Skip to main content

Boolean-Valued Sets as Vague Sets

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Vague Objects and Vague Identity

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 33))

Abstract

The standard fuzzy logic and fuzzy set theory are degree-functional and thus susceptible to the problem of penumbral connections. This chapter attempts to radically revise them in order to remove this feature. Whereas the original theory assigns any real number in [0,1] to a proposition or set membership, the revised theory, called Boolean-valued set theory, assigns a value in a Boolean lattice structure B = ⟨D,∧,∨,¬,0,1⟩; consequently, “p or not-p” will receive value 1 and “p and not-p” will receive value 0 for any proposition p in Boolean-valued set theory. The resulting view of vague sets is essentially that depicted in Boolean-valued models of ZFC set theory introduced by Scott and Solovay. On this view, propositions and set membership have many values between 0 and 1, but the values are Boolean-structured and only partially ordered, so we cannot turn them into meaningful numerical degrees in [0,1]. The identity relation between two sets is also given various values, depending on the values of the membership relations involving the two sets; so this theory also endorses vague identity among sets.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It should be emphasized, however, that semantic supervaluationism already accepts precisified worlds, whether they are called “precisified worlds” or “precisifications.” A version of it that employs the transworld identity theory of individuals also accepts the existence of trans-precisificational objects. The only difference between this version of semantic supervaluationism and ontic supervaluationism I advocate is whether precisifications differ only with respect to semantic facts (i.e., what word refers to which precise object) or also with respect to non-semantic facts (i.e., what trans-precisificational object coincides with which precise object). Thus, the charge often made against my brand of ontic supervaluationism that it assumes a larger ontology than semantic supervaluationism, is totally off the mark.

  2. 2.

    An infinite-valued logic called standard Łukasiewicz logic L 1 (or \( {L}_{{\mathrm{\aleph}}_1}\! \)) is often used as the basis of fuzzy logic. Klir and Yuan (1995, Chap. 8) provides a useful account of fuzzy logic and its connection to fuzzy set theory.

  3. 3.

    See Smith (2008a) for more details about this point.

  4. 4.

    Klir and Yuan (1995) is a standard textbook of fuzzy logic and set theory. Goguen (1969), Lakoff (1973), and Machina (1976) use modified versions of fuzzy set theory in their philosophical accounts of vagueness. Smith (2008a) is a more recent attempt to defend fuzzy set theory.

  5. 5.

    Experimental support of this claim is given in, e.g., Bonini et al. (1999), Alxatib and Pelletier (2011), and Serchuk et al. (2011).

  6. 6.

    At the end of the day, I think we should give up this assumption, as I shall argue in the final section. It is a reasonable assumption, however, and whether we should give it up at the end of the day or not really does not affect the current argument. The argument holds up insofar as the value of the disjunction is not constant at the center, right end, and left end.

  7. 7.

    Another possible way to satisfy the desiderata is Edgington’s (1992, 1997). Her idea is to use the standard probability calculus to measure the degree of vagueness; that is,

    $$ \begin{array}{c}{\left [\kern-0.15em[ \neg p\right ]\kern-0.15em] }_V=1-\left [\kern-0.15em[ p\right ]\kern-0.15em] {}_V;\\ {}{\left [\kern-0.15em[ p\wedge q\right ]\kern-0.15em] }_V=\left [\kern-0.15em[ p\right ]\kern-0.15em] {}_V\times \left [\kern-0.15em[ q\kern0.5em \mathrm{given}\kern0.5em p\right ]\kern-0.15em] {}_V;\\ {}{\left [\kern-0.15em[ p\vee q\right ]\kern-0.15em] }_V=\left [\kern-0.15em[ p\right ]\kern-0.15em] {}_V+\left [\kern-0.15em[ q\right ]\kern-0.15em] {}_V-\left [\kern-0.15em[ p\wedge q\right ]\kern-0.15em] {}_V.\end{array} $$

    Edgington contends that just as credence and objective chance may share the same logic even though they are conceptually different (cf. Lewis 1980), the degrees of truth (or what she calls “verity”) pertaining to vagueness may also follow the same logic even though it is different from either credence or objective chance. Discussion of Edgington’s view is beyond the scope of this paper.

  8. 8.

    For the sake of simplicity we shall ignore in this paper the universal and existential quantifiers in the object language. To include those quantifiers, we have to require that the relevant Boolean lattice B be complete. Generally, a complete lattice G is a lattice that has the glb and lub for any subset of D G whether it is finite or infinite. Then we can have

    $$ \begin{array}{c}{\left [\kern-0.15em[ \forall x\;\phi (x)\right ]\kern-0.15em] }_B=\underset{a\in U}{\wedge }{\left [\kern-0.15em[ \phi (a)\right ]\kern-0.15em] }_B;\\ {}{\left [\kern-0.15em[ \exists x\;\phi (x)\right ]\kern-0.15em] }_B=\underset{a\in U}{\vee }{\left [\kern-0.15em[ \phi (a)\right ]\kern-0.15em] }_B.\end{array} $$
  9. 9.

    It’s not as if there is absolutely no way of assigning numbers between 0 and 1 that conforms to the ordering relation ≤. For instance, Zhang (1982) came up with one way, in which the paths in the lattice structure and the locations in the paths are given binary interpretations, which are then translated into real numbers in [0,1]. However, on Zhang’s assignment, if, for instance, 〚p B  = 5/8 and 〚q B  = 3/8, then even though 〚p B  ∧ ¬p B  = 0 and 〚p B  ∨ ¬p B  = 1, 〚p B  ∧ 〚q B  = 1/8 and 〚p B  ∨ 〚q B  = 7/8. These are hardly the values one would expect or can make sense of. As this example illustrates, while it is possible for us to assign numbers between 0 and 1, such an assignment lacks intuitive meaning.

  10. 10.

    Or, in a multiple-conclusion formulation such as that of the classical sequent calculus,

    $$ \Gamma \vdash \Delta \iff \underset{p\in \Gamma}{\wedge }{\left [\kern-0.15em[ p\right ]\kern-0.15em] }_B\le \underset{q\in \Delta}{\vee }{\left [\kern-0.15em[ q\right ]\kern-0.15em] }_B\kern0.5em \mathrm{for}\ \mathrm{any}\kern0.5em B. $$
  11. 11.

    Needless to say, classical logic can be defined semantically, as the bivalent logic. But, then, classical logic, thus defined, is deductively no different from the logic defined by the general Boolean-valued semantics.

  12. 12.

    Unless you embrace Edgington’s aforementioned view.

  13. 13.

    Williamson (1994) and Keefe (1998, 2000, Chap. 5) also criticize fuzzy set theory for its linear value assignments. Goguen (1969), even though he is generally sympathetic to fuzzy set theory, also considers this feature a shortcoming of the theory and develops a system in which values are only partially ordered. Goguen’s theory is rather different from the present proposal; most importantly, his general framework is not Boolean, though he accepts Boolean structures as special cases. We will not discuss Goguen’s theory in this paper. See Williamson (1994, pp. 131–135) for a brief critical examination of Goguen’s theory and other similar theories.

  14. 14.

    Weatherson’s general framework is similar to this chapter’s, although his main concern is with introducing “≤” (or “<,” “truer than”) in the object language.

  15. 15.

    I would like to thank Richard Zach for pressing this point.

  16. 16.

    As far as I know, Zhang is the first researcher to point out the significant connections between fuzzy set theory and Boolean-valued set theory.

  17. 17.

    One might still contend that = in Boolean-valued set theory is not really identity but something else. (I myself argued in Akiba (2000a, b, 2004) that what is often considered vague identity between vague individuals is not really identity but mere coincidence.) The issue of vague (or indeterminate) identity is without doubt an extremely delicate one. The root problem is that we, collectively, do not seem to have a clear idea of what vague identity ought to be. Still, I am inclined to think that vagueness of = here is as good a candidate of vague identity as anything can be. But a full defense of this claim is beyond the scope of this paper. See Williamson (1996, 2002) and Smith (2008b) for arguments for the unintelligibility and nonexistence of vague identity, and see Akiba (MS) for my defense of vague identity. Thanks to the anonymous reviewer of this chapter for raising this issue.

  18. 18.

    Of course, it may not be, because of quantum indeterminacy, for instance. For quantum indeterminacy, see Darby (2014) and the papers cited therein.

  19. 19.

    I owe much to the anonymous reviewer for seeing this point.

  20. 20.

    I would like to thank the anonymous reviewer of this chapter for valuable comments. His/her comments on the relation between the possible worlds semantics and Boolean-valued semantics were particularly helpful. I also would like to thank for comments Nick Smith, Richard Zach, and the audience at the Society for Exact Philosophy 41st annual meeting, May 24, 2013, Université de Montréal, where a part of this chapter was presented.

References

  • Akiba, K. (2000a). Vagueness as a modality. Philosophical Quarterly, 50, 359–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Akiba, K. (2000b). Identity is simple. American Philosophical Quarterly, 37, 389–404.

    Google Scholar 

  • Akiba, K. (2004). Vagueness in the world. Noûs, 38, 407–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Akiba, K. (MS). A defense of indeterminate distinctness. In preparation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alxatib, S., & Pelletier, F. J. (2011). The psychology of vagueness: Borderline cases and contradictions. Mind and Language, 26, 287–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. (2010). Ontic vagueness: A guide for the perplexed. Noûs, 44, 601–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E., & Williams, J. R. G. (2011). A theory of metaphysical indeterminacy. In K. Bennett & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 6, pp. 103–148). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. L. (2005). Set theory: Boolean-valued models and independence proofs (3rd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press. (1st ed., 1977.)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bonini, N., Osherson, D., Viale, R., & Williamson, T. (1999). On the psychology of vague predicates. Mind and Language, 14, 377–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chow, T. Y. (2008). A beginner’s guide to forcing, version 2. http://arxiv.org/pdf/0712.1320v2.pdf

  • Cohen, P. J. (1966). Set theory and the continuum hypothesis. New York: Benjamin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darby, G. (2014). Vague objects in quantum mechanics? In K. Akiba & A. Abasnezhad (Eds.), Vague objects and vague identity (pp. 69–108). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, D. (1992). Validity, uncertainty and vagueness. Analysis, 52, 193–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, D. (1997). Vagueness by degrees. In R. Keefe & P. Smith (Eds.), Vagueness: A reader (pp. 294–316). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1978). Can there be vague objects? Analysis, 38, 208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1975). Vagueness, truth and logic. Synthese, 30, 265–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goguen, J. A. (1969). The logic of inexact concepts. Synthese, 19, 325–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gottwald, S. (1979). Set theory for fuzzy sets of higher level. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 2, 125–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gottwald, S. (2006). Universes of fuzzy sets and axiomatizations of fuzzy set theory. Part I: Model-based and axiomatic approaches. Studia Logica, 82, 211–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keefe, R. (1998). Vagueness by numbers. Mind, 107, 565–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keefe, R. (2000). Theories of vagueness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klir, G. J., & Yuan, B. (1995). Fuzzy sets and fuzzy logic: Theory and applications. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. (1973). Hedges: A study in meaning criteria and the logic of fuzzy concepts. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2, 458–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1980). A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In R. C. Jeffrey (Ed.), Studies in inductive logic and probability (Vol. 2, pp. 263–293). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1988). Vague identity: Evans misunderstood. Analysis, 48, 128–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machina, K. (1976). Truth, belief and vagueness. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 5, 47–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morreau, M. (2002). What vague objects are like. Journal of Philosophy, 99, 333–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (2000). Indeterminate identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rasiowa, H., & Sikorski, R. (1963). The mathematics of metamathematics. Warsaw: PWN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sattig, T. (2014). Mereological indeterminacy: Metaphysical but not fundamental. In K. Akiba & A. Abasnezhad (Eds.), Vague objects and vague identity (pp. 25–42). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Serchuk, P., Hargraves, I., & Zach, R. (2011). Vagueness, logic and use: Four experimental studies on vagueness. Mind and Language, 26, 540–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. J. J. (2008a). Vagueness and degrees of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. J. J. (2008b). Why sense cannot be made of vague identity. Noûs, 42, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B. (2005). True, truer, truest. Philosophical Studies, 123, 43–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. R. G. (2008). Multiple actualities and ontically vague identity. Philosophical Quarterly, 58, 134–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1996). The necessity and determinacy of distinctness. In S. Lovibond & S. G. Williams (Eds.), Essays for David Wiggins: Identity, truth and value (pp. 1–17). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2002). Vagueness, identity and Leibniz’s law. In A. Bottani, M. Carrara, & P. Giaretta (Eds.), Individual essence and identity (pp. 273–304). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zadeh, L. A. (1965). Fuzzy sets. Information and Control, 8, 338–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, J. (1980). A unified treatment of fuzzy set theory and Boolean-valued set theory – Fuzzy set structures and normal fuzzy set structures. Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications, 76, 297–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, J. (1982). Between fuzzy set theory and Boolean valued set theory. In M. M. Gupta & E. Sanchez (Eds.), Fuzzy information and decision procedures (pp. 143–147). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, J. (1983). Fuzzy set structure with strong implication. In P. P. Wang (Ed.), Advances in fuzzy sets, possibility theory, and applications (pp. 107–136). New York: Plenum.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ken Akiba .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Akiba, K. (2014). Boolean-Valued Sets as Vague Sets. In: Akiba, K., Abasnezhad, A. (eds) Vague Objects and Vague Identity. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 33. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7978-5_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics