Skip to main content

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 38))

  • 133 Accesses

Abstract

During the period from 1846 to 1850, De Morgan’s thinking about relations developed in two ways which were essential for motivating a formal logic of relations. The first was the recognition that relations are a subject for logical study in their own right. The form which this recognition took in De Morgan’s work was unusual, and it gave rise to philosophical problems; but it was important in shaping his entire approach to the logic of relations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. De Morgan often referred to the fact that FL appeared on the same day as George Boole’s The Mathematical Analysis of Logic (Cambridge: Macmillan, Barclay, & Macmillan, 1847). His first reference to this seems to be in his review of Boole, where he says, “On the very day in which Mr. De Morgan’s work was published in London, the one at the head of our article appeared at Cambridge.” (Athenaeum, 29 January 1848, 107.) This claim is essentially correct, though De Morgan may have stretched the truth by a day or two. He wrote in his own copy of Boole’s work (University of London Library) that he received it on 27 November 1847. He wrote Boole on 28 November that he had read Boole’s work “with great admiration,” which suggests either that De Morgan read the work very quickly, or that he received it before the 27th, or that he was being overly polite. FL was published on 24 November.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See G.C. Smith, The Boole-De Morgan Correspondence 1842–1864 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), 24.

    Google Scholar 

  3. De Morgan correctly adds the qualification that in the general case, we have “y = -x as one at least of certain alternatives.” Thus, suppose that y = - x and z = x2 yield z = (- y)2. From this it follows only that z = (- y)2 and z = (x)2 yield either y = - x or y = x. Thus, y = - x is only one of two alternatives. But not even this condition is satisfied in the relational case (3.14). (A comment by John Corcoran pointed out to me the need for this clarification.)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Unsigned review of FL, Athenaeum (11 December 1847), 1264. De Morgan does not identify the critic, but his phrasing is exactly the same as that of the review, except that there is a misprint which has replaced “marking” by “making.”

    Google Scholar 

  5. It must be confessed that De Morgan does not have a clearly stated distinction between premises and rules; but some such distinction seems required in this context. For an interesting discussion of this distinction in Boole, see John Corcoran and Susan Wood, “Boole’s Criteria for Validity and Invalidity,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 21 (1980): 609–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. C.S. Peirce, “Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives, Resulting from an Amplification of the Conceptions of Boole’s Calculus of Logic,” Memoirs of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, n.s. Vol. 9, pt. 2 (1870): 317–78. On the relation between De Morgan and Peirce see my article, “De Morgan, Peirce and the Logic of Relations,” Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 14 (1978): 247–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. On earlier treatments of oblique inferences see Paul Thorn, “Termini Obliqui and the Logic of Relations,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 59 (1977): 143–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. E.J. Ashworth, “Joachim Jungius (1587–1657) and the Logic of Relations,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 49 (1967): 72–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. G.H.R. Parkinson, Logic and Reality in Leibnizs Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), 37–50. Oblique inferences contain oblique terms-that is, terms in some grammatical case other than the nominative.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Thus Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell appear to be incorrect in their treatment of the argument. Principia Mathematica, Vol. I, 2d ed. (1925; reprinted, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1950), 291. For more on the formulation of this argument, see R.G. Wengert, “Schematizing De Morgan’s Argument,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 15 (1974): 165–66; and in response, my “On De Morgan’s Argument,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 18 (1977): 133–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Logic, 50.

    Google Scholar 

  12. S2, 28–29. Leibniz seems to have used a similar principle in dealing with oblique inferences. See Leibniz’s 1687 letter to Vegetius, in G.H.R. Parkinson, ed., Leibniz Logical Papers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1966), 88.

    Google Scholar 

  13. C.S. Peirce, “Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives,” passim.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1990 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Merrill, D.D. (1990). Generalizing the Copula. In: Augustus De Morgan and the Logic of Relations. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 38. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2047-7_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2047-7_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7418-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2047-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics