Skip to main content

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 38))

  • 130 Accesses

Abstract

For over one hundred years, the links between logic and mathematics have been so close that it is difficult to think of the one without the other. All the persons chiefly responsible for the development of symbolic logic were both mathematicians and logicians.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Encylopedia Brittanica, 11th ed., s.v. “De Morgan, Augustus.”

    Google Scholar 

  2. See his wide-ranging contributions to the Penny Cyclopaedia, Notes and Queries, and, especially, the Athenaeum Even though his contributions to the Athenaeum were unsigned, it is possible to determine what they were because bound copies of them, initialed by De Morgan, are deposited at the University of London Library.

    Google Scholar 

  3. “On the Foundation of Algebra,” Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 7 (1841): 173–87; 7 (1842): 287–300; 8 (1844): 139–42; 8 (1847): 241–53.

    Google Scholar 

  4. In fact, only one of the 324 teaching notebooks deals solely with logic. This is Ms. 775/203, “On the Two Forms of the Universal Affirmative Proposition,” De Morgan Papers, University of London Library. A few other notebooks consider geometrical demonstration (see note 23).

    Google Scholar 

  5. “On the Study of Mathematics.”

    Google Scholar 

  6. De Morgan even uses this very language. See S5, 345 and De Morgan’s review of Herbert Spencer, The Classification of the Sciences, Athenaeum (21 May 1864): 709.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See note 1, Chapter Two.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See also De Morgan’s review of Sir William Hamilton, Lectures on Metaphysics and Logic, Athenaeum (24 November 1860): 706.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See also Notes and Queries (27 August 1864): 161.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See also De Morgan’s review of John Stuart Mill, An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philosophy, Athenaeum (27 May 1865): 711; “Speech of Professor De Morgan, President,” Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 1 (1866): 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Penny Cyclopaedia, Vol. XV (1839), s.v. “Mathematics,” 11ff.

    Google Scholar 

  12. G.C. Smith, ed., The Boole-De Morgan Correspondence 1842–1864 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982).

    Google Scholar 

  13. For some other references to Boole by De Morgan, see his review of Boole’s Mathematical Analysis of Logic, Athenaeum (29 January 1848): 107–8;

    Google Scholar 

  14. his obituary of Boole, Macmillan’s Magazine (February, 1865): 279–80; “Budget of Paradoxes, No. XXIII,” Athenaeum (11 March 1865): 350;

    Google Scholar 

  15. De Morgan to Sir William Rowan Hamilton, 5 October 1852, in Robert Percival Graves, Life of Sir William Rowan Hamilton, Vol. III (Dublin: Hodges, Figgis & Co./London: Longmans, Green & Co., 1889), 421.

    Google Scholar 

  16. In the title of his detailed review of The Boole-De Morgan Correspondence, John Corcoran has gone so far as to use the apt phrase “Correspondence without Communication”; History and Philosphy of Logic 7 (1986): 65–75. For other reviews see those by Theodore Hailperin, Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (1984): 657–59;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. and Calvin Jongsma, Historia Mathematica 12 (1985): 186–90. In reading through De Morgan’s extensive correspondence with both Boole and Sir William Rowan Hamilton, one gets the impression that he never seriously studied their works. With his great variety of interests and heavy work schedule, he probably had neither the time nor the inclination to do so. Boole seems not to have studied De Morgan’s work carefully either. On 27 May 1852, he wrote Sir William Hamilton, “The peculiarities of Mr. De Morgan’s system of logic I have not made an object of study, and I do not feel competent therefore to pass any opinion upon the correctness or mutual consistency of his views.”

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. John Veitch, Memoir of Sir William Hamilton, Bart. (Edinburgh and London: William Blackwood and Sons, 1869), 344.

    Google Scholar 

  19. De Morgan to Boole, 28 November 1847, Correspondence, 25.

    Google Scholar 

  20. “Introductory Lecture” and Penny Cyclopaedia, Vol. XI (1838), s.v. “Geometry,” 151, 156.

    Google Scholar 

  21. In this we followed Ian Mueller, “Greek Mathematics,” 37–43.

    Google Scholar 

  22. These include The Connexion of Number and Magnitude: An Attempt to Explain the Fifth Book of Euclid (London: Taylor and Walton, 1836); “Short Supplementary Remarks on the First Six Books of Euclid’s Elements,” Companion to the Almanac for 1849, 5–20; “On Indirect Demonstration,” Philosophical Magazine 3 (1852): 435–38. Among his teaching notebooks in the University of London Library, see “Notions Preliminary to Geometry,” 775/202; “On the Two Forms of the Universal Affirmative Proposition,” 775/203; and 775/310 (untitled).

    Google Scholar 

  23. For De Morgan’s views on issues regarding the place of logic in the teaching of geometry, see the following articles from the Quarterly Journal of Education: “On Mathematical Instruction” 1 (1831): 264- 79; “On the Method of Teaching the Elements of Geometry, Part I” 6 (1833): 35–49; and “A Method of Teaching Geometry, No. II” 6 (1833): 237–51.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Penny Cyclopaedia, Vol. XV (1839), s.v. “Mathematics,” 12.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See especially the “Foundation of Algebra” series (n. 3).

    Google Scholar 

  26. “Calculus of Functions,” Encyclopaedia Metropolitana (1836), 306–92; and Penny Cyclopaedia, Vol. XVI (1840), s.v. “Operation.”

    Google Scholar 

  27. For the problems of interpreting negative and “impossible” numbers see Ernest Nagel, “‘Impossible Numbers’: A Chapter in the History of Modern Logic,” in Studies in the History of Ideas, ed. Columbia University Philosophy Department (New York: Columbia University Press, 1935), 429–74; Morris Kline, Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times (New York: Oxford University Press, 1972), 592–97, 626–32.

    Google Scholar 

  28. The Principles of Algebra, 2 vols. (London, 1796–99).

    Google Scholar 

  29. We will leave open the question of just which laws to retain. We must, for instance, exclude laws such as (x) ~ (x2 = -1), which hold for the reals and not for the imaginaries. Peacock seems to have had in mind algebraic identities, such as x(x + 1) = x2 + x.

    Google Scholar 

  30. For recent discussions of this period see Morris Kline, Mathematical Thought, 772–94; Harvey W. Becher, “Woodhouse, Babbage, Peacock and Modern Algebra,” Historia Mathematica 7 (1980): 389–400;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Daniel A. Clock, “A New British Concept of Algebra: 1825–1850” (diss., University of Wisconsin, 1964);

    Google Scholar 

  32. J.M. Dubbey, “Babbage, Peacock and Modern Algebra,” Historia Mathematica 4 (1977): 295–302;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Elaine Koppelman, “The Calculus of Operations and the Rise of Abstract Algebra,” Archive for History of Exact Sciences 8 (1971): 155–242;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Luboš Nový, Origins of Modern Algebra (Leyden: Noordhoff International Publishing, 1973);

    Google Scholar 

  35. Helena M. Pycior, “George Peacock and the British Origins of Symbolical Algebra,” Historia Mathematica 8 (1981): 23–45; “Historical Roots of Confusion among Beginning Algebra Students: A Newly Discovered Manuscript,” Mathematics Magazine 55 (1982): 150–56; “Early Criticism of the Symbolical Approach to Algebra,” Historia Mathematica 9 (1982): 392- 412; “Internalism, Externalism, and Beyond: 19th Century British Algebra,” Historia Mathematica 11 (1984): 424–41;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Joan L. Richards, “The Art and Science of British Algebra: A Study in the Perception of Mathematical Truth,” Historia Mathematica 7 (1980): 343–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. A Treatise on Algebra: Vol. I., Arithmetical Algebra (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1842); Vol. II., On Symbolical Algebra and its Applications to the Geometry of Position (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1845); “Report on the Recent Progress and Present State of Certain Branches of Analysis,” Report of the Third Meeting of the British Association for the Advancement of Science (London: John Murray, 1834), 185–352. See also De Morgan’s review of Peacock’s Treatise in the Quarterly Journal of Education 9 (1835): 91- 110, 293–311.

    Google Scholar 

  38. “Report,” 194.

    Google Scholar 

  39. “Report,” 194–95.

    Google Scholar 

  40. “Report,” 198.

    Google Scholar 

  41. “Report,” 199.

    Google Scholar 

  42. “Report,” 200.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Trigonometry and Double Algebra (London: Taylor, Walton, and Maberly, 1849), 89. This will be refered to as “TDA.” For discussions of De Morgan’s work in algebra see Helena M. Pycior, “Augustus De Morgan’s Algebraic Work: The Three Stages,” Isis 74 (1983): 211–26;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Joan L. Richards, “Augustus De Morgan, The History of Mathematics, and the Foundations of Algebra,” Isis 78 (1987): 7–30;

    Google Scholar 

  45. and G.C. Smith, “De Morgan and the Laws of Algebra,” Centaurus 25 (1981): 50–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. “On Infinity; and on the Sign of Equality,” Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 11 (1866): 145–89; “On Divergent Series and Various Points of Analysis Connected with Them,” Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 8 (1849): 182–203.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1990 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Merrill, D.D. (1990). Logic and Mathematics. In: Augustus De Morgan and the Logic of Relations. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 38. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2047-7_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2047-7_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7418-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2047-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics