).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid. (Works p. 448).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Berkeley (1949), II, pp. 203–4.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid., p. 204.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Berkeley (1949), I, pp. 265–6.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Berkeley (1949), I, p. 264.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Berkeley (1949), I, p. 273.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Berkeley (1949), II, p. 203.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Broad (1925), p. 324.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Though Berkeley himself slips into the ordinary sense of ‘immediately’ — see Berkeley (1949), I, p. 174; p. 191 does not have this sense.

    Google Scholar 

  34. As with Hume it is often unclear whether ‘reasoning’ includes inductive reasoning. At times Reid seems to mean a priori, demonstrative reasoning, sometimes expressly (Works pp. 110, 122, 124, 332, 458, 460), sometimes implicitly (Works pp. 117, 121, 125, 448–9, 450, 665), opposed to ‘experience’. At other times he seems to include inductive reasoning within ‘reasoning’ (Works pp. 188, 193, 199, 244, 481–2). Hume, when he is careful, rejects the contrast between ‘reason’ and ‘experience’ as ‘superficial’ — Hume (1975), V i note.

    Google Scholar 

  35. IP, I, vi (Works p. 241); Cf. Hume (1978), Introduction, p. xvi.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid. (Works pp. 209–10).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid. (Works p. 420); Cf. IP, I, v (Works p. 239), IP, VI, v (Works p. 443).

    Google Scholar 

  38. I, I, ii (Works p. 98). In his index Hamilton, referring to Works pp. 97 and 98, states that mind can only be studied in one way, by observation and experiment (Works p. 1005). Reid in fact says “nature’s works” (Works p. 97); but contrast I, V, iii (Works p. 122) on the method of “our philosophy concerning the human mind”.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid. (Works p. 460).

    Google Scholar 

  40. I, V, vii (Works p. 129). Cf. Moore: “I can know things, which I cannot prove”, ‘Proof of an External World’ in (1959), p. 150.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Cf. Reid on the absurdity of Descartes’ attempt to prove the existence of the material world, IP, I, vi (Works pp. 241–2).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Ibid. (Works p. 185). Cf. Gilbert Ryle, ‘Sensation’ in (1971), II, pp. 343–5. Ryle’s example is similar to one of Reid’s (loc.cit.).

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ibid. (Works p. 450); Cf. IP, II, xxi (Works p. 332).

    Google Scholar 

  44. IP, VIII, i (Works p. 492), Cf. Hutcheson (1973), I VII, II.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid. (Works p. 502).

    Google Scholar 

  46. Berkeley (1949), III, Fourth Dialogue, 6, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Cf. Austin’s charge that Berkeley confused ‘sign of and ‘sign for’ — Austin (1970), p. 126.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Karnes closes his essay, ‘Veracity of the External Senses’ with “a comparison between the evidence of our senses and that of human testimony” (1779 p. 261).

    Google Scholar 

  49. Cf. Austin, (1962), p. 11; and (1970), p. 48 and p. 97.

    Google Scholar 

  50. ‘A Defence of Common Sense’, in (1959), pp. 42–3; but contrast ‘Hume’s Philosophy’, in (1922), pp. 158–9.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Cf. Moore, ‘The Nature and Reality of Objects of Perception’, in (1922), p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Somerville, J. (1989). Making Out the Signatures: Reid’s Account of the Knowledge of Other Minds. In: Dalgarno, M., Matthews, E. (eds) The Philosophy of Thomas Reid. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 42. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2338-6_16

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2338-6_16

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7552-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2338-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics