Skip to main content

Epistemic Reasoning in Life and Literature

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
David Makinson on Classical Methods for Non-Classical Problems

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 3))

Abstract

Epistemic Logic has recently acquired importance as a growing field with influence in Distributed Computing, Philosophy, Economics, and of late even in Social Science and Animal behavior. Here, on a relatively light note, we give examples of epistemic reasoning occurring in literature and used very effectively by writers like Shakespeare, Shaw, Arthur Conan Doyle, and O’Henry. For variety we also give an example of epistemic reasoning used by fireflies, although it is far fetched to suppose that fireflies use epistemic reasoning in any kind of a conscious way. Surely they are getting a lot of help from Darwin. It is this writer’s hope that epistemic reasoning as a formal discipline will some day acquire importance comparable to that of Statistics. Hopefully these examples make part of the case.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Although Temple has great difficulty figuring out what adults and children are up to, she has enormous communication and empathy with animals. She has worked out methods to ease the last moments on earth of animals bound for slaughter.

  2. 2.

    Some of the examples in this section also occur in (Parikh et al.). Some are new.

  3. 3.

    In the quoted paragraph, \(ch(b, \{U, \lnot U\}\) refers to Vikram’s choice between the two actions, take umbrella and not take umbrella when Vikram is in state \(b\). Note that we are taking a state as an element  of the space of all possible states. Believing that it is raining  will be a subset  consisting of all states in which Vikram believes it is raining. Thus a state where Vikram believes it is raining and is standing will be distinct from a state where he believes it is raining and is sitting down. Neither state deserves to be called the  state of believing that it is raining.

  4. 4.

    Note, however that we do not address false information, as conveyed by the Photuris in this paper. That will be the subject of a sequel.

  5. 5.

    This incident is also discussed at length in Genot and Jacot (2012).

  6. 6.

    For a still earlier example, see the incident of Yudhisthira and Drona in the battle of the Mahabharata, (Smith 2009; Wikipedia entry on Drona). Incidents of deception also occur in the Hebrew Bible, see Brams (2003), Sects. 6.2 and 6.3.

References

  • Alchourron, C., Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: Partial meet contraction and revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50, 510–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brams, S. (2011). Game theory and the humanities: Bridging two worlds. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams, S. (2003). Bibliocal games. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chwe, M. S.-Y. (2013). Jane Austen, Game theorist. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chwe, M. S.-Y. (2003). Rational ritual. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wikipedia entry on Drona, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Drona.

  • Genot, E., & Jacot, J. (2012). How can questions be informative before they are answered? Strategic information in interrogative games. Episteme, 9(2), 189–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grandin, T. (2006). Thinking in pictures and other reports from my life with autism. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kourousias, G., & Makinson, D. (September 2007). Parallel interpolation, splitting, and relevance in belief change. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 72, 994–1002.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Lambalgen, M., & Counihan, M. (2008). Formal models for real people. Journal of Logic Language and Information, 17, 385–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neyman, A. (1991). The positive value of information. Games and Economic Behavior, 3, 350–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, M., & Rubinsein, A. (1994). A course in game theory. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parikh, R. (1999). Belief revision and language splitting. In Proc. Logic, Language and Computation, Ed. Moss, Ginzburg and de Rijke, CSLI 1999, pp. 266–278 (earlier version appeared in 1996 in the prliminary proceedings).

    Google Scholar 

  • Parikh, R. (March 2011). Beth definability, interpolation and language splitting. Synthese, 179(2), 211–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parikh, R. (2008). Sentences, belief and logical omniscience, or what does deduction tell us? Review of Symbolic Logic, 1, 459–476.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parikh, R., & Ramanujam, R. (2003). Journal of Logic, Language and Information. A knowledge based semantics of messages, 12, 453–467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parikh, R., Tasdemir, C., & Witzel, A. (2011). The power of knowledge in games, http://cuny.academia.edu/RohitParikh/Papers/.

  • Premack, D. G., & Woodruff, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1(4).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sacks, O. (1995). An anthropologist on mars. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (2010). Signals: Evolution, learning and information. New York: Oxford University press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. (2009). The mahabharata : An abridged translation (p. 477). New Delhi: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbrugge, R., & Mol, L. (2008). Learning to apply theory of mind. Journal of Logic Language and Information, 17(4), 489–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition, 13(1), 103–128.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Steven Brams, Yang Liu, Carol Parikh, Prashant Parikh, Paul Pedersen, Hilary Putnam, Noson Yanofsky and Ruili Ye for comments. This paper was supported by a grant from PSC-CUNY under the Faculty Research Assistance Program.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rohit Parikh .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Parikh, R. (2014). Epistemic Reasoning in Life and Literature. In: Hansson, S. (eds) David Makinson on Classical Methods for Non-Classical Problems. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 3. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7759-0_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics