Skip to main content

Dutch Cartesian Empiricism and the Advent of Newtonianism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Cartesian Empiricisms

Part of the book series: Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ((AUST,volume 31))

Abstract

At least since Voltaire, the perception of Cartesianism has often suffered from comparison to Newtonianism. In particular, Descartes’ ‘Rationalism’ has been regarded as basically flawed on account of its incompatibility with Newton’s approach to natural philosophy, which was to dominate much of eighteenth-century thought. In this paper it is argued that, on the contrary, both Descartes and some of his most tenacious Dutch admirers did not eschew Empiricism at all, but were actually instrumental in the early dissemination of Newtonianism on the Continent, and at Leiden University in particular.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Or so experts have traditionally inferred from Voltaire 1964, esp. 71, but there is no clear evidence that he actually attended the funeral of Newton, whom he incidentally never met either. See Barber 1979. For more on Voltaire and Newton in general see Rousseau 1976.

  2. 2.

    Voltaire 1964, 75: “La Géometrie était un guide que lui-même avait en quelque façon formé, et l’aurait conduit sûrement dans sa Physique; cependant il abandonna à la fin ce guide et se livra à l’esprit de système. Alors sa Philosophie ne fut qu’un roman ingénieux, et tout au plus vraisemblable pour les ignorants.”

  3. 3.

    Voltaire 1964, 76: “que deux et deux ne font quatre que parce que Dieu l’a voulu ainsi.”

  4. 4.

    Cassirer 1951, Chap. 1.

  5. 5.

    Voltaire 1826, 90: “La véritable physique consiste donc à bien déterminer tous les effets. Nous connaîtrons les causes premières quand nous serons des dieux.…Il nous est donné de calculer, de peser, de mesurer, d’observer: voilà la philosophie naturelle; presque tout le reste est chimère.”

  6. 6.

    Voltaire 1826, 95: “Il ne substitua donc qu’un chaos au chaos d’Aristote.”

  7. 7.

    [Voltaire] 1771, 218–225. In a passage added to the 1739 edition of the (fifteenth of the) Lettres philosophiques Voltaire specifically mentions Bacon as the man of whom Descartes should have taken heed. Voltaire 1964, 232.

  8. 8.

    Von Borzeszkowski and Wahsner 2000.

  9. 9.

    Herivel 1965; McGuire 1995; Guiccardini 2009, 59–136 and 293–308; Ducheyne 2012, esp. 253–263 and 269–278.

  10. 10.

    Koyré 1968, 115. In addition Koyré stressed the religious nature of Newton’s opposition to Descartes: 127. See more recently I. Bernard Cohen’s highly detailed “Guide to Newton’s Principia” in Newton 1999; Janiak 2008; Janiak and Schliesser 2011.

  11. 11.

    Thijssen-Schoute 1989; Dibon 1990; Verbeek 1992; Van Bunge 2001; Vermij 2002. For a detailed analysis of some of the early critiques, see Van Ruler 1995.

  12. 12.

    ’s Gravesande 1717.

  13. 13.

    Boerhaave 1715. On Boerhaave, see most recently Knoeff 2002; Kooijmans 2012.

  14. 14.

    ’s Gravesande 1720–1721, 1723, 1736.

  15. 15.

    Brunet 1926; Gori 1972; Ruestow 1973; de Pater 1979, 1994; Schuurman 2004, Chap. 8; Van der Wall 2004.

  16. 16.

    Israel 2001, Chap. 27 and 2006, Chap. 8; Vermij 2003; Jorink 2009. See also Ruestow 1973, Chap. 7.

  17. 17.

    Vermij 1991.

  18. 18.

    Jorink 2009.

  19. 19.

    See Chap. 1 by Dobre and Nyden.

  20. 20.

    See Chap. 10 by Nyden; Gori 1972, 20–42. See, more recently, also Feingold 2004, 69: “The person to put Holland on the Newtonian map, so to speak, was Burchard de Volder.” Wim Klever has tried to turn De Volder into a covert supporter of Spinoza: Klever 1989. This has been refuted by Lodge 2005.

  21. 21.

    Wiesenfeldt 2002, 1: “die Abkehr von einer dogmatischen Naturphilosophie und eine empirische Ausrichtung der philosophischen Lehre.”

  22. 22.

    Wiesenfeldt 2002, 56.

  23. 23.

    See, on De Bruyn and De Le Boë Sylvius, as well as on most of the Dutch authors mentioned in this paper: Van Bunge et al. 2003.

  24. 24.

    Le Clerc 1709, 356–359.

  25. 25.

    Wiesenfeldt 2002, 61: the Royal Society itself was on summer break, so De Volder will not have been present at one of its sessions, but he appears to have met both Robert Boyle and Robert Hooke. In Cambridge he visited Newton.

  26. 26.

    Wiesenfeldt 2002, 62.

  27. 27.

    Wiesenfeldt 2002, 89.

  28. 28.

    Wiesenfeldt 2002, 90.

  29. 29.

    They were collected in De Volder 1695. De Volder was unhappy with this book since he claimed the disputations involved were not meant to be published and were merely part of an academic exercise. They did not necessarily reflect his personal views. See Wiesenfeldt 2002, Chap. 7.

  30. 30.

    Le Clerc 1709, 398. See Chap. 9 by Dobre.

  31. 31.

    Le Clerc 1709, 383.

  32. 32.

    Vermij 2002, 350–352; Schuurman 2004, Chap. 5.

  33. 33.

    Le Clerc 1709, 398: “sur la fin de ses jours, et même quelques années auparavant, il avoit reconnu le foible du Cartesianisme; autant apparement, par sa propre méditation, que par le secours des habiles Anglois, qui ont établi d’autres principes. Je l’ai ouï se moquer, plus d’une fois, d’une bonne partie des Méditations de Descartes, quoi qu’il les eût expliquées pendant long-tems.”

  34. 34.

    De Volder 1664; Wiesenfeldt 2002, 225.

  35. 35.

    De Volder 1682; Wiesenfeldt 2002, 225–226.

  36. 36.

    De Volder 1698; Ruestow 1973, 106–112; Wiesenfeldt 2002, 227–230.

  37. 37.

    Wiesenfeldt 2002, 108–132.

  38. 38.

    Lodge 2004. A critical edition of this correspondence is forthcoming.

  39. 39.

    Krop 2003, 187–189. Taking his cue from the history of applied mathematics, in the same volume, Vanpaemel 2003 also stresses the continuity between Dutch Cartesianism and Newtonianism.

  40. 40.

    Garber 2001, Chaps. 6 and 5.

  41. 41.

    Garber 2001, Chap. 2 and Garber 1992, Chap. 2. See also, for instance, Schuster 1993.

  42. 42.

    For Regius, see Chap. 7 by Bellis.

  43. 43.

    See, for instance, Verbeek 1993, 2002.

  44. 44.

    Cook 2010, 26.

  45. 45.

    Cook 2007, 259.

  46. 46.

    AT IV 224–225, CSMK 358–359.

  47. 47.

    Clarke 1982, 17; Schuurman 2004, 26–33.

  48. 48.

    Laporte 1988, 477: “Se plier en toutes choses, à ce qu’on voit; l’enregistrer comme on le voit, à quelque ordre qu’il appartienne, sans rien y mêler de sa sensibilité propre: voilà l’attitude cartésienne, telle qu’elle se manifeste dans la théorie de méthode, comme aussi dans le Cogito et dans les démarches qui en precedent. C’est l’attitude empirique, au sens premier et authentique du mot: ceux-là seuls répugnent à en convenir, que des associations invétérées conduisent toujours à confondre empirique et sensualiste. En sorte que, si nous voulons à toute force caractériser la philosophie de Descartes par un nom, le nom qui lui siérait le mieux serait, tout paradoxe à part, celui d’empirisme—empirisme radical et intégral.”

  49. 49.

    Clarke 1982, Chap. 2.

  50. 50.

    Clarke 1982, Chap. 5.

  51. 51.

    See also Buchdahl 1963.

  52. 52.

    See most recently Garber and Longuenesse 2008.

  53. 53.

    Schuurman 2007. See also Ruestow 1973, 78–87; Wiesenfeldt 2002, 82–89, 162–184.

  54. 54.

    Schuurman 2004, 68–69.

  55. 55.

    Haakonssen 2004, 103–104.

  56. 56.

    Haakonssen 2004, 114.

  57. 57.

    See for a very interesting recent account, Aalderink 2010.

References

  • Aalderink, Mark. 2010. Philosophy, scientific knowledge, and concept formation in Geulincx and Descartes. Utrecht University: Publications of the Department of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barber, William H. 1979. Voltaire et Newton. In Voltaire and the English, ed. Mason Haydn, 193–202. Oxford: Voltaire Foundation (SVEC 176).

    Google Scholar 

  • Boerhaave, Herman. 1715. Sermo academicus de comparendo certo in physicis. Leiden: Petrus van der Aa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunet, Pierre. 1926. Les physiciens hollandais et la méthode expérimentale en France au XVIIIe siècle. Paris: Albert Blanchard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchdahl, Gerd. 1963. The relevance of Descartes’ philosophy of science for modern philosophy of science. The British Journal for the History of Science 1: 227–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, Ernst. 1951. The philosophy of the enlightenment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, Desmond M. 1982. Descartes’ philosophy of science. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, Harold J. 2007. Matters of exchange. Commerce, medicine, and science in the Dutch golden age. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, Harold J. 2010. Victories for Empiricism, failures for theory: Medicine and science in the seventeenth century. In The body as object and instrument of knowledge. Embodied Empiricism in early modern science, ed. Charles T. Wolfe and Ofer Gal, 9–32. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • de Pater, C. 1979. Een newtoniaans natuuronderzoeker. Utrecht: Proefschrift Rijskuniversiteit Utrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Pater, C. 1994. Willem Jacob ’s Gravesande (1688–1742) and Newton’s Regulae Philosophandi, 1742. Lias 21: 257–294.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Volder, Burchard. 1664. Disputatio medica inauguralis de natura. Leiden: Severinus Matthias.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Volder, Burchard. 1682. Oratio de conjugendis philosophicis et mathematicis diciplinis. Leiden: Voorn.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Volder, Burchard. 1685. Disputationes philosophicae omnes contra Atheos. Middelburg: Johannes Lateranus.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Volder, Burchard. 1695. Exercitationes academicae quibus Renati Cartesii philosophia defenditur adversus Petri Danielis Huetii Censuram philosophiae Cartesianae. Amsterdam: Arnoldus van Ravestein.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Volder, Burchard. 1698. Oratio de rationis viribus et usu in scientiis. Leiden: Frederik Haring.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, René. 1991. Philosophical writings of Descartes, vol. III, Trans. John Cottingham, Dugald Murdoch, Robert Stoothoff, and Anthony Kenny. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, René. 1996. Oeuvres de Descartes, 2nd ed. C. Adam and P. Tannery. Paris: Vrin

    Google Scholar 

  • Dibon, Paul. 1990. Regards sur la Hollande du siècle d’Or. Naples: Vivarium.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ducheyne, Steffen. 2012. “The main business of natural philosophy.” Isaac Newton’s natural-philosophical methodology. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feingold, Mordechai. 2004. The Newtonian moment. Isaac Newton and the making of modern culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel. 1992. Descartes’ metaphysical physics. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel. 2001. Descartes embodied. Reading Cartesian philosophy through Cartesian science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel, and Béatrice Longuenesse (eds.). 2008. Kant and the early moderns. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gori, Giambattista. 1972. La fondazione dell’esperienza in ’s Gravesande. Florence: Olschki.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gravesande, Willem Jacob ’s. 1717. Oratio inauguralis de Matheseos in omnibus scientiis, praecipue in Physicis, Usu, nec non de Astronomiae perfectione ex Physica haurienda. Leiden: Samuel Luchtmans

    Google Scholar 

  • Gravesande, Willem Jacob ’s. 1720–1721. Physices elementa mathematica, experimentis confirmata, sive Introductio ad Philosophiam Newtonianam, 2 vols. Leiden: P. and B. J. van der Aa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gravesande, Willem Jacob ’s. 1723. Philosophiae Newtonianae Institiones in usos academicos. Leiden: Petrus van der Aa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gravesande, Willem Jacob ’s. 1736. Introductio ad philosophiam, metaphysicam et logicam continens. Leiden: J. and H. Verbeek.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guiccardini, Niccolò. 2009. Isaac Newton on mathematical certainty and method. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haakonssen, Knud. 2004. The idea of early modern philosophy. In Teaching new histories of philosophy, ed. J.B. Schneewind, 99–121. Princeton: University Center for Human Values.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herivel, John. 1965. The background to Newton’s Principia. A study of Newton’s dynamical researches in the years 1664–1684. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Israel, Jonathan I. 2001. Radical enlightenment. Philosophy and the making of modernity, 1650–1750. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Israel, Jonathan I. 2006. Enlightenment contested. Philosophy, modernity, and the emancipation of man, 1670–1752. Oxford: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janiak, Andrew. 2008. Newton as philosopher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Janiak, Andrew, and Eric Schliesser (eds.). 2011. Interpreting Newton. Critical essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jorink, Eric. 2009. “Honouring Sir Isaac, or, exorcising the ghost of Spinoza”. Some remarks on the success of Newton in the Dutch Republic. In Future perspectives on Newton scholarship and the Newtonian legacy in eighteenth-century science and philosophy, ed. Steffen Ducheyne, 23–34. Brussels: Koninklijke Vlaamse Akademie van België voor Wetenschappen en Kunsten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klever, Wim. 1989. A Crypto-Spinozist on a Leiden Cathedra. Lias 15: 191–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knoeff, Rina. 2002. Herman Boerhaave (1668–1738). Calvinist chemist and physician. Amsterdam: Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kooijmans, Luuc. 2012. Het orakel. De man die de geneeskunde opnieuw uitvond: Herman Boerhaave (1669–1738). Amsterdam: Balans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyré, Alexandre. 1968. Études newtoniennes. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krop, Henri. 2003. Medicine and philosophy in Leiden around 1700: Continuity or rupture? In The early enlightenment in the Dutch Republic, 1650–1700, ed. Wiep van Bunge, 173–197. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laporte, Jean. 1988. Le rationalisme de Descartes. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. First published in 1945.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Clerc, Jean. 1709. Eloge de feu de Mr. De Volder, Professeur en Philosophie et aux Mathematiques dans l’Academie de Leide. Bibliotheque choisie 18: 346–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lodge, Paul. 2004. Leibniz’s close encounter with Cartesianism in the correspondence with De Volder. In Leibniz and his correspondents, ed. Paul Lodge, 162–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lodge, Paul. 2005. Burchard de Volder: Crypto-Spinozist or Disenchanted Cartesian? In Receptions of Descartes. Cartesianism and anti-Cartesianism in early modern Europe, ed. Tad M. Schmalz, 128–146. London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McGuire, J.E. 1995. Tradition and innovation. Newton’s metaphysics of nature. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, Isaac. 1999. The Principia. Mathematical principles of natural philosophy, ed. and trans. I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohault, Jacques. 1671. Traité de physique. Paris: Veuve de Charles Sevreux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, André Michel (ed.). 1976. Voltaire en Angleterre, 3 vols. Oxford: Voltaire Foundation (SVEC 145–147).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruestow, Edward G. 1973. Physics at seventeenth and eighteenth-century Leiden. Philosophy and the new science in the University. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, John A. 1993. Whatever should we do with Cartesian method? – Reclaiming Descartes for the history of science. In Essays on the philosophy and science of René Descartes, ed. Stephen Voss, 195–223. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schuurman, Paul. 2004. Ideas, mental faculties and method. The logic of Descartes and Locke and its reception in the Dutch Republic, 1630–1750. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuurman, Paul. 2007. Continuity and change in the Empiricism of John Locke and Gerard de Vries (1648–1705). History of European Ideas 33: 292–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thijssen-Schoute, C.L. 1989. Nederlands cartesianisme. Utrecht: HES. First published in 1954.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Bunge, Wiep. 2001. From Stevin to Spinoza. An essay on philosophy in the seventeenth-century Dutch Republic. Brill: Leiden.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Bunge, Wiep, Henri Krop, Bart Leeuwenburgh, Han van Ruler, Paul Schuurman and Michiel Wielema (eds.). 2003. The dictionary of seventeenth and eighteenth-century Dutch Philosophers, 2 vols. Bristol: Thoemmes.

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Wall, Ernestine G.E. 2004. Newtonianism and religion in the Netherlands. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 35: 493–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Ruler, J.A. 1995. The crisis of causality. Voetius and Descartes on God, nature, and change. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanpaemel, Geert. 2003. The culture of mathematics in the early Dutch enlightenment. In The early enlightenment in the Dutch Republic, 1650–1700, ed. Wiep van Bunge, 197–211. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek, Theo. 1992. Descartes and the Dutch. Early reactions to Cartesian philosophy, 1637–1650. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek, Theo (ed.). 1993. Descartes et Regius. Autour de l’Explication de l’Esprit humain. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek, Theo. 2002. Dutch Cartesian philosophy. In A companion to early modern philosophy, ed. Steven Nadler, 167–182. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermij, Rienk. 1991. Secularisering en natuurwetenschap in de zeventiende en achttiende eeuw. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermij, Rienk. 2002. The Calvinist Copernicans. The reception of the new astronomy in the Dutch Republic, 1575–1750. Amsterdam: Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermij, Rienk. 2003. The formation of the Newtonian natural philosophy. The case of the Amsterdam mathematical Amateurs. The British Journal for the History of Science 26: 183–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • [Voltaire]. 1771. Questions sur l’Encyclopédie, par des amateurs, vol. III. [Paris: s.n] (1st ed. 1770).

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltaire. 1826. Dictionnaire philosophique, vol. 53, Oeuvres completes de Voltaire. Paris: s.n.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltaire. 1964. Lettres philosophiques, ed. Raymond Naves. Paris: Garnier.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Borzeszkowski, Horst-Heino, and Renate Wahsner. 2000. Voltaire’s Newtonianism. A bridge from English Empiricism to Cartesian rationalism and its implications for the concept of mechanics in German idealism. Preprints Max Planck-Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte 147: 5–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiesenfeldt, Gerhard. 2002. Leerer Raum in Minervas Haus. Experimentelle Naturlehre an der Universität Leiden, 1675–1715. Amsterdam: Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wiep van Bunge .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

van Bunge, W. (2013). Dutch Cartesian Empiricism and the Advent of Newtonianism. In: Dobre, M., Nyden, T. (eds) Cartesian Empiricisms. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol 31. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7690-6_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics