Skip to main content

Speaker Plans, Linguistic Contexts, and Indirect Speech Acts

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Studies in Cognitive Systems ((COGS,volume 5))

Abstract

Some indirect speech acts are unrelated to the semantic meaning of the sentence uttered, how ever widely we construe “semantic meaning”. Searle gives this example:

  1. A:

    Let’s go to the movies tonight.

  2. B:

    I have to study for an exam.

    (Searle, Indirect Speech Acts [Searle75])

The sentence “I have to study for an exam” is not lexically tied to turning down proposals to go to the movies. There is no sense in which this is part of its meaning. However, in this context B uses it to do just this.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  • Allen, J. and C. Perrault. “Analysing intentions in utterances,” Artificial Intelligence 15, 143–178, 1980.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, J. “Recognizing intentions from natural language utterances,” Computational Models of Discourse, M. Brady and R. Berwick, eds., pp. 108–166, Cambridge University Press, 1983.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N. “Conditional assertion and restricted uantification,” Nous IV, pp. 1–13, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N. and T. Steel. The Logic of Questions and Answers, Yale Press, 1976.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brand, M. “Intentional action and plans,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy X, P. French, et al., eds., Minnesota University Press, 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, P. and C. Perrault. “Elements of a plan based theory of speech acts,” Cognitive Science 3, pp 177–212, 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, P. and H. Levesque. “Speech acts and the recognition of shared plans,” Proceedings of the Third Biennial Conference of the Canadian Society for Computational Studies of Intelligence, pp. 263 271, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazdar, G. “Speech act assignment,” Elements of Discourse Understanding, A. Joshi, B. Webber, I. Sag, eds., Cambridge University Press, pp. 64–83, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. “Meaning,” Philosophical Review 66, pp. 377–388, 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. “Logic and conversation” Syntax and Semantics 3: Speech Acts, P. Cole and J. Morgan, eds., Academic Press, pp. 41–58, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grosz, B. and C. Sidner. “Attention, intention, and the structure of discourse,” Computational Linguistics 12, pp. 175–204, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C. “Mathematical models of dialogue,” Theoria 37, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hinkleman, E. “A plan-based approach to conversational implicature,” unpublished.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbs, J. “Towards an understanding of coherence in dialogue,” Strategies for Natural Language Processing, W. Lehnert and M. Ringle, eds., Lawrence Erlbaum Associate, pp. 223–243, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ilobbs, J. “On the coherence and structure of discourse,” The Structure of Discourse, L. Polanyi, ed., Ablex, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kautz, H. “A Formal theory of plan recognition,” Ph.D. thesis, University of Rochester, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. Pragmatics, Cambridge University Press, 1983.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. “Storekeeping in a language game,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 8, pp. 339–359, 1979.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Litman, D. “Linguistic coherence: a plan-based alternative,” Coling 86, pp. 215–223, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • Litman, D. and J. Allen. “A plan recognition model for subdialogues in conversation,” Cognitive Science 11, pp. 163–200, 1987.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perrault, C. and J. Allen. “A plan based analysis of indirect speech acts,” Computational Linguistics 6,pp. 167–182, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, L., ed., The Structure of Discourse,Ablex, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. Indirect speech acts, Syntax and Semantics 3: Speech Acts, P. Cole and J. Morgan, Academic Press, pp. 59–82, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. “Presuppositions,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 2, pp. 447–457, 1973.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. “Pragmatic presuppostions,” Semantics and Philosophy, M. Munitz and P. Unger, eds., Academic Press, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomason, R. Accommodation, Conversational Planning, and Implicature, (draft), unpublished.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1990 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

McCafferty, A. (1990). Speaker Plans, Linguistic Contexts, and Indirect Speech Acts. In: Kyburg, H.E., Loui, R.P., Carlson, G.N. (eds) Knowledge Representation and Defeasible Reasoning. Studies in Cognitive Systems, vol 5. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-0553-5_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-0553-5_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-6736-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-0553-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics