Skip to main content

Atoms and the ‘Analogy of Nature’: Newton’s Third Rule of Philosophizing

  • Chapter
Tradition and Innovation

Part of the book series: The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science ((WONS,volume 56))

Abstract

As in the case of ancient atomism, the revival of atomistic doctrines in the seventeenth century gave rise to questions regarding the existence and properties of primordial entities. With their insistent emphasis on sensory experience as a foundation of physical knowledge, the English experimental empiricists were faced with various epistemological problems. The majority, such as Robert Hooke and Henry Power, believed that atoms could in principle be observed: hence their problem was not the nature of knowledge of the microscopic, but rather how our knowledge could be extended into that realm.1 Thinkess such as Henry More and Ralph Cudworth tended to the view that, even if we could observe atoms, it would not add to our knowledge of first principles.2 Newton, and to some extent Locke, were confronted with a more difficult problem. Simply stated it is this: are there justificatory principles by which to sanction inferences from what is observable to what in principle is unobservable? If the basis of natural knowledge is strictly confined to what is actually or possibly observable, how can any claims be established about the nature and existence of atoms? The following study will refer to these questions as the problem of transduction;3 moreover it will be concerned primarily to analyse Newton’s use of the phrase ‘the analogy of Nature’. In its best known context that phrase appears in the Rules of Philosophizing prefixed to the third Book of the Principia in 1713.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. For a detailed discussion of this approach with a full analysis of a range of texts see Laurens Laudan ‘The Clock Metaphor and Probabilism: The Impact of Descartes on English Methdoological Thought, 1650–65’, Annals of Science 22 (1966), 81–97. I am grateful to Charles B. Schmitt Laurens Laudan, Gerd Buchdahl and John Yolton for comments on an early draft of this paper. They are in no way responsible for its interpretatin.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See Henry More, Divine Dialogues (London, 1668)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ralph Cudworth, The True Intellectual System of the Universe (London, 1678).

    Google Scholar 

  4. In his study Philosophy, Science and Sense Perception (The Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore, 1964), Maurice Mandelbaum has used the term ‘transdiction’ in designating this problem. To conform more with the usage of the terms ‘deduction’ and ‘induction’, I have decided to use the term ‘transduction’, i.e. ‘leading across’. In no way do I wish to imply thereby that the latter is a special type of ‘ inference’; rather, the term is used to designate a problem recognized in seventeenth-century natural philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Sir Isaac Newton, The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, translated by Benjamin Motte (London, 1729), vol. II, 203. I have altered the Latin of the statement of the rule in the interest of accuracy. The corresponding Latin is in the appendix to this paper. The original is found in Isaac Newton, Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (Cambridge, 1713), 357.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Another such integral element is homogeneity. Though never explicitly stated by Newton, this is a fundamental presupposition lying behind his identification of a quantity of matter with its vis inertiae, a proportionality questioned by Roger Cotes in a letter of February 1711/2. See Joseph Edleston, Correspondence of Sir Isaac Newton and Professor Cotes (London, 1850), 65–66.

    Google Scholar 

  7. This is the received view as developed in the writings of Basil Willey, The Seventeenth-Century Background (London, 1934)

    Google Scholar 

  8. M. Macklen, The Anatomy of the World: Relations between Natural and Moral Law from Donne to Pope (Minnesota, 1958)

    Google Scholar 

  9. G. P. Conger, Theories of Macrocosms and Microcosms in the History of Philosophy (New York, 1922).

    Google Scholar 

  10. For this topic see Earl R. Wasserman, ‘Nature Moralized: The Divine Analogy in the Eighteenth Century’, A Journal of English Literary History 20 (1953), 39–76.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See, for instance: Henry Pemberton, A View of Sir Isaac newton’s Philosophy (London, 1728), 24–25; Colin Maclaurin, An Account of Sir Isaac Newton’s Philosophical Discoveries (London, 1748), 22

    Google Scholar 

  12. Gowin Knight, An Attempt to demonstrate that all the Phaenomena of Nature may be explained by two simple active Principles Attraction and Repulsion (London, 1748), 7

    Google Scholar 

  13. George Cheyne, Philosophical Principles of Religion: Natural and Revealed (London, 1715), 36 Willem Jacob Storem-van’s Gravesande, Phyices Elementa Mathematica sive Introduction ad Philosophiam Newtoniam (Editio Secunda, Lugduni Batavorum, 1725), Praefatio, and Liber I, Caput I, 1–7

    Google Scholar 

  14. Benjamin Martin, Pilosophia Britannica: or a New and Comprehensive System of the Newtonian Philosophy (Reading, 1747), 1–42. In his first lecture, Martin discusses Newton’s four rules in some detail. Thus when ‘we take survey of the visible world’, we conclude that all bodies ‘consist of one and the same sort of Matter or Substance’. He concludes that ‘Matter, thus variously modified and configurated, constitutes an infinite variety of bodies, all of which are found to have the following common Properties ’.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Thomas Rutherforth, A System of Natural Philosophy (Cambridge, 1748), Introduction. The first three rules are discussed the only means of making ‘knowledge real and universal’ Rule Three is seen primarily as an inductive rule.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Richgard Helsham, A Course of Lectures in Natural Philosophy, published by Bryan Robinson, 5th edition (London, 1777). The four rules are quoted in full in the Preface. Robinson notes that ‘This method and these rules, have been carefully observed by our author in these Lectures ’ (p. viii).

    Google Scholar 

  17. George Adams, Lectures on Natural and Experimental Philosophy (London, 1794), vol. II. In a lengthy lecture entitled ‘In the method of Reasoning in Natural Philosophy’ Adams concludes his discussion of the history of method by analysing Newton’s first three rules. Of the third rule he says that it allows us ‘by analogy to extend our conclusion to all other bodies, and thus make it universa: a way of reasoning, that is agreeable to the harmony of things and to the old maxim ascribed to Hermes (p 134). For this maxim see note 40 below, on Maclurin. Adams is drawing on Maclaurin’s treatise.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Tiberius Cavallo, The Elements of Natural or Experimental Philosophy (London, 1803), vol. I, 7. Quotes Newton’s four rules and connects them with the generality of the three laws.

    Google Scholar 

  19. William Nicholson, An Introduction to Natural Philosophy (London, 1805), vol. I. In his introduction he discusses intuition, demonstration, and probabilistic knowledge, saying of natural philosophy that it is based on analogy: ‘To give stability to this science, it is necessary to admit no probabilities, as first principles of analogy, but those which possess the strongest and most incontrovertible resemblance to truth. For this purpose, the following rules are adopted’: the first three rules are then quoted without comment.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Joseph Pristley, Disquisitions Relating to Matter and Spirit, 2nd edition (Birmingham, 1782), sections I and II

    Google Scholar 

  21. Etienne Bonnot de Condillac, (Euvres Complètes de Condillac, tome troisième (Paris, 1803), chapitre XII, 327–358

    Google Scholar 

  22. Petrus van Musschenbroek, Elementa physicae (Lugduni Batavorum, 1734), 6, and Introductio ad philosophiam naturalem (Lugduni Batavorum, 1764), vol. I, 14; Roger Joseph Boscovicch, A Theory of Natural Philosophy (Latin-English Edition, London, 1922), sections 40–42. Boscovich is critical of the third rule on the grounds that induction does not support the transference of many physical properties to the parts of phenomena. The Theory was first published in 1758.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Brian Higgins, A Philosophical Essay Concerning Light (London, 1776), 18–19

    Google Scholar 

  24. James Hutton, Dissertations on Different Subjects in Natural Philosophy (Edinburgh, 1792), part III, 279–300

    Google Scholar 

  25. William Whewell, On the Philosophy of Discovery (London, 1860), chapter XVIII, 181–200, section 14. Whewell is mainly concerned in this chapter with the notion of vera causa as discussed in Newton’s first rule. He points out, however, that the third rule’s conception of universal laws in inconsistent with the stricture of the fourth rule that a ‘law may be inaccurate’. See also Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences (London, 1840), vol. I, 416, where Whewell observes that the third rule is circular.

    Google Scholar 

  26. James Challis, ‘On Newton’s “Foundations of all Philosophy”‘, Phil. Mag. 26 (1863), 280–292. In this particular article Challis is attempting to base a theory of science on Newton’s third rule. These discussions are the most interesting in the literature I have examined. Most of these writers are concerned with the problem of generalizing properties of matter, rather than with Newton’s criterion for deciding essential qualities. Many other writers such as Halley, Stirling, Ferguson, Desaguilers, Wright and Worster mention or refer to the rule; these with the above references are more than sufficient to establish the widespread influence of this aspect of Newton’s methodology throughout the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries. I am grateful to Laurens Laudan for the references to Condillac and Musschenbrock, and to Peter Heimann for calling attentinn to Higgins.

    Google Scholar 

  27. This question is discussed with great vigour and in detail by James Hutton in his Dissertations on Different Subjects in Natural Philosophy (Edinburgh 1792), part III, ‘Physical Dissertations on the Powers of Matter and Appearance of Bodies’, and in his An Investigation of the Principles of Knowledge, and of the Process of Reason, From Sense to Science and Philosophy (Edinburgh, 1794), vol. II, section XII. Hutton makes it clear by referring to unnamed contemporaries that the problem of identifying matter with bodies or with some sort of unperceived theoretical enttty was a live issue in the late eighteenth century. His own position is unambiguous. Identifying matter with intensive powers he states: ‘Matter as a thing distinctly different from body has not been observed by us nor ever can be made the subject of our observation. Our immediate knowledge, or all external information comes necessarily from sensible and perceptible bodies, which being formed of matter must be distinctly different from it’, Dissertations, part III 306.

    Google Scholar 

  28. A similar distinction is made by the Newtonian Thomas Exley, Principles of Natural Philosophy: or, a New Theory of Physics, Founded on Gravitation, and Applied in Explaining the General Properties of Matter (London, 1829). Exley makes a distinction between ‘The theoretical constutution of matter’, section II, 6–45, and ‘The theoretical construction of bodies’. In Postulate I (p. 3) he states: ‘Let it be granted that an atom of matter consists of an indefinitely small sphere of repulsion, which is the central part of an indefinitely extended concentric sphere of attraction’; drawing on this postulate, Proposition I of section II states: ‘If matter be constituted, as in post. I., it will be capable of rest and motion, as will also the bodies consisting of such matter’. [Italics mine.] Exley’s distinction is really that between ordinary matter and ‘theoretical’ matter; since in Definition I of section I he defines matter as ‘that substance which we perceive by the senses’.

    Google Scholar 

  29. For a discussion of these theories see P. M. Heimann and J. E. McGuire, ‘Newtonian Forces and Lockean Powers: Concepts of Matter in Eighteenth-Century Thought’, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 3 (1971), 233–306.

    Google Scholar 

  30. There is much literature on this, though more research is desirabe. The standard sources are: Kurd Lasswitz, Geschichte der Atomistik yom Mittelater bis Newton, vol. I (Hamburg and Leipzig, 1890)

    Google Scholar 

  31. J. R. Partington, A History of Chemistry, vol. II (London, 1961).

    Google Scholar 

  32. See also M. Boas [Hall], ‘The Establishment of the Mechanical Philosophy’, Osiris 10 (1952), 412–541

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. R. Hooykaas, ‘The Experimental Origin of Chemical Atomic and Molecular Theory before Boyle’, Chymia, 2 (1949), 65–80

    Google Scholar 

  34. 11e Thomas S. Kuhn, ‘Robert Boyle and Structuall Chemistry in the Seveneeenth Century’, Isis 43 (1952), 12–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Tullio Gregory, ‘Studi sull’Atomismo de Seicento. David van Goorle e Daniel Sennert’, Giornale Critico della Filosofia Italiana, Fasc I (1966), 44–63; W. Subow, ‘Zur Geschichte des Kampfes zwischen dem Atomismus und dem Aristotelismus im 17. Jahrhundert (Minima naturalia und Mixtio)’, in N. A. Figurowski et al., Sowjetische Beiträge zur Geschichte der Naturwissenschaft (Berlin, 1960), 161–191

    Google Scholar 

  36. E. J. Dijksterhuis, The Mechanization of the World Picture, trans C. Dikshoorn (Oxford, 1962), patt III, section V

    Google Scholar 

  37. Robert H. Kargon, Atomism in England from Hariot to Newton (Oxford, 1966).

    Google Scholar 

  38. For a discussion of this distinction in relation to Galileo, Gassendi, Descartes and leibniz see Ivor Leclerc, ‘Atomism, Substance, and the Concept of Body in Seventeenth-Century Thought’, Filosofia Della Scienza, No. 27 (Turin, 1968) (printed also in Filosofia, 1968).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Petrus Gassendi, Opera Omnia, Band I, Syntagma Philosophicum (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstat, 1964).

    Google Scholar 

  40. David J. Furley, Two Studies in the Greek Atomists (Princeton 1967) 24. The sentence is from Furley’s translation of Epicurus’s Letter to Herodotus. Furley’s treatment of the use of analogy in the atomic theory of Epicurus is important and throws light on Gassendi’s though.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Gassendi op. cir., Syntagma, caput VII, 273 and 279.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Gassendi, caput VII, 280–282.

    Google Scholar 

  43. J.E. McGuire and P. M. Rattansi, ‘Newton and the “Pipes of Pan”‘, Notes & Records of the Royal Society 21 (1966), 108–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. MS. U. L. C. Add. 3965. 6. Fiolo 270r: ‘Atomos vero corpora solida esse voluerunt et figuris varÿs praedita, non mathematice sed physice tantum indivisibilia. Nam et atomum unumquemque ex pertibus innumeris minoribus constare sed quae non ex conventu conciliatae sunt, at arcte et sine poris et intestitÿs ab aeterno stipatae et adeo condensatae et in solidum compactae ut in solidum compactae ut nullis Naturae viribus ab invicem avelli et separari possinit. Quae ex atomorum congressu conflantur iterum dividi posse et in atomos eodem resolvi propterea quod atomi non in solidum congrediantur sed se mutuo in puncto tantum mathematico contingant spatÿs reliquis inter se vacuis relictus: sed atomos ipsos ob soliditatem et plenum partium contactum ac densitatem summam nec dividi posse nec alteri nec ulla ratione comminui nec augmentum unquam sumere sed immutabilia rerum semina in aeternum manere, et inde fieri ut rerum species perpetuo conserventur.’

    Google Scholar 

  45. Works of the Honoruable Robert Boyle, ed. Thomas Birch (London, 1744), vol. II. Boyle states in his prefacee that he had formed his opinions before reading Gassendi.

    Google Scholar 

  46. See also Walter Charleton, Physiologia: Epicuro-Gassendo-Charttoniana: or a Fabrick of Science Natural, upon the Hypothesis of Atoms (London, 1654).

    Google Scholar 

  47. Boyle, Physiologia: Epicuro-Gassendo-Charttoniana: or a Fabrick of Science Natural, upon the Hypothesis of Atoms (London, 1654)., note 22, vol. II, 474.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Boyle, Physiologia: Epicuro-Gassendo-Charttoniana: or a Fabrick of Science Natural, upon the Hypothesis of Atoms (London, 1654), 460.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Boyle, Physiologia: Epicuro-Gassendo-Charttoniana: or a Fabrick of Science Natural, upon the Hypothesis of Atoms (London, 1654)., 460.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Boyle, Physiologia: Epicuro-Gassendo-Charttoniana: or a Fabrick of Science Natural, upon the Hypothesis of Atoms (London, 1654)., 465.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Boyle, Physiologia: Epicuro-Gassendo-Charttoniana: or a Fabrick of Science Natural, upon the Hypothesis of Atoms (London, 1654) 466.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Boyle, Physiologia: Epicuro-Gassendo-Charttoniana: or a Fabrick of Science Natural, upon the Hypothesis of Atoms (London, 1654)., vol. IV, 312.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Italics mine. Sir Isaac Newton, Opticks or a Treatise of the Reflections, Refractions, Inflections & Colours of Light (based on the fourth edition, London, 1730, Dover Publications, 1952), 400.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Sir Isaac Newton, Opticks or a Treatise of the Reflections, Refractions, Inflections & Colours of Light (based on the fourth edition, London, 1730, Dover Publications, 1952) 352.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Sir Isaac Newton, Opticks or a Treatise of the Reflections, Refractions, Inflections & Colours of Light (based on the fourth edition, London, 1730, Dover Publications, 1952) 254–269.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Sir Isaac Newton, Opticks or a Treatise of the Reflections, Refractions, Inflections & Colours of Light (based on the fourth edition, London, 1730, Dover Publications, 1952) 255.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Sir Isaac Newton, Opticks or a Treatise of the Reflections, Refractions, Inflections & Colours of Light (based on the fourth edition, London, 1730, Dover Publications, 1952) 262. Henry Power expresses the same conception: ‘The Doctrine of Effiuxions, their penetrating Natures, their invisible paths, and unsuspected effects, are very considerable, for several Effusions there may be from diverse other Bodies, which invisibly act their parts at any time and perhaps through any Medium: a part of Philosophy but yet in discovery, and will, I fear, prove the Last Leaf to be turned over in the Book of Nature.’ (Experimental Philosophy, 58.) Power’s last sentence is taken directly from Sir Thomas Browne, Pseudodoxia Epidemica, edited by Charles Saye (London 1904), 218–219. It must be noted however, that like many of their contemporaries, Power and Browne were never entirely unambiguous about observigg atoms in principle.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Sir Isaac Newton, Opticks or a Treatise of the Reflections, Refractions, Inflections & Colours of Light (based on the fourth edition, London, 1730, Dover Publications, 1952) 340

    Google Scholar 

  59. This phrase is employed by Newton repeatedly in his work. The greatest and most perceptive of Newton’s disciples. Colin Maclaurin in his An Account of Sir Isaac Newton’s Philosophical Discoveries, referring to this Newtonian conception as used in the Opticks with respect to the ‘more hidden parts of nature’ observes: ‘he endeavours to judge of them [causes], by analogy, from what he had found in the greater motions of the system; a way of reasoning that is agreeable to the harmony of things, and to the old maxim ascribed by Hermes, and approved by the observation and judgement of the best philosophers. “That what passes in the heavens above is similar and analogous to what passes on earth below”‘; op. cit., note 9, 22. As we shall see, this observation accurately reflects the spirit of the third rule.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Joseph Edleston, Correspondence of Sir Isaac Newton and Professor Cotes (London, 1850), 155. The Scholium Generale of the second edition of the Principia Mathematica Philosophia Naturalis (Cambridge, 1713) reads: ‘In hac Philosophia Propositiones deducuntur ex Phaenomenis, & redduntur generales per Inductionem’ (484).

    Google Scholar 

  61. He read Johannes Magirus, Physiologiae Peripateticae Libri Sex cum Commentaris (Cantabrigiae 1642)

    Google Scholar 

  62. Daniel Stahl, Axiomata Philosophica sub Titulis XX Comprehensa (London, 1652).

    Google Scholar 

  63. See J. E. McGuire and Martin Tamny, Certain Philosophical Questions: Newton’s Trinity Notebook (Cambridge University Press, 1983), 3–25

    Google Scholar 

  64. Richard S. Westfall, ‘The Foundations of Newton’s Philosophy of Nature’, British Journal for the History of Science 1 (1962) 172. Newton probably also read Robert Sanderson’s Logic.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  65. See G. L. Huxley, ‘Two Newtonian Studies’, Harvard Library Bulletin 13 (1959), 348–361. In any event coaching in traditional logic was an essential part of the curriculum in Newton’s day.

    Google Scholar 

  66. For contexts in which Newton uses this term, see letter to Cotes, op. cit., note 41, 155 and 156, and the Scholium Generale, Principia (1713), 484.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Philosophy, Science and Sense Perception, 77. Thinkers such as Newton and Descarts, though their philosophies differ in many respects, were concerned more with the way principles are established, and less with ‘verifying’ them or ascertaining their predictive powers. The Newtonians, however, pointed out that Newton’s gravitational theory predicted things not known before, and that its explanatory power covered phenomena hitherto unrelated.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Principia, op. cit., note 39, 484. In the preface to the first edition Newton uses this expression. Newton’s use of this verb will be discussed fully in section III below.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Correspondence of Isaac Newton, ed. H. W. Turnbull (London, 1961), vol. I, 209 (letter dated 6 July 1672). For Cotes, Correspondence of Newton and Cotes, 155 and 156.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Isaac Newton, The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, translated by Benjamin Motte (London, 1729), vol. II, 204.

    Google Scholar 

  71. For a full discussion of these early drafts of the Rule, see I. Bernard Cohen’s ‘Hypotheses in Newton’s Philosophy’, Physis Rivista Internazionale di Storia della Scienza 8 (1966), 163–184, and Chapters 6 and 7.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Vincent Wing, Astronomia Britannia (London, 1669). Trinity College Library, N. Q. 18.36.

    Google Scholar 

  73. U.L.C. Add. 4004, Folio 15r: ‘Ax: 100. Every thing doth naturally perserve in yt state in wch it is unlesse it bee interrupted by some externall cause, hence axiome 1st, & 2d, & 3d. A body once moved will always keep ye same celerity, quantity & determination of its motion.’

    Google Scholar 

  74. John Herivel, The Background to Newton’s PRINCIPIA: A Study of Newton’s Dynamical Researches in the years 1664–84 (Oxford, 1965), 55–64.

    Google Scholar 

  75. John Herivel, The Background to Newton’s PRINCIPIA: A Study of Newton’s Dynamical Researches in the years 1664–84 , 9–13. In the early propositions of Book I, Principia, Newton operates mathematically with the tangential and inertial components as if they were the same, though he clearly recognized that they are conceptually distinct.

    Google Scholar 

  76. For a somewhat different approach to the problems just discussed see Derek T. Whiteside ‘Newtons’s Early Thoughts on Planetary Motion: A Fresh Look’, The British Journal for the History of Science 2 (1964), 117–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  77. John Herivel’s reply, ‘Newton’s First Solution to the Problem of Kepler Motion’, BJHS 2 (1964–65), 350–351. Both scholars tend to under estimate the ontological presuppositions characterized above, which provided the framework for Newton’s mathematical analysis of motion.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  78. N.Q. 16.200, Trinity College Library. For an analysis of this draft see Chapter 6; see also section III of the present chapter.

    Google Scholar 

  79. John Passmore, Philosophical Reasoning (London, 1961), 38

    Google Scholar 

  80. Frank E. Manuel, Isaac Newton, Historian (Cambridge, 1963), 44.

    Google Scholar 

  81. For a discussion of these thinkers see A. A. Luce, Berkeley and Malebranche (London 1934)

    Google Scholar 

  82. George Berkeley, Philosophical Commentaries, ed. A. A. Luce, note to entry 358, 388; Richard H. Popkin, ‘Berkeley and Pyrrhonism’, The Review of Metaphysics 5 (1951), 223–246

    Google Scholar 

  83. Richard H. Popkin, ‘Leibniz and the French Sceptics’, Revue Internationale de Philosophic, nos. 76–77 (1966), 228–247

    Google Scholar 

  84. Richard A. Watson, ‘The Breakdown of Cartesian Metaphysics’, Journal of the History of Philosophy I (1963), 177–197

    Google Scholar 

  85. Harry M. Bracken, ‘Berkeley and Malebranche on Ideas’, The Modern Schoolman 41 (1963), 1–15

    Google Scholar 

  86. Anita Dunlevy Fritz ‘Malebranche and the Immaterialism of Berkeley’, Review of Metaphysics 3 (1949–50), 59–80

    Google Scholar 

  87. Richard A. Watson, The Downfall of Cartesianism 1673–1717: a Study of Epistemological Issues in Late 17th-Century Cartesianism (Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1966). The main early anti-Cartesian writers in France were: Simon Foucher, Critique de la vérité où l’on examine en même-terms une partie des principes de M r Descartes (Paris, 1675); P. D. Hueti, Censura Philosophiae Cartesianae (Editio Quarta aucta et emendata, Paris, 1694); J. B. du Hamel Astronomia Physicae (Paris 1660)

    Google Scholar 

  88. Nicolas Malebranche, De la Recherche de la Vérité, ed. Genevieve Lewis (Paris, 1945), Eclaircissement vie: ‘Qu’il est très difficile de prouver qu’il y a des Corps’, 24–33.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Nicolas Malebranche, Dialogues on Metaphysics and on Religion, translated by Morris Ginsberg (London, 1923), 71–75, 167–168.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Beatrice K. Rome, The Philosophy of Malebranche (Chicago, 1963), chapter VI.

    Google Scholar 

  91. René Descartes, Philosophical Writings, translated and edited by G. E. M. Anscombe and P. T. Geach (London, 1966), 202. The Principles of Philosophy, from Latin text of 1644. See also (Œuvres de Descartes, edited by Charles Adam and Paul Tannery, vol. VIII, Pars Secunda, CCI, 324.

    Google Scholar 

  92. From Descartes, Philosophical Writings, 202.

    Google Scholar 

  93. For an interesting critique of Descartes’s position see Anthony Kenny, Descartes: A Study of Philosophy (Random House, 1968), 214.

    Google Scholar 

  94. See Henry More, A Collection of Several Philosophical Writings (London, 1712), 61–113.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Descartes, Philosophical Writings, 235.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Descartes, Philosophical Writings,236. Descartes is quit unambiguous about the unity of matte: ‘I do not see how any reasonable man can deny the great advantage of forming ideas about microscopic events (in minutis corpusculis), which elude our senses by their mere minuteness, on the pattern of sensibly observed macroscopic events (in magnis corporibus), instead of bringing into our explanation some new conception of things wholly dissimilar to sensible objects’ (236).

    Google Scholar 

  97. Alan Gewirth, ‘Clarness and Distinctness in Descartes’ in Descartes: a Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Willis Doney (Notre Dame, 1968), 264–277, and Richard Watson, op. cit., note 58 ‘The Breakdown of Cartesian Metaphysics’, 181–184.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Descartes, Philosophical Writings, 208.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Acta Eruditorum, April 1695, 145–157. Gottfried William Leibniz, Philosophical Papers and Letters, translated and edited by Leroy E. Loemker (Chicago, 1956), vol. II, 845, letter to Burcher de Voider (1643–1709) of 23 June 1699. De Voider, among other things, forced Leibniz to formulate some of his clearest statements on substance and the distinction between body and non-extended forces of which it was composed. See also Leibniz’s Specimen Dynamicum of 1695 (Philosophical Papers and Letters, vol. II, 711–738) and On Nature Itself (Ibid., 808–825).

    Google Scholar 

  100. For a discussion of this point with reference to the concept of phaenomena bene fundata see H. W. B. Joseph, Lectures on the Philosophy of Leibniz (Oxford, 1949), chapter 5. The point is clearly made by Leibniz in the following passage: ‘It is to be observed that matter, taken as a complete being is nothing but a collection or what results from it, and that every real collection presupposes simple substances or real unities, and when we consider further what belongs to the nature of these real unities, i.e. perception and its consequences, we are transferred, so to speak, into another world, that is, into the intelligible world of substances, whereas before we were only among the phenomena of the senses’; New Essays concerning Human Understanding, translated by A. G. Langley (New York and London, 1896), 428. Also the following passage: ‘But strictly speaking matter is nothing but a phenomenon founded in things like the rainbow or the parhelion, and all reality belongs only to unities’;

    Google Scholar 

  101. C. J. Gerhard, Die Philosophischen Schriften yon G. W. Leibniz (Berlin, 1875–90), vol. II, 268.

    Google Scholar 

  102. For a classic discussion of this aspect of Leibniz’s thought see Leibniz: the Monadology transaated by Robert Latta (Oxford, 1898), 21–39.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Philosophical Papers and Letters, vol. II, 845.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Philosophical Papers and Letters, p. 838. For a discussion of Leibniz’s theory of matter, see Bertrand Russell, A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz (Cambridge 1900), chapters VII and VIII.

    Google Scholar 

  105. I have used the Torino edition of 1958 edited by Paolo Broinghiar, with a preface by Adriano Carugo and Ludovico Geymonat. The Discorsi was first published in 1638. See also Opere, ed. naz., vol. VIII, 86

    Google Scholar 

  106. The translation is mainly based on Dialogues concerning Two New Sciences, translated by Henry Crew and Alfonso De Salvo (New York, Dover Publications, n. d.), 40–41. I have also consulted Thomas Salisbury’s translation, Mathematical Discourese and Demonstrations touching Two New Sciences (London, 1665), 33. I am grateful to James MacLachlan of the University of Toronto for calling my attention to this passage.

    Google Scholar 

  107. There is a discussion of this by Ernest Goldbeck: ‘Galileis Atomisiik und ihre Quellen’, Biblioteca Mathematica Zeitschrift für Geschichte der mathematischen Wissenschaften, series 3 (Leipzig, 1902), 84–102. The Galilean discussion of ‘atoms’ began in his Discorso intorso alle case che stanno in su l’acqua o che in quella si muovono (Florence, 1612). See Opere, vol. IV. The contribution of matter is discussed there almost as an afterthought.

    Google Scholar 

  108. U. L. C. Add. 4005.15 Folio 81r-v. For an analysis of this draft see Chapter 6. See Draft 2 in

    Google Scholar 

  109. Alexander Koyré, ‘Pour une Edition Critique des Œuvres de Newton’, Revue d’Histoire des Sciences 8 (1955), 19–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  110. In his Wiles Lectures, delivered in Belfast, May 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (London, 1687), p. 411. Hypothesis II was changed slightly in the third edition; see Alexander Koyré, Newtonian Studies (London, 1965), 265–266.

    Google Scholar 

  112. Isaac Newton, Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematics (London, 1726), 389.

    Google Scholar 

  113. A. Rupert Hall and Marie Boas Hall, Unpublished Scientific Papers of Isaac Newton (Cambridge, 1962), 293.

    Google Scholar 

  114. ‘Regulam voco Propositionem ominem quae ex Phaenomenss per argumentum Inductionss (stabilitur) colligitur & cum ysdem congruit.’ U. L. C. Add. 3965.13 Folio 420r.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Isaac Newton, Optice: sire de Reflexionibus, Refractionibus, Inflexionibus & Coloribus Lucis (London 1706), 171. A similar distinction between and a use of, these verbs is found in Descartes’s Regulae which Newton probably knew. In Rule XII we find him saying while dis cussing the properties of magnets: ‘Sed insuper ut quaestio sit perfecta, volumus illam omnimo determinari, adeo ut nihil amplius quaeratur, quam id quod deduci potest ex datis.’ (Italics mine.) Œuvres de Descartes, edited by Charles Adam and Paul Tannery (Paris, 1908), vol. X, 431. Also in Rule XII we find: ‘ . primo diligenter colligit illa omnia quae de hoc lapide habere potest experimenta, ex quibus deinde deducere conatur qualis necessaria sit naturam simplicium mixtura ad omnes iilos ’. There is no doubt that there are abundant scholastic precedents for this usage. Like Newton, Descartes is clearly not using ‘deduce’ in the sense of ‘formally deduce’. It is not unlikely that Newton was influenced by Descartes, since both were more concerned with the mode of establishing principles rather than with their explictt verification. A similar observation has been made of Galileo with respect to establishing principles by E. McMullin. See his Introduction in Galileo, Man of Science (Basic Books, New York, 1967), 13.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Opticks (1730), 211.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Optice (1706), 176.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Correspondence, vol. I, 209.

    Google Scholar 

  119. U. L. C. Add. 3970, Folio 479r-v.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Newton, Mathematical Principles (1729), 392.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Op. cit., note 50, 27. This was written just prior to the first version of Book I of the Principia. In February 1692–93 he used the same form of words in writing to Bentley in English: ‘That Gravity should be innate, inherent and essential to Mattte ’. There is no evidence that Newton ever reconsidered his view that vis insita was contrary to gravity in this respect. Quotation from the Bentley letter is from I. Bernard Cohen, Isaac Newton’s Papers and Letters on Natural Philosophy (Cambridge, 1958), 302.

    Google Scholar 

  122. U. L. C. Add. 4004 Folio 15r.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Correspondence of Newton and Cotes, 154–155.

    Google Scholar 

  124. U.L.C. Add. 3970.13, Folio 420r. ‘Hypothesin voco opinionem omnem quae nec phaenom-enon est, nec demonstratur, nec ex Phaenomenis per Argumentum Inductionss deducitur.’ On the justification for Newton’s tougher line on hypothesis, see I. Bernard Cohen, ‘Hypotheses in Newton’s Philosophy’, Physis Rivista lnternationale di Storia della Scienza 8 (1966), 165–184. Also see Chapter 7.

    Google Scholar 

  125. R. Boyle Works (1772), vol. IV, 72.

    Google Scholar 

  126. For two excellent discussions of Boyle and Descartes on analogy, transduction, and hypo-theticalism, see Laurens Laudan, ‘The Clock Metaphor and Probabilism: The Impact of Descartes on English Methodolgoical Thought, 1650–65’, Annals of Science 22 (1966, 81–97, and Maurice Mandelbaum, op cit., note 3, chapter II.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Henry Power, Experimental Philosophy, In Three Books: Containing New Experiments Microscopical, Mercurial, Magnetical, in avouchment and Illustration of the now famous Atomical Hypothesis (Introduction by Marie Boas Hall, Johnson Reprint of 1664 Edition, New York and London, 1966). Newton had Power’s book in his library.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Ralph Cudworth, The True Intellectual System of the Universe (London, 1678), 858.

    Google Scholar 

  129. Ralph Cudworth, The True Intellectual System of the Universe (London, 1678),856

    Google Scholar 

  130. Ralph Cudworth, The True Intellectual System of the Universe (London, 1678),, 858–859. Similar arguments are to be found in Henry More’s An Antidote against Atheism, in A Collection of Several Philosophical Writings (London: 1712), 53 and 97.

    Google Scholar 

  131. Hall and Hall, op. cit., note 88, 130–146. I have partially developed this theme in Newton in Chapters 3 and 5.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Op. cit., note 32, and Francis Oakley, ‘Christian Theology and the Newtonian Science: The Rise of the Concept of the Laws of Nature’, Church History30 (1961), 435–436.

    Google Scholar 

  133. Dictionary of National Biography (London, 1888), vol. 18, 271.

    Google Scholar 

  134. Joseph Glanvill, Sadducismus Triumphatus: or a full and plain Evidence concerning Witches and Apparitions, fourth edition (London, 1726). The 1681 edition was a re-edition of Philosophical Considerations touching Witches of 1666, the fourth edition of which in 1668 was entitled A Blow at Modern Sadducism . The quotations used in this paper are unchanged throughout these editions.

    Google Scholar 

  135. Joseph Glanvill, Sadducismus Triumphatus: or a full and plain Evidence concerning Witches and Apparitions, fourth edition (London, 1726, 24. I do not wish to imply that the phrase ‘analogy of Nature’ is original with either Glanvill or Newton. But Glanvill’s is the earliest English use of the phrase known to me. It can no doubt be located in the countless scholastic manuals used in the seventeenth century.

    Google Scholar 

  136. Joseph Glanvill, Sadducismus Triumphatus: or a full and plain Evidence concerning Witches and Apparitions, fourth edition (London, 1726 5.

    Google Scholar 

  137. John Locke, An Essay concerning Human Understanding (London, 1690). The quotations used remain the same in editions published later in Locke’s lifetime.

    Google Scholar 

  138. John W. Yolton, Locke and the Compass of Human Understanding: A Selective Commentary on the ‘Essay’ (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  139. Locke, Essay, 339.

    Google Scholar 

  140. Locke, 3.6.12, p. 213. Surprisingly, Locke scholars have scarcely commented on his adherence to the chain of being. A. S. Pringle-Pattison has a short footnote reference to it in his edition of An Essay concerning Human Understanding (Oxford, 1924), 341–342. What he says follows almost entirely A. C. Fraser’s footnote comment in his edition reproduced by Dover (New York, 1959), vol. II, 380–381. Both fail to see how these ideas provide part of the general framework of Locke’s Essay, and content themselves with saying that they are ‘more comprehensive speculation than is usual with him’, Fraser, op. cit., 380.

    Google Scholar 

  141. Locke., 2.1.15, p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

  142. Locke4.16.12, pp. 339–340.

    Google Scholar 

  143. Locke, 3.6.12, pp. 213–214.

    Google Scholar 

  144. Locke., 3.6.12, pp. 213–214. For a different interpretation of Locke’s use of analogy-based bypotheses, which places emphasis on his ‘hypotheticalism’, see Laurens Laudan, ‘The Nature and Sources of Locke’s Views on Hypotheses’, Journal of the History of Ideas, 27 (1967), 221–223.

    Google Scholar 

  145. George Cheyne, Philosophical Principles of Religion: Natural and Revealed (in two parts, London, 1715), Part I, 50.

    Google Scholar 

  146. See Chapter 5.

    Google Scholar 

  147. Cheyne Philosophical Principles, part II, 46. See also 38–39: ‘A Wise Man performs all his Works in Number, Weight, and Measure, and sure infinite Wisdom, Simplicity, and Unity, must accomplish all it’s Works and with the most Consumate Harmony, Proposition and Regularity, and this in the following parts of this Treattise we shall call the Analogy of Things’. These analogical schema were extended into political and social realms in the 1690s. There is no surer indication of the entrenchment of such reasoning in connection with providentialism as a means of justifying political and social events than the poems of Thomas Shadwell: A Congratulatory Poem on his Highness the Prince of Orange, his coming into England (London, 1689);

    Google Scholar 

  148. John Theophilus Desaguliers: The Newtonian System of the World the Best Model of Government: an Allegorical Poem (London, 1728). Nehemiah Grew in his Cosmologia Sacra: or a Discourse of the Universe as it is the Creature and Kingdom of God (London, 1701) also connects nature, religion, government and society by the use of analogy and Providnntialism. The New England Divine Jonathan Edwards writing early in the eighteenth century in developing his theory of reality from Newton’s doctrine of gravitation and the Cambridge Platonist doctrines of God and space, makes analogical connections which echo Cheyne. See his Dissertation on the End For which God Created the World, in Works (New York, 1881), vol. II, 201f. In Images and Shadows of Divine Things (Yale, 1948), the moral and religious worlds are reflected in the physical world. He holds like Cheyne that just as the planets are attracted to the sun so minds are attracted to God by ‘moral gravity’ or love.

    Google Scholar 

  149. Chyne Philosophical Principles, part I, 42.

    Google Scholar 

  150. Chyne Philosophical Principles., part II, A3.

    Google Scholar 

  151. Chyne Philosophical Principles., part I, 36.

    Google Scholar 

  152. Chyne Philosophical Principles. part II, 103–104. For evidence of Cheyne’s cautious attitude towards analogical reasoning see An Essay on Regimen (London, 1740), 226 Analogy provides only ‘dark hints’ and by it ‘we may very readily err in the details, and in the Eliciting and Application of a particular case; but not so readily in the general Law’. The chain of being is discussed by Maclaurin, Account, 15–19, in Lockean fashion as background to his discussion of Newton’s experimental philosophy: ‘ For tho’ all sorts and degrees are equally the objects of philosophical speculation; yet it is from those which are proportional to sense that a philosopher must set out in his enquiries, ascending or descending afterwards as his pursuits may require’ (18). The most elaborate use of the doctrine is found in Berkeley’s Siris in The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, ed. A. A. Luce and T. E. Jessop (Edinburgh, 1953), vol. V.

    Google Scholar 

  153. Sir Isaac Newton, The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, trans. Benjamin Motte (London, 1729), vol. II, 203.

    Google Scholar 

  154. Correspondence, vol. I, 376.

    Google Scholar 

  155. Opticks (1730), 125.

    Google Scholar 

  156. Opticks (1730), , Query 31, 376.

    Google Scholar 

  157. Mathematical Principles (1729), vol. II, 202. Rule I of the third Book which states: ‘We are to admit no more causes of natural things than such as are both true and sufficient to explain their appearances.’

    Google Scholar 

  158. See Chapter 7. See also David Kubrin, ‘Newton and the Cyclical Cosmos: Providence and the Mechanical Philosophy,’ J. H. I. 27 (1967), 326–346.

    Google Scholar 

  159. Hall and Hall, op. cit., note 86, 341. This passage is from an intended conclusion for the first edition of the Principia. It is by no means isolated; a similar passage was added to the closing paragraph of the third Book of the 1713 Principia. For an analysis of this and related materials see Chapter 7. In Les Métèores, Discours VII, Œuvres, vol. VVI, 321, Descartesl beginning with exhalations, arrives by a series of transmutations at ‘du sang, ou les sauterelles ou choses semblables’.

    Google Scholar 

  160. See Chapter 5. Though Newton had a notion of the conservation of matter, with respect to momentum it was not independent of active principles. The former had to be periodicalyy ‘recruited’. The sensibility of Newton’s thought regarding conservation seems to hark back to the ‘biological’ thought of such thinkers as Power and Glisson who moved from the material to the immaterial, partly because they had no conscious notion of a ‘state’ of matter. With respect to both matter and motion Robert Hooke had a relatively clear notion of conservation: ‘Both these Powers I take to be the immediate Product of the Omnipotent Creato, and immutable in themselve, without a like command of the same Power; and always to act in a regular and Uniform Geometrical or Mechanical Method; which Method by diligent Observation and curious Scrutiny may by natural and artifical Means be discovered, and, as I conceive, reduced under certain Rules, and Geometrically demonstrated.’ Robert Hooke, Postumous Works (London, 1705), 73. Hooke derived his ideas on conservation from Genesis, pp. 97, 172, 175. For him matter and motion are appearances of one ‘POWER’.

    Google Scholar 

  161. Johs. Lohne, ‘Newton’s Proof of the Sine Law and his Mathematicll Principles of Colors’, Archive for the History of Exact Sciences I (1961), 393.

    Google Scholar 

  162. Correspondence, vol. I, 366

    Google Scholar 

  163. Lohne, op. cit., 393.

    Google Scholar 

  164. See Chanter 7.

    Google Scholar 

  165. Is. Newton, Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (London, 1687), 411. Translation mine.

    Google Scholar 

  166. As it stands the significance of the sentence is not easily established; however in conjunction with the first ‘Hypoth IV’, namely, ‘Things which agree as to all their known qualities with other kinds of things are not to be considered as new kinds of things’, we may be able to clarify what Newton was attempting to say. Both sentences seem to refer to analogical reasoning. Thus the ‘known qualities’ of matter, among others, includes extension impenetrabllity, etc., which comprise the known positive analogy. But imperceptible particles operate on the sensory organs, i.e. sight, smells, sounds, etc.: thus they are analogous with perceptible bodies in that they are solid. Given the causal theory of perception generally accepted in his time, through this analogy of effect, Newton could claim to have good grounds for supposing that imperceptible particles have at least other known essential qualities of gross bodies. Therefore they are ‘not to be considered as new kinds of things’. This sort of reasoning was employed by Newton in his general argument for the universalizing of gravitation. Similar presuppositioss for the argument by analogy from perceptible things is found in Lucretiusss De Rerum Natura, Book I, lines 599–631: see translation by Cyril Bailey (Oxford, 1924), 46–48. This was a source that Newton knew well. Thus this line of reasoning places Newton’s thought regarding tran-scategorical inference closer to that of Epicurus and Gassend:: see section I above. Nevertheless, this particular type of analogical reasoning would ultimately be justified by Newton through the general metaphysicll of analogy described in the last two sections of this paper.

    Google Scholar 

  167. Hall and Hall, op. cit., note 86, 138–140, and Newton’s intended letter for Hartsoeker of May 1712, U. L. C. Add. 3965.17 fol. 257r-v. Part of this is published in Chapter 5. The similarity of Newton’s views regarding ‘immaterial’ matter as an entity dependent upon God is remarkably similar to those of Malebranche, op. cit., note 57. For a different view of the unity and inter-dependenee of natural objects in relation to Providence, see Locke’s Essay, 4.6.11.

    Google Scholar 

  168. Gowin Knight, An attempt to demonstrate that all the Phaenomena in Nature may be explained by two simple active Principles Attraction and Repulsion (London, 1748), Coroll. II, Prop. VII, p. 7. Corollary I states that: ‘the Existence, Extension, Impenetrability, Mobility, and vis inertiae of matter, are apparently the immediate Effects of God’s will’ (7).

    Google Scholar 

  169. Philosophy, Science and Sense Perception, 78. Italics in original.

    Google Scholar 

  170. Philosophy, Science and Sense Perception, 87. Italics in original.

    Google Scholar 

  171. Philosophy, Science and Sense Perception, 88.

    Google Scholar 

  172. Alexander Koyré and I. Bernard Cohen, ‘Newton and the Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence’, Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Sciences 15 (1962), 113.

    Google Scholar 

  173. Mathematical Principles (1729), vol. II, 204.

    Google Scholar 

  174. Principia (1713), praefecto.

    Google Scholar 

  175. Correspondence of Newton and Cotes, 158–159.

    Google Scholar 

  176. Edward Stillingfleet, Origenes Sacrae, or a Rational Account of the Grounds of Christian Faith (London, 1680), 425. (The first edition was published in 1662).

    Google Scholar 

  177. Edward Stillingfleet, Origenes Sacrae, or a Rational Account of the Grounds of Christian Faith (London, 1680), 425, 425

    Google Scholar 

  178. But he also conceived micro-particles as having properties different from gross bodies. There is also a strong possibility that Newton may have conceived the particles of his later aethereal medium to be noninertial. In all three editions of the Principia, definition I, which is concerned with the notion of the quantity of matter (mass), seems to contrast ponderable bodies with the aether; for Newton says that he has ‘no regard in this place to a medium, if any such there is, that freely pervades the interstices between the parts of bodies’. This conjecture is strengthened by Newton’s observation in the intended letter to Hartsoeker (op. cit., note 138) of ‘a power seated in (an immaterial) a substance in wch bodies move & flote without resistence & which has therefore no vis inerttae ’. There is furthermore a curious inconsistency in Newton’s thought, displayed not only in the difference between these speculations and the third rule, but in the rule itself. In the remarks to the rule he speaks of ‘The extension, hardness, impenetrability, and vis inertiae of the whole’, resulting ‘from the extension, hardness, impenetrability, mobility and vis inertiae of the parts: and thence we conclude the least particles of all bodies to be all extended, and hard, and impenetrable, and moveable, and endow’d with their vires inertiae’. Not only does this commit the fallacy of composition, but the reasoning is evidently circular since the qualities of bodies are held to be known through experience alone. In any event, the possibiltty of micro-entities different from gross bodies occurred to Newton as early as 1663 in his Questiones quaedam Philosophiae (U. L. C. Add. 3996). He states there four possible positons ‘Off yt first mater’, namely: ‘Whither it be mathematicall points: or Mathematicall points & parts: or a simple entity before division indistinct: or individuals i.e. Attomes’ (Folio 88r). Newton rejects the other positions and argues for Gassendist-like atoms, which he associates with Henry More’s notion of ‘indiscerpible’ parts (Folio 89).

    Google Scholar 

  179. U.L.C. Add. 3970. Fol. 338r.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1995 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

McGuire, J.E. (1995). Atoms and the ‘Analogy of Nature’: Newton’s Third Rule of Philosophizing. In: Tradition and Innovation. The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol 56. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-1581-7_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-1581-7_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7207-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-1581-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics