Skip to main content

Stare Decisis and the Selection Effect

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Precedent in the United States Supreme Court

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 33))

  • 909 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter contends that there are significant systemic obstacles to determining whether the Supreme Court actually adheres to stare decisis. Political-science research suggests that precedent exerts relatively little constraint on the Court’s decisionmaking. The author contends that this research is unreliable, however, because of the selection effect: A strong norm of stare decisis, if it existed, would allow only the closest cases—those where precedent is least constraining—to reach the Court in the first place. Whether the selection effect actually operates in this way, however, depends on whether litigants, lawyers, and lower-court judges believe the Court applies stare decisis. And whether the Court does so is precisely what the empirical studies cannot reveal. As things stand, then, there is no reliable way to know whether the Court really follows precedent. The Court could fill this information gap by conspicuously reaffirming decisions known to be opposed by a majority of Justices, but it rarely has done so. This failure, more than any empirical research, suggests that the Court does not in fact accord much weight to precedent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On the distinction between vertical and horizontal precedent, see Dobbins (2010), Schauer (2009, 36–37), Kornhauser (1995), and Alexander (1989).

  2. 2.

    Except, of course, to the extent that so-called apex courts craft their opinions and establish rules in light of how they expect courts below them to understand and interpret those rules on future occasions.

  3. 3.

    The statement in the text is slightly too simple. A judge may have more or less confidence in her agreement with a prior decision, and agreement may thus be better understood in scalar rather than bimodal terms. And to the extent that this is the case, then internalization (in Hart’s (2012) sense) of a norm of stare decisis may supplement agreement with the earlier decision, producing greater confidence in the outcome than would have existed absent the stare decisis norm.

  4. 4.

    As noted above in note 3, the fact that the obligations of stare decisis are typically understood as short of absolute makes the statement in the text—that stare decisis is interesting or important only when a judge disagrees with the prior decision—a somewhat misleading overstatement. A judge’s agreement with a prior decision may be relatively weaker or stronger, and a judge who weakly agrees with a previous decision might have a stronger reason to follow it because of the additional reason of stare decisis than she would have were no such additional reason to be present.

  5. 5.

    See Lee (1999) and Wise (1975).

  6. 6.

    Ken Foskett quotes Justice Scalia as saying that Justice Thomas “does not believe in stare decisis, period” (2004, 281–82) (emphasis in original).

  7. 7.

    For example, see Dworkin (2007), complaining that the fourth in a line of Supreme Court cases on student speech, Morse v. Frederick, 551 U.S. 393 (2007), failed to follow the precedent of the first case, Tinker v. Des Moines Indep. School Dist., 393 U.S. 503 (1969)—even though the second and third cases in the same line (Bethel School Dist. v. Fraser, 478 U.S. 675 (1986), and Hazelwood School Dist. v. Kuhlmeier, 484 U.S. 260 (1988)) had ruled against students and in favor of restrictions and thus seemed consistent with Morse.

  8. 8.

    The most-explicit arguments against stare decisis in constitutional law come from the political right. See, for example, Paulsen (2005), Lawson (1994), and Cooper (1988). But the systematic rejection of precedential constraint by the (liberal) Warren Court has also been well documented. See Maltz (1980); see also Guardians Ass’n v. Civil Service Comm’n, 463 U.S. 582, 618 (1983) (Marshall, J., dissenting) (rejecting the idea that stare decisis should stand in the way of sound substantive principle).

  9. 9.

    The statements of the Justices, whether in opinions or extrajudicial, are particularly unhelpful, because the overwhelming number of claims of reliance on precedent are made by Justices in support of outcomes they believe substantively correct. Far more rare but nevertheless more telling are the opinions or votes of Justices known to disagree with the first-order merits of a position that they are, for second-order reasons of stare decisis, supporting. See Schauer (2007); see also Kelman (1985). And for the argument that stare decisis may have indirect effects that are harder to measure but may be more consequential, see Fallon (2001).

  10. 10.

    See, for example, Bailey and Maltzman (2011), Bartels (2009), Fowler and Jeon (2008), Bailey and Maltzman (2008), Hansford and Spriggs (2006), Segal and Spaeth (2001), Wahlbeck (1997), Segal and Spaeth (1996), and Brenner and Spaeth (1995).

  11. 11.

    Segal and Spaeth (1996, 2001) and Brenner and Spaeth (1995) are perhaps the most skeptical about the effect of stare decisis, but most are at least more skeptical than the typical law professor or law student, and certainly more skeptical than the public statements of judges and Justices.

  12. 12.

    “Rationalization” was the term of choice for many of the Legal Realists in arguing that judges typically or often first reached a result on largely non-legal grounds and only thereafter sought to explain, justify, or rationalize that law-independent outcome choice on legal grounds. See Frank (1930) and Hutcheson (1928–1929). On this aspect of and understanding of Legal Realism, see Schauer (2013).

  13. 13.

    The judicial opinion as an ex post rationalization of decisions reached on other grounds is also one of the principal themes in Frank (1930). See also Stumberg (1939, 532); Cohen (1935, 809–12); Cohen (1933, 237); Frank (1933, 910–11); and Llewellyn (1931, 1238–39). Note also the comment attributed to Chief Justice Hughes by Justice Douglas that “[a]t the constitutional level where we work, 90 % of any decision is emotional. The rational part of us supplies the reasons for supporting our predilections” (Douglas 1980, 8). And on the distinction between the logic of decision and the logic of justification, a distinction that provides some philosophical support for the rationality of the Realists’ less philosophical observations, see Wasserstrom (1961).

  14. 14.

    See Kritzer and Richards (2005) and Richards and Kritzer (2002).

  15. 15.

    See Lax and Rader (2010).

  16. 16.

    See Hathaway (2001). Path dependence will certainly make otherwise counterfactually eligible results impossible or undiscoverable, but this is a different phenomenon from that of a judge who actually sees a possible result and feels constrained by a stare decisis norm from reaching it.

  17. 17.

    See also Cross and Spriggs (2010) and Kritzer and Richards (2003).

  18. 18.

    On analogical reasoning in law, see Levi (2013), Weinreb (2005), Spellman (2004), Brewer (1996), and Sunstein (1993). For skepticism about the extent to which analogical reasoning, especially in law, is a distinct form of reasoning at all, see Posner (2006), Alexander (1998), and Alexander (1996).

  19. 19.

    On the often-ignored distinction between precedential and analogical reasoning, see Schauer (2008).

  20. 20.

    410 U.S. 113 (1973).

  21. 21.

    In the Court’s 2010 Term, for example, it considered 7,868 petitions for certiorari or other form of review, granted review in 90 of those cases, and ultimately decided 75 with full signed opinions and after briefing and argument. See The Statistics (2011, 369). In the 2011 Term, a total of 7,685 petitions was considered, and again there were 75 final dispositions with full signed opinions after briefing and oral argument (The Statistics 2012).

  22. 22.

    The scholarship on the selection effect is vast, the canonical modern source being George L. Priest & Benjamin Klein’s “The Selection of Disputes for Litigation” (1984). The Priest and Klein hypothesis about the nature of the disputes that are settled or litigated has spawned a substantial literature, much of it focused on challenging or supporting Priest and Klein’s claim that the selection effect will incline towards a 50 % win rate for plaintiffs in the cases that do not settle and thus wind up being tried to judgment. See, for example, Revesz (2000), Shavell (1996), Kessler et al. (1996), Waldfogel (1995), Hilton (1993), Eisenberg (1990), Wittman (1985), Priest (1985), and Bebchuk (1984). That question is theoretically and empirically important, but for purposes of this chapter all that is needed is the core insight that the cases that go to trial are a non-random and disproportionately indeterminate sample of legal events. On this basic point, useful analyses include Taha (2010), Kastellec and Lax (2008), Lederman (1999), Schauer (1988), and Posner (1986, Sect. 21).

  23. 23.

    It is important to acknowledge that much of the force of the selection effect may not apply to many criminal cases. Because most criminal defendants and most habeas corpus petitioners proceed in forma pauperis and thus at no cost to themselves (even apart from the fact that the time expended on litigation may be a consumption item and not a cost for those who are incarcerated), the normal disincentives to pursue likely hopeless litigation, appeal, and post-conviction remedies will often be absent.

  24. 24.

    See note 5 and accompanying text.

  25. 25.

    See Fon and Parisi (2006) and Shoenberger (2009).

  26. 26.

    This need not be the case. Prior to the House of Lords’s Practice Statement of 1966, even the highest courts in Great Britain were prohibited from reversing their own precedents. See Practice Statement (Judicial Precedent), [1966] 1 W.L.R. 1234 (H.L.); see also Blom-Cooper (2009, 782). After 1966, however, there remain no courts in common-law jurisdictions that do not have the power to reverse precedents that they themselves have created, even though any meaningful norm of stare decisis will make such an action more difficult—will require a stronger justification than would have been necessary to reach the same outcome in the absence of the earlier decision.

  27. 27.

    Dickerson v. United States, 530 U.S. 428 (2000), might be such a case, although judicial supremacy issues make the case a far from perfect example.

References

  • Alexander L (1989) Constrained by precedent. South Calif Law Rev 63(1):1–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander L (1996) Bad beginnings. Univ Pa Law Rev 145(1):57–87

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexander L (1998) The banality of legal reasoning. Notre Dame Law Rev 73(3):517–533

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailey MA, Maltzman F (2008) Does legal doctrine matter? Unpacking law and policy preferences on the U.S. Supreme Court. Am Pol Sci Rev 102(3):369–384

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailey MA, Maltzman F (2011) The constrained court: law, politics, and the decisions justices make. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartels BL (2009) The constraining capacity of legal doctrine on the U.S. Supreme Court. Am Pol Sci Rev 103(3):474–495

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bebchuk LA (1984) Litigation and settlement under imperfect information. Rand J Econ 15(3):404–415

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blom-Cooper L (2009) 1966 and all that: the story of the practice statement. In: Blom-Cooper L, Dickson B, Drewy G (eds) The judicial House of Lords. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 1876–2009

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brenner S, Spaeth HJ (1995) Stare indecisis: the alteration of precedent on the Supreme Court, 1946–1992. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer S (1996) Exemplary reasoning: semantics, pragmatics, and the rational force of legal argument by analogy. Harv Law Rev 109(5):923–1028

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen FS (1933) Ethical systems and legal ideals. Harcourt: Brace, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen FS (1935) Transcendental nonsense and the functional approach. Columbia Law Rev 35(6):809–849

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper CS (1988) Stare decisis: precedent and principle in constitutional adjudication. Cornell Law Rev 73(2):401–410

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross FB, Spriggs JF II (2010) The most important (and best) Supreme Court opinions and justices. Emory Law Rev 60(2):407–502

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobbins JC (2010) Structure and precedent. Mich Law Rev 108(8):1453–1496

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas WO (1980) The Court years, 1939–1975. Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (2007) The Supreme Court phalanx. N Y Rev Books 54(14):92–101

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberg T (1990) Testing the selection effect: a new theoretical framework with empirical tests. J Legal Stud 19(2):337–358

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fallon RH Jr (2001) Stare decisis and the Constitution: an essay on constitutional methodology. N Y Univ Law Rev 76(2):570–597

    Google Scholar 

  • Fon V, Parisi F (2006) Judicial precedents in civil law systems: a dynamic analysis. Int Rev Law and Econ 26(4):519–535

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foskett K (2004) Judging Thomas: the life and times of Clarence Thomas. Harper Collins Publishers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fowler JH, Jeon S (2008) The authority of Supreme Court precedent. Soc Netw 30(1):16–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank J (1930) Law and the modern mind. Brentano’s, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank J (1933) Why not a clinical lawyer-school. Univ Pa Law Rev 81(8):907–923

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansford TG, Spriggs JF II (2006) The politics of precedent on the U.S. Supreme Court. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (2012) The concept of law, 3rd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hathaway OA (2001) Path dependence in the law: the course and pattern of legal change in a common law system. Iowa Law Rev 86(2):601–665

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilton KN (1993) Asymmetric information and the selection of disputes for litigation. J Legal Stud 22(1):187–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmes OW (1897) The path of the law. Harv Law Rev 10(8):457–478

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutcheson JC (1928–1929) The judgment intuitive: the function of the ‘hunch’ in judicial decision. Cornell Law Q 14(3):274–288

    Google Scholar 

  • Kastellec JP, Lax JR (2008) Case selection and the study of judicial politics. J Empirical Leg Stud 5(3):407–446

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelman M (1985) The forked path of dissent. Supreme Court Rev 1985:227–298

    Google Scholar 

  • Kessler D, Meites T, Miller G (1996) Explaining deviations from the fifty-percent rule: a multimodal approach to the selection of cases for litigation. J Legal Stud 25(1):233–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornhauser LA (1995) Adjudication by a resource-constrained team: hierarchy and precedent in a judicial system. South Calif Law Rev 68(6):1605–1629

    Google Scholar 

  • Kritzer HM, Richards MJ (2003) Jurisprudential regimes and Supreme Court decisionmaking: the Lemon regime and Establishment Clause cases. Law Soc Rev 37(4):827–840

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kritzer HM, Richards MJ (2005) The influence of law in the Supreme Court’s search-and-seizure jurisprudence. Am Polit Res 33(1):33–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawson G (1994) The constitutional case against precedent. Harv J Law Publ Policy 17(1):23–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Lax JR, Rader KT (2010) Legal constraints on Supreme Court decision making: do jurisprudential regimes exist? J Polit 72(2):273–284

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lederman L (1999) Which cases go to trial?: An empirical study of predictors of failure to settle. Case West Reserv Law Rev 49(2):315–358

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee TR (1999) Stare decisis in historical perspective: from the founding era to the Rehnquist Court. Vanderbilt Law Rev 52(3):647–735

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi EH (2013) An introduction to legal reasoning, 2nd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Llewellyn K (1931) Some realism about Realism—responding to Dean Pound. Harv Law Rev 44(8):1222–1264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maltz EM (1980) Some thoughts on the death of stare decisis in constitutional law. Wis Law Rev 1980(3):467–496

    Google Scholar 

  • Paulsen MS (2005) The intrinsically corrupting influence of precedent. Constitutional Comment 22(2):289–298

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner RA (1986) Economic analysis of law, 3rd edn. Little, Brown & Co., Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner RA (2006) Reasoning by analogy. Cornell Law Rev 91(3):761–774

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest GL (1985) Reexamining the selection hypothesis: learning from Wittman’s mistakes. J Legal Stud 14(1):215–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest GL, Klein B (1984) The selection of disputes for litigation. J Legal Stud 13(1):1–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Revesz RL (2000) Litigation and settlement in the federal appellate courts: impact of panel selection procedures on ideologically divided courts. J Legal Stud 29(2):685–710

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richards MJ, Kritzer HM (2002) Jurisprudential regimes in Supreme Court decision making. Am Polit Sci Rev 96(2):305–320

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scalia A (1989) Originalism: the lesser evil. Univ Cincinnati Law Rev 57(3):849–865

    Google Scholar 

  • Scalia A (1997) Response. In: Scalia A (ed) A matter of interpretation: federal courts and the law. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (1985) Easy cases. South Calif Law Rev 58(1):399–440

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (1987) Precedent. Stanford Law Rev 39(3):571–605

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (1988) Judging in a corner of the law. South Calif Law Rev 61(6):1717–1733

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (2007) Has precedent ever really mattered in the Supreme Court? Ga State Univ Law Rev 24(2):381–401

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (2008) Why precedent in law (and elsewhere) is not totally (or even substantially) about analogy. Perspect Psychol Sci 3(6):454–460

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (2009) Thinking like a lawyer: a new introduction to legal reasoning. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (2013) Legal realism untamed. Tex Law Rev 91(4):749–780

    Google Scholar 

  • Segal JA, Spaeth HJ (1996) The influence of stare decisis on the votes of United States Supreme Court justices. Am J Polit Sci 40(4):971–1003

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segal JA, Spaeth HJ (2001) Majority rule or minority will: adherence to precedent on the United States Supreme Court. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Shavell S (1996) Any frequency of plaintiff victory at trial is possible. J Legal Stud 25(2):493–501

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoenberger A (2009) Change in the European civil law systems: infiltration of the Anglo-American case law system of precedent into the civil law system. Loyola Law Rev 55(1):5–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Spellman BA (2004) Reflections of a recovering lawyer: how becoming a cognitive psychologist—and (in particular) studying analogical and causal reasoning—changed my views about the field of psychology and law. Chicago-Kent Law Rev 79(3):1187–1214

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumberg GW (1939) May’s law of crimes. By Kenneth C. Sears and Henry Weihofen. Tex Law Rev 17(4):531–532

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein CR (1993) On analogical reasoning. Harv Law Rev 106(3):741–791

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taha AE (2010) Judge shopping: testing whether Judges’ political orientations affect case filings. Univ Cincinnati Law Rev 78(3):1007–1042

    Google Scholar 

  • The Statistics (2011) The Supreme Court, 2010 Term: the statistics. Harv Law Rev 125(1):362–377

    Google Scholar 

  • The Statistics (2012) The Supreme Court, 2011 Term: the statistics. Harv Law Rev 126(1):388–403

    Google Scholar 

  • Wahlbeck PJ (1997) The life of the law: judicial politics and legal change. J Polit 59(3):778–802

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldfogel J (1995) The selection hypothesis and the relationship between trial and plaintiff victory. J Polit Economy 103(2):229–260

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wasserstrom RA (1961) The judicial decision: toward a theory of legal justification. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinreb LL (2005) Legal reason: the use of analogy in legal argument. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wise EM (1975) The doctrine of stare decisis. Wayne Law Rev 21(4):1043–1060

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittman D (1985) Is the selection of cases for trial biased? J Legal Stud 14(1):185–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frederick Schauer .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schauer, F. (2013). Stare Decisis and the Selection Effect. In: Peters, C. (eds) Precedent in the United States Supreme Court. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 33. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7951-8_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics