Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 3))

Abstract

An account of legal change in a common law system is developed. Legal change takes place incrementally through court decisions that are constrained by previous decisions in other courts. The assumption is that a court’s decision has to be consistent with the rules set out in earlier court decisions. However, the court is allowed to make add new distinctions and therefore make a different decision based on factors not present in the previous decision. Two formal models of this process are presented. The first model is based on refinement of (the set of factors taken into account in) the set of previous cases on which a decision is based. In the second model the focus is on a preference ordering on reasons. The court is allowed to supplement, but not to revise the preference ordering on reasons that can be inferred from previous cases. The two accounts turn out to be equivalent. A court can make a consistent decision even if the case base is not consistent; the important requirement is that no new inconsistencies should be added to the case base.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Makinson (1996, 2003) and Gärdenfors (2011).

  2. 2.

    The term “derogation” is often used to refer only to limitation of a norm, while its full removal is described as an “abrogation”. My terminology here follows that of Alchourrón and Makinson (1981).

  3. 3.

    Alchourrón and Makinson (1981).

  4. 4.

    Alchourrón and Makinson (1982).

  5. 5.

    Alchourrón, Gärdenfors, and Makinson (1985).

  6. 6.

    See Raz (1979, pp. 180–209) and Simpson (1961).

  7. 7.

    See Horty (2011), and then Horty and Bench-Capon (2012) for a development of this account within the context of related research from Artificial Intelligence and Law; see Lamond (2005) for his earlier proposal.

  8. 8.

    See Rissland and Ashley (1987) and then Ashley (1989, 1990) for an introduction to the model; see also, Rissland (1990) for an overview of research in Artificial Intelligence and Law that places this work in a broader context.

  9. 9.

    Aleven (1997) has analyzed 147 cases from trade secrets law in terms of a factor hierarchy that includes 5 high-level issues, 11 intermediate-level concerns, and 26 base-level factors. The resulting knowledge base is used in an intelligent tutoring system for teaching elementary skills in legal argumentation, which has achieved results comparable to traditional methods of instruction in controlled studies; see Aleven and Ashley (1997).

  10. 10.

    Both of the assumptions mentioned in this paragraph are discussed in Horty (2011).

  11. 11.

    For the purpose of this paper, I simplify by assuming that the rule underlying a court’s decision is plain, ignoring the extensive literature on methods for determining the rule, or ratio decidendi, of a case. I will also assume that a case always contains a single rule, ignoring situations in which a judge might offer several rules for a decision, or in which a court reaches a decision by majority, with different judges offering different rules, or in which a judge might simply render a decision in a case without setting out any general rule at all.

  12. 12.

    See Horty (2013).

  13. 13.

    The most straightforward way in which the negation of the reason for the opposite decision would be entailed by the rule supporting the original, of course, is by being contained explicitly among the exceptions to that rule; but speaking more generally of entailment allows for other encodings as well.

  14. 14.

    Makinson (2003).

  15. 15.

    See Makinson (1986, 1989, 1994, 1998) and Makinson and van der Torre (2000).

References

  • Alchourrón, C., Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: Partial meet contraction and revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50, 510–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón, C., & Makinson, D. (1981). Hierarchies of regulations and their logic. In R. Hilpinen (Ed.), New studies in deontic logic (pp. 125–148). Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón, C., & Makinson, D. (1982). On the logic of theory change: Contraction functions and their associated revision functions. Theoria, 48, 14–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aleven, V. (1997). Teaching case-based argumentation through a model and examples. Unpublished PhD thesis, Intelligent Systems Program, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aleven, V., & Ashley, K. (1997). Evaluating a learning environment for case-based argumentation skills. In Proceedings of the 6th International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law (ICAIL-97) (pp. 170–179). The Association for Computing Machinery Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashley, K. (1989). Toward a computational theory of arguing with precedents: accomodating multiple interpretations of cases. In Proceedings of the 2nd International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law (ICAIL-89) (pp. 93–110). The Association for Computing Machinery Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashley, K. (1990). Modeling legal argument: Reasoning with cases and hypotheticals. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (2011). Notes on the history of ideas behind AGM. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 40, 115–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. (2011). Rules and reasons in the theory of precedent. Legal Theory, 17, 1–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. (2013). Common law reasoning. Manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J., & Bench-Capon, T. (2012). A factor based definition of precedential constraint. Artificial Intelligence and Law, 20, 181–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamond, G. (2005). Do precedents create rules? Legal Theory, 11, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D. (1986). On the formal representation of rights relations: Remarks on the work of stig kanger and lars lindahl. The Journal of Philosophical Logic, 15, 403–425.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D. (1989). General theory of cumulative inference. In M. Reinfrank, J. de Kleer, M. Ginsberg & E. Sandewall (Eds.), Proceedings of the 2nd International Workshop on Nonmonotonic Reasoning, volume 346 of Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence (pp. 1–18). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D. (1994). General patterns in nonmonotonic reasoning. In D. Gabbay, C. Hogger, & J. Robinson (Eds.), Handbook of Logic in Artificial Intelligence and Logic Programming: Nonmonotonic Reasoning and Uncertain Reasoning (Vol. 3, pp. 35–110). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D. (1996). In memoriam Carlos Eduardo Alchourrön. Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1, 3–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D. (1999). On a fundamental problem of deontic logic. In P. McNamara, H. Prakken. (Eds.), Norms, Logics and Information Systems: New Studies in Deontic Logic and Computer Science, Series: Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence and Applications (Vol. 49, pp. 29–53). Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D. (2003). Ways of doing logic: What was different about AGM 1985? Journal of Logic and Computation, 13, 5–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D., & van der Torre, L. (2000). Input/output logics. The Journal of Philosophical Logic, 29, 383–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1979). The Authority of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rissland, E. (1990). Artificial intelligence and law: Stepping stones to a model of legal reasoning. Yale Law Journal, 99, 1957–1981.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rissland, E., & Ashley, K. (1987). A case-based system for trade secrets law. In Proceedings of the 1st International Conference on AI and Law (ICAIL-87) (pp. 60–66). The Association for Computing Machinery Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, A. W. B. (1961). The ratio decidendi of a case and the doctrine of binding precedent. In A. G. Guest (Ed.), Oxford essays in jurisprudence (pp. 148–175). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Horty .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Horty, J. (2014). Norm Change in the Common Law. In: Hansson, S. (eds) David Makinson on Classical Methods for Non-Classical Problems. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 3. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7759-0_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics