Advertisement

The Cartesian Psychology of Antoine Le Grand

  • Gary HatfieldEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Studies in History and Philosophy of Science book series (AUST, volume 31)

Abstract

In the Aristotelian curriculum, De anima or the study of the soul fell under the rubric of physics. This area of study covered the vital (“vegetative”), sensitive, and rational powers of the soul. Descartes’ substance dualism restricted reason or intellect, and conscious sensation, to human minds. Having denied mind to nonhuman animals, Descartes was required to explain all animal behavior using material mechanisms possessing only the properties of size, shape, position, and motion. Within the framework of certainty provided by the metaphysical foundations of his physics, he posited such mechanisms in accordance with appropriately lessened standards of certainty. As Cartesianism (or the Cartesian revolution) spread, adherents offered survey textbooks or treatises of physics to replace the corresponding Aristotelian curriculum. These books typically discussed the role of experience in physics and the appropriate standard of certainty. A comprehensive Cartesian natural philosophy needed to mechanize the offices of the Aristotelian sensitive soul, including sense perception, memory, and cognitive and appetitive responses to the environment. Descartes’ Treatise on Man (1664) offered an initial explanatory program. This chapter examines the role of experience in the natural philosophy and mechanistic psychology of Descartes’ English follower Antoine Le Grand. He offered detailed accounts of the sensory and motor mechanisms shared by human and nonhuman animals (for which he claimed “physical certainty”). These frame his Cartesian psychology.

Keywords

Seventeenth Century Nonhuman Animal Living Thing Absolute Certainty Natural Theology 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Ariew, Roger. 2011. The new matter theory and its epistemology: Descartes (and late scholastics) on hypothesis and moral certainty. In Vanishing matter and the laws of motion: Descartes and beyond, ed. Dana Jalobeanu and Peter R. Anstey, 31–46. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  2. Blome, Richard. 1692. Proposals for the printing an entire course or body of philosophy, according to the principles of the famous Renate Des Cartes. London: R. Blome.Google Scholar
  3. Bouillier, Francisque. 1842. Histoire et critique de la révolution cartésienne. Lyon: Boitel.Google Scholar
  4. Boyle, Robert. 1674. The excellency of theology compar’d with natural philosophy. London: Henry Herringman.Google Scholar
  5. Buchdahl, Gerd. 1969. Metaphysics and the philosophy of science, the classical origins: Descartes to Kant. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  6. Clarke, Desmond M. 1982. Descartes’ philosophy of science. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Clarke, Desmond M. 1992. Descartes’ philosophy of science and the scientific revolution. In Cambridge companion to Descartes, ed. John Cottingham, 258–285. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Clatterbaugh, Kenneth. 1999. The causation debate in modern philosophy, 1637–1739. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  9. Cohen, I. Bernard. 1985. The Newtonian revolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Cottingham, John. 1998. Descartes’s treatment of animals. In Descartes, ed. John Cottingham, 225–233. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Descartes, René. 1649. A discourse of a method for the well guiding of reason, and the discovery of truth in the sciences. London: Thomas Newcombe.Google Scholar
  12. Descartes, René. 1650. The passions of the soule. London: J. Martin, and J. Ridley.Google Scholar
  13. Descartes, René. 1653. Excellent compendium of Musick. London: Humphrey Moseley.Google Scholar
  14. Descartes, René. 1707. La Philosophie morale de Monsieur Descartes. Brussels: Foppens.Google Scholar
  15. Descartes, René. 1680. Six metaphysical meditations wherein it is proved that there is a god and that mans mind is really distinct from his body. Trans. William Molyneux. London: Benjamin Tooke.Google Scholar
  16. Descartes, René. 1984–1991. The philosophical writings, 3 vols. Trans. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, D. Murdoch, and A. Kenny (for the third volume). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Descartes, René. 1996. Oeuvres de Descartes. 2nd ed, ed. Ch. Adam and P. Tannery. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
  18. Easton, Patricia. 2012. Antoine Le Grand. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2012 edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/legrand/. Accessed 28 Nov 2012.
  19. Fernel, Jean. 2003. Physiologia. Trans. J.M. Forrester. Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society. (Originally published in Latin in 1567.)Google Scholar
  20. Garber, Daniel. 1992. Descartes’ metaphysical physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  21. Garber, Daniel. 2001. Descartes on knowledge and certainty: From the Discours to the Principia. In Descartes embodied: Reading Cartesian philosophy through Cartesian science, 111–129. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Hall, A. Rupert, and Marie Boas Hall (eds.). 1971. The correspondence of Henry Oldenburg: Volume VIII, 1671–1672. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
  23. Hatfield, Gary. 1985. First philosophy and natural philosophy in Descartes. In Philosophy, its history and historiography, ed. A.J. Holland, 149–164. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Hatfield, Gary. 1986. The senses and the fleshless eye: The Meditations as cognitive exercises. In Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, ed. Amélie Rorty, 45–79. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  25. Hatfield, Gary. 1990. Metaphysics and the new science. In Reappraisals of the scientific revolution, ed. David Lindberg and Robert Westman, 93–166. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Hatfield, Gary. 1992. Descartes’s physiology and its relation to his psychology. In Cambridge companion to Descartes, ed. John Cottingham, 335–370. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Hatfield, Gary. 1996. Was the scientific revolution really a revolution in science? In Tradition, transmission, transformation, ed. Jamil Ragep and Sally Ragep, 489–525. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  28. Hatfield, Gary. 2000. Descartes’ naturalism about the mental. In Descartes’ natural philosophy, ed. Stephen Gaukroger, John Schuster, and John Sutton, 630–658. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  29. Hatfield, Gary. 2005. Rationalist theories of sense perception and mind–body relation. In Blackwell companion to rationalism, ed. Alan Nelson, 31–60. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Hatfield, Gary. 2007. Animals. In Companion to Descartes, ed. John Carriero and Janet Broughton, 404–425. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  31. Hatfield, Gary. 2009. Psychology in philosophy: Historical perspectives. In Psychology and philosophy: Inquiries into the soul from late scholasticism to contemporary thought, ed. Sara Heinamaa and Martina Reuter, 1–25. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  32. Hatfield, Gary. 2012. Mechanizing the sensitive soul. In Matter and form in early modern science and philosophy, ed. Gideon Manning, 151–186. Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Laporte, J. 1928. La finalité chez Descartes. Revue d’Histoire de la Philosophie 2: 366–396.Google Scholar
  34. Laudan, Larry. 1966. The clock metaphor and probabilism: The impact of Descartes on English methodological thought, 1650–65. Annals of Science 22: 74–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Le Grand, Antoine. 1671. Philosophia veterum, e mente Renati Descartes more scholastico breviter degesta. London: J. Martyn.Google Scholar
  36. Le Grand, Antoine. 1672. Institutio philosophiae, secundum principia domini Renati Descartes: novo methodo adornata & explicata: in usum juventutis academicae. London: J. Martyn.Google Scholar
  37. Le Grand, Antoine. 1673. Historia naturae, variis experimentis & ratiociniis elucidata: secundum principia stabilita in Institutione philosophiae edita ab eodem authore. London: J. Martyn.Google Scholar
  38. Le Grand, Antoine. 1675. Dissertatio de carentia sensus & cognitionis in brutis. London: J. Martyn.Google Scholar
  39. Le Grand, Antoine. 1680. Institutio philosophiae, secundum principia D. Renati Descartes: nova methodo adornata, & explicata: in usum juventutis academicae, 4th ed. London: J. Martyn.Google Scholar
  40. Le Grand, Antoine. 1694. An entire body of philosophy according to the principles of the famous Renate Des Cartes, 2 vols, ed. R. Blome. London: Samuel Roycroft. (Reprint, New York: Johnson Reprint, 1972.)Google Scholar
  41. Le Grand, Antoine. 1711. Institutio philosophiae, secundum principia domini Renati Descartes: nova methodo adornata, & explicate: in usum juventutis academicae. Nuremberg: J. Ziegeri.Google Scholar
  42. Lennon, Thomas M. (ed.). 2003. Cartesian views: Papers presented to Richard A. Watson. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  43. Locke, John. 1690. An essay concerning human understanding. London: Bassett.Google Scholar
  44. Machamer, Peter, and J.E. McGuire. 2009. Descartes’s changing mind. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Oldenburg, Henry. 1671. An accompt of some books. Philosophical Transactions 6: 2136–2142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Plutynski, Anya. 2011. In defense of rationalist science. In Science at the frontiers: Perspectives in history and philosophy of science, ed. William Krieger. Lanham: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
  47. Régis, Pierre-Sylvain. 1691. Cours entier de philosophie, ou systeme general selon les principes de M. Descartes, Latest edition, 3 vols. Amsterdam: Huguetan. (Reprint, New York: Johnson, 1970).Google Scholar
  48. Rey, Alain (ed.). 1992. Dictionnaire historique de la langue française: contenant les mots français en usage et quelques autres délaissés, 2 vols. Paris: Dictionnaires Le Robert.Google Scholar
  49. Rogers, G.A.J. 1985. Descartes and the English. In The light of nature: Essays in the history and philosophy of science presented to A. C. Crombie, ed. J.D. North, J.J. Roche, and A.C. Crombie, 281–302. Dordrecht: Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  50. Rohault, Jacques. 1987. System of natural philosophy, illustrated with Dr. Samuel Clarke’s notes, taken mostly out of Sir Isaac Newton’s philosophy. New York/London: Garland Publishing. (Originally published in French in 1671.)Google Scholar
  51. Rosenfield, Leonora Cohen. 1968. From beast-machine to man-machine: Animal soul in French letters from Descartes to La Mettrie, 2nd ed. New York: Octagon Books.Google Scholar
  52. Ryan, John. 1935. Anthony Legrand (1629–1699): Franciscan and Cartesian. New Scholasticism 9: 226–250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Schmaltz, Tad M. 2002. Radical Cartesianism: The French reception of Descartes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Shapiro, Barbara J. 1983. Probability and certainty in seventeenth-century England: A study of the relationships between natural science, religion, history, law, and literature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  55. Simmons, Alison. 2001. Sensible ends: Latent teleology in Descartes’s account of sensation. Journal of the History of Philosophy 39: 49–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Thaddeus, Father. 1898. The Franciscans in England, 1600–1850: Being an authentic account of the second English Province of Friars Minor. London: Art and Book Co.Google Scholar
  57. Trevisani, Francesco. 1992. Descartes in Germania: la ricezione del cartesianesimo nella Facoltà filosofica e medica di Duisburg (1652–1703). Milan: Angeli.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of PennsylvaniaPhiladelphiaUSA

Personalised recommendations