Skip to main content

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 43))

  • 114 Accesses

Abstract

We proceed to develop logical systems intended to provide formal interpretations for the different layers of the modal syllogistic. In this Chapter, we construct an axiomatic system and formal semantics for an apodeictic system which includes ecthetic proofs of Baroco XLL and Bocardo LXL. In our system, Aristotle’s restrictions on Substitution and Cut are dropped. And the problematic moods are integrated with the apodeictic. A related system is formulated in which only assertoric forms appear, with or without modalised terms. We then give a classification of alternative approaches. The axiomatic system of McCall, with Johnson’s semantics — which rejects Baroco XLL and Bocardo LXL — is located within this classification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. THOM 1981 §18.

    Google Scholar 

  2. OCKHAM II.24.27–48 argues that “the Philosopher in the Prior Analytics speaks of the conversion of necessity-propositions only when they are taken in the composite sense [i.e. de dicto] or equivalently.”

    Google Scholar 

  3. JOHNSON 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  4. STAHL 1976 p.209 uses similar diagrams.

    Google Scholar 

  5. PATTERSON 1990 is mistaken when he says (n.20) that Li-conversion “is not valid on the reading (de re) one needs if Darii NAN [our LXL] is to be valid”. Our de re semantics validates both Li-conversion and Darii LXL.

    Google Scholar 

  6. BRENNER p.8.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See McCALL 1963 §20. McCall’s approach will be discussed in §25.1.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See THOMASON p.112. Thomason’s ideas will be discussed in §25.1.

    Google Scholar 

  9. These are all features of system A in THOM 1981 Chapter Six.

    Google Scholar 

  10. CAMPSALL 14.04.

    Google Scholar 

  11. The basic idea of introducing modalised terms and special principles relating them to unmodalised terms is in STAHL 1976 p.179, and before that in GEACH pp.202–203.

    Google Scholar 

  12. A proof can be adapted from that in THOM 1981 §46.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See SMILEY; THOM 1981 §48.

    Google Scholar 

  14. JOHNSON 1989 p.274.

    Google Scholar 

  15. THOM 1991, 1.5.

    Google Scholar 

  16. THOMASON Definition 2.

    Google Scholar 

  17. JOHNSON 1989 (d,e) p.274.

    Google Scholar 

  18. THOMASON Definition 3.

    Google Scholar 

  19. JOHNSON 1989 (c) p.274.

    Google Scholar 

  20. JOHNSON 1989 p.274.

    Google Scholar 

  21. JOHNSON 1989 (c) p.274.

    Google Scholar 

  22. JOHNSON 1989 (c) p.274.

    Google Scholar 

  23. JOHNSON 1989 (c) p.274.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See FREDDOSO p.18.

    Google Scholar 

  25. JOHNSON 1989 p.274. THOMASON p.116. GEACH p.202 proposes a superstructure identical with this, except that Lo-forms are read as in superstructure A.

    Google Scholar 

  26. BURIDAN 2,6,8: “In any divided sentence de necessario the subject is ampliated to supposit for those things which can be.”

    Google Scholar 

  27. BURIDAN 4.2.3: “In the first figure, there is always a valid syllogism from a pair of premisses de necessario… to a conclusion with the same mode….”

    Google Scholar 

  28. BURIDAN 4.2.5: “In the second figure… there is always a valid syllogism from a pair of premisses de necessario… to a conclusion which is de necessario….”

    Google Scholar 

  29. BURIDAN 4.2.8: “In the third figure… a conclusion de necessario always follows from two premisses which are de necessario….”

    Google Scholar 

  30. BURIDAN 4.2.53: “In the first figure… from a major de necessario and an assertoric minor there is always a valid syllogism to a particular conclusion de necessario….”

    Google Scholar 

  31. BURIDAN 2.6.27: “(a) From no sentence de necessario does there follow another sentence de necessario by conversion of the terms, except (b) a universal negative follows from a universal negative.”

    Google Scholar 

  32. BURIDAN 2.6.14: “From no sentence de necessario does there follow an assertoric sentence, or conversely, unless an assertoric universal negative follows from a universal negative de necessario.”

    Google Scholar 

  33. BURIDAN 4.2.53: “In the first figure… from a major de necessario and an assertoric minor there is always a valid syllogism… but… not to a universal conclusion de necessario.”

    Google Scholar 

  34. BURIDAN 4.2.57.

    Google Scholar 

  35. BURIDAN 4.2.65.

    Google Scholar 

  36. OCKHAM IIIa.31.15–16 etc. Buridan allows that the normal implication of an ampliateci subject can be cancelled by inserting the phrase ‘what is’ before the subject; and Ockham allows that the normal implication of a subject that is neither ampliated nor restricted can be cancelled by an explicit ampliation of the subject.

    Google Scholar 

  37. OCKHAM IIIc. 11.3–6. These inferences are said to be valid whether the modal propositions are taken ‘in sensu compositionis’ or ‘in sensu divisionis’.

    Google Scholar 

  38. OCKHAM IIIa.31.8–43. These syllogisms are said to be valid if (but only if) the modal propositions are taken ‘in sensu divisionis’.

    Google Scholar 

  39. OCKHAM II.24.49–79.

    Google Scholar 

  40. §41. See Ockham IIIa.33.54–62.

    Google Scholar 

  41. NORTMANN 1994, p. 117. For a critique of Theophrastus, see PATTERSON 1995 §4.1.

    Google Scholar 

  42. See BOCHENSKI, Chapter 5 §3.

    Google Scholar 

  43. ŁUKASIEWICZ p.189.

    Google Scholar 

  44. ŁUKASIEWICZ p.137.

    Google Scholar 

  45. KNUUTTILA p.163.

    Google Scholar 

  46. BECKER, p.90.

    Google Scholar 

  47. For critiques of the Becker approach, see McCALL 1963 §8, PATTERSON 1989 §1.

    Google Scholar 

  48. ANGELELLI, pp.176–213.

    Google Scholar 

  49. ANGELELLI p.207.

    Google Scholar 

  50. ANGELELLI p.210.

    Google Scholar 

  51. NORTMANN 1994, 120–121. Nortmann mistakenly refers here to Ferio LQM, a mood which, though arguably Aristotelian, is not explicitly proved in the text.

    Google Scholar 

  52. ANGELELLI §12.

    Google Scholar 

  53. This analysis occurs in SCHMIDT, p.82.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Neither NORTMANN 1990 nor NORTMANN 1994 explicitly includes an analysis of Li- or Lo-forms. The analysis I have suggested implies the convertibility of Li-forms, as shown above.

    Google Scholar 

  55. NORTMANN 1990 p.73. For a critique of Nortmann’s approach, see PATTERSON 1995 pp.178ff.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1996 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Thom, P. (1996). System AL . In: The Logic of Essentialism. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 43. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-1663-0_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-1663-0_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7244-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-1663-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics