Skip to main content

The Grammar of Psychological Concepts

  • Chapter
Beyond the Inner and the Outer

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 214))

  • 132 Accesses

Abstract

Systematic definitions of psychological concepts are rare in psychology. Rather they are systematically neglected in favour of a systematic specification of experimental techniques. The probable reason for this all but deliberate neglect is that psychologists recognize in these definitions the conventions of everyday human knowledge, to which they are professionally disinclined to conform. Psychologists ought not be led by the archaeology of the memory in Proust, the Odyssey of here and now in Joyce, and in general by the lexical contingencies of language.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. According to Wilson (1978, p. 181), Descartes was firmly committed to the possibility of providing physiological accounts of all mental occurrences except the exercise of pure understanding. Only pure understanding has no connection at all with the brain.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See Brentano (1971, II). There are some interesting parallels between Brentano’s description of psychological concepts and Wittgenstein’s. See further chapter 4, § 3.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See Köhler (1929, p. 30), where he asks why the problem of behaviourism has no parallel in physics: The answer is simple enough: Physics is an old science and psychology is in its infancy’. Wittgenstein refers to Köhler’s ‘young science’ theory without mentioning him by name in Philosophical Investigations II xiv, p. 232.

    Google Scholar 

  4. The highly speculative character of James’s physiological explanations is also commented on by Myers (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  5. I mean Ryle’s distinction between ‘occurrences’ and ‘dispositions’. See Ryle (1949, chapter 5). But for a similar use, see also Armstrong (1968, pp. 82–89).

    Google Scholar 

  6. See James (1890, II, p. 7).

    Google Scholar 

  7. See Schopenhauer (1888, pp. 52–57). Schopenhauer, as so many others, is quoted by James (1890, II, pp. 273–275).

    Google Scholar 

  8. See Bain (1855, p. 183).

    Google Scholar 

  9. See Moore (1903, p. 450).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Brentano discusses the subject in his ‘Vom Phänomenalen Grün’ (1907, pp. 5–44).

    Google Scholar 

  11. See James (1890, II, pp. 181–182), chapter XX.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See James (1890, II, pp. 181 ff.). Given his view that sensations have a cognitive relation with the outer world from the outset, his image of the ‘little world’ of sensations is rather peculiar.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See James (1890, II, pp. 183 ff.).

    Google Scholar 

  14. See James (1890, II, p. 154).

    Google Scholar 

  15. See James (1890, II, p. 157). According to Vesey (1965, pp. 49–57), Ryle too endorses the local-sign theory.

    Google Scholar 

  16. James (1890, II, pp. 189 ff.) means the psychologists Brown and Delboeuf.

    Google Scholar 

  17. James’s article appeared originally as ‘What is an emotion’ (1884) and as ‘The physical basis of emotion’ (1894), both published in James (1920).

    Google Scholar 

  18. See James (1920, p. 346).

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Wundt (1874).

    Google Scholar 

  20. See James (1920, pp. 351–352), where he confesses to be dissatisfied with the example, but maintains his view that the felt emotion is some or other organic change.

    Google Scholar 

  21. In the early stages of his development Wittgenstein shows much more sympathy with the James-Lange theory (and especially with the idea that the experience of loca table feelings is important) than in his later work; see The Brown Book, p. 103.

    Google Scholar 

  22. James seems to confuse cause and object, for he calls for instance heartbeats the objects of anger. But as Myers (1986, p. 241) rightly remarks, we have to distinguish between the awareness of heartbeats and the feeling of anger. The relation between the emotion and the bodily feeling is contingent and hence the emotion can exist alongside the bodily feeling. In that case the ‘objects’ postulated by James are not required. Wittgenstein would call these ‘objects’ causes.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Wittgenstein does admit that there are typical cases in which the object of emotions is identical to their cause (RPP II, § 148).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Wittgenstein mentions Heidegger in his conversations with Waismann. See McGuinness (1979, pp. 67–68).

    Google Scholar 

  25. See James (1890, II, pp. 51 ff.).

    Google Scholar 

  26. See Köhler (1929, pp. 5–6).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Kosslyn (1973) endorses the ‘picture-theory’ rather explicitly.

    Google Scholar 

  28. See Hume (1978, p. 1).

    Google Scholar 

  29. See Russell (1948, pp. 107–109). The same view can be found in Russell (1921, pp. 145 ff.).

    Google Scholar 

  30. See James (1890, II, pp. 70–71).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ryle’s position (1949, chapter 8) seems to be more in line with that of Watson. 45 The English translation writes ‘image’ here. The same word is translated in § 84 as ‘image-picture’ and in § 110 as ‘imagination-picture’.

    Google Scholar 

  32. There is a striking resemblance here between Wittgenstein and Sartre. The latter writes for instance that in the imagination ‘je n’y trouverai jamais que ce que j’y ai mis’ (1940, p. 23).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Perhaps Wittgenstein was influenced by this aphorism of Weininger (1904, p. 67): ‘Dualism consists in the fact that we do not create our sensations’.

    Google Scholar 

  34. See Perky (1910). Sartre (1940, p. 108) also criticizes this experiment.

    Google Scholar 

  35. See Hume (1978, p. 2).

    Google Scholar 

  36. Russell’s main thesis is that ‘all psychic phenomena are built up out of sensations and images alone’ (1927, p. 279).

    Google Scholar 

  37. For this sounding-board metaphor, see James (1890, II, p. 471).

    Google Scholar 

  38. An exception must be made for Hintikka (1986, pp. 289 ff.). But Hintikka also wants to accommodate the whole of psychological concepts within the categories of either episodic private experiences or propositional attitudes. His use of the latter is rather dispositional, as evidenced by his examples: belief, hope, and expectation. At any rate it leaves out ‘mental activities’ and ‘abilities’.

    Google Scholar 

  39. This epistemological view of Wittgenstein is held by many authors, such as Albritton (1964), Malcolm (1950; 1954), and Kenny (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  40. See Last Writings, § 959.

    Google Scholar 

  41. See chapter 1, pp. 16–17 for a general description of the content of MS 128. MS 180b is exclusively devoted to feelings of tendency and expectation. The first few pages contain some remarks about the secondary meanings of words (see chapter 6, pp. 161–162 ± 3ff.).

    Google Scholar 

  42. See James (1890, I, pp. 249 ff.).

    Google Scholar 

  43. See James (1890, I, p. 233).

    Google Scholar 

  44. See James (1890, I, p. 243).

    Google Scholar 

  45. See James (1890, I, p. 244).

    Google Scholar 

  46. See Weininger (1903, p. 100) for his remarks about psychology. He writes on the will in (1904, pp. 153–156).

    Google Scholar 

  47. See for instance Mounce (1981, p. 88) and Hacker (1972, pp. 59–60).

    Google Scholar 

  48. This equation is also commented on by Winch (1968).

    Google Scholar 

  49. See James (1890, II, pp. 487–488).

    Google Scholar 

  50. Lotze is also mentioned by James as a supporter of the ideo-motor theory (1890, II, p. 523).

    Google Scholar 

  51. See James (1890, II, pp. 524–525).

    Google Scholar 

  52. The manuscripts concerned are MS 115 (1) and MS 157a. There are also lecture notes on the freedom of the will by Smythies (1945–1946).

    Google Scholar 

  53. For this interpretation, see von Wright (1982, p. 151).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1990 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ter Hark, M. (1990). The Grammar of Psychological Concepts. In: Beyond the Inner and the Outer. Synthese Library, vol 214. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2089-7_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2089-7_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7438-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2089-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics