Skip to main content

The Role of History and Philosophy in University Mathematics Education

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Abstract

University level mathematics is organised differently in different universities. In this paper we consider mathematics programmes leading to a graduate degree in mathematics. We briefly introduce a multiple perspective approach to the history of mathematics from its practices, reflections about uses of history and the research direction in philosophy of mathematics denoted ‘Philosophy of Mathematical Practice’. We link history and philosophy of mathematical practices to recent ideas in mathematics education in order to identify different roles history and philosophy can play in the learning of mathematics at university level. We present, analyse and discuss different examples of inclusions of history and philosophy in university programmes in mathematics. These presentations are divided into courses in history and philosophy, respectively, since this is the main way they are organised at the universities. We shall see, however, that the history courses address philosophical questions and that the philosophy courses employ historical material. The chapter ends with comments on how mathematics educations at university level can benefit from history and philosophy of mathematics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   749.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For the roles of the history and philosophy of mathematics in liberal arts education, we refer to the previous chapter by Judith Grabiner.

  2. 2.

    Our joint paper (Kjeldsen and Carter 2012) serves as an example of this mutual beneficial relationship.

  3. 3.

    See, e.g. Lützen and Purkert (1989) where the different historiographical views of Cantor and Zeuthen are discussed.

  4. 4.

    In Kjeldsen (2012) Jensen’s terminology is outlined and used as lens through which we can identify and distinguish between different conceptions and uses of history of mathematics.

  5. 5.

    This is our translation of the Danish word ‘lærd’.

  6. 6.

    Their views on mathematics are very different. For a presentation of their positions, see Shapiro (2000). For a nontraditional description of Plato’s philosophy, in line with the perspective of mathematical practice, see McLarty (2005).

  7. 7.

    Another interesting development in mathematics around the turn of the century was the move towards structuralism. What is studied in mathematics is not the objects as such – it is the relations between objects. This is most famously described by Hilbert saying ‘one must be able to say “tables, chairs, beer-mugs” each time in place of “points, lines, planes”’ (Blumenthal 1935, pp. 402–403), expounded mathematically in his Foundations of Geometry (Hilbert 1899). Traces of this conception about mathematics can still be found in today’s philosophies of mathematics; see Benacerraf (1965), Hellman (1996), Resnik (1999), and Shapiro (1997). More recently philosophers have argued that category theory provides a sound basis of a ‘top-down’ structuralist view (Awodey 1996; Landry and Marquis 2005).

  8. 8.

    Since the original foundational schools failed for a variety of reasons, other ways of obtaining a foundation were looked for. It was, for example, proved by Gentzen during 1930s that if sufficiently strong methods (induction over ε0) are used, then it is possible to prove the consistency of arithmetic. A different approach is to find a weaker system than Primitive Recursive Arithmetic where completeness and consistency are provable.

  9. 9.

    See, e.g. Ferreiros and Gray (2006), Mancosu (2008), Van Kerkhove and Van Bendegem (2007), and Van Kerkhove et al. (2010).

  10. 10.

    Philosophy of Mathematics: Sociological Aspects and Mathematical Practice.

  11. 11.

    One misconception is that when Frege started worrying about the foundation of analysis, it had already been settled by the work of Weierstrass in Berlin. The fact of the matter, Tappenden argues, is that problems of real analysis were being solved, but Frege knew of the (revolutionary) work of Riemann from the 1850s integrating geometry and complex analysis, opening up whole new fields of study.

  12. 12.

    The introduction of Riemann surfaces and K-theory.

  13. 13.

    The project was called Competencies and Mathematical Learning. It was initiated by the Danish National Council for Science Education in 2000. For a shortened English version of the original report, see Niss and Højgaard (2011).

  14. 14.

    It is generally held that students’ beliefs influence their learning, for example, that affective beliefs play a major role (Burton 2004). Here we are only interested in philosophical beliefs.

  15. 15.

    It has also been argued that knowledge of philosophy can turn you into a better person. Philosophy teaches rational thinking, and in particular, ethics deals with the good and bad.

  16. 16.

    http://sis.ku.dk/kurser/viskursus.aspx?knr=121117&sprog=2&forrige=57876

  17. 17.

    http://sis.ku.dk/kurser/viskursus.aspx?knr=121117&sprog=2&forrige=57876

  18. 18.

    http://sis.ku.dk/kurser/viskursus.aspx?knr=121117&sprog=2&forrige=57876

  19. 19.

    http://sofia.nmsu.edu/~history/; http://www.cs.nmsu.edu/historical-projects

  20. 20.

    http://sofia.nmsu.edu/~history/

  21. 21.

    http://sofia.nmsu.edu/~history/

  22. 22.

    See http://www.cs.nmsu.edu/historical-projects.

  23. 23.

    Personal e-mail correspondence between David Pengelley and Tinne Hoff Kjeldsen on Monday the 25. of June, 2012.

  24. 24.

    Three to eight students is the common group size, but students are allowed to perform a project on their own.

  25. 25.

    Under the ‘profession’ requirement, the students have a choice between a modelling project, a pure mathematics project, a history and/or philosophy of mathematics project or a project on aspects of mathematics education, according to in what kind of direction, they want their future profession to move.

  26. 26.

    See also Niss’ (2001) narrative on his 25 years of experiences with the RUC model.

  27. 27.

    The students’ project report can be downloaded at the following address: http://milne.ruc.dk/ImfufaTekster/pdf/403.pdf.

  28. 28.

    All quotes from student reports have been translated into English by us.

  29. 29.

    The students’ project report can be downloaded at the following address: http://milne.ruc.dk/ImfufaTekster/pdf/416.pdf.

  30. 30.

    Until 1971 it was compulsory for all university students in Denmark to take an introductory philosophy course, so-called filosofikum. This course was mainly handled by philosophers.

  31. 31.

    In addition ‘videnskabsteori’ is mentioned. It is best translated as ‘theory of science’ and is usually thought of more broadly than philosophy of science, including social science, history of science and ethics.

  32. 32.

    The following is taken – and translated – from slides used in the course.

  33. 33.

    The topic of the role of models in society is also dealt with at USD, and the following description is mainly based on the treatment there.

  34. 34.

    Maddy’s (1990) set theoretic realism and Shapiro’s (2000) ante rem structuralism are examples of what is presented. In addition we discuss Field’s (1980) fictionalism and the empiricism of Mill.

  35. 35.

    A scientific theory is confirmed as a whole. If mathematics is part of a confirmed scientific theory, then the included mathematics is also confirmed.

  36. 36.

    In Aarhus and Copenhagen, it is very common for teachers to write their own textbook material.

References

  • Abraham, T.H. (2004). Nicolas Rashevsky’s Mathematical Biophysics. Journal of the History of Biology, 37, 333–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, L. D., Jørgensen, D. R., Larsen, L. F. and Pedersen, M. L. (2003). Rashevsky’s pride and prejudice (in Danish). Report, 3rd semester, Nat-Bas, Roskilde University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashton, P. & Kean, H. (eds.) (2009). People and their Pasts. Public History Today. Houndsmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Awodey, S. (1996). Structures in mathematics and logic: A categorical perspective. Philos. Math., 4, 29–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnett, J. (2012). Bottled at the Source: The Design and Implementation of Classroom Projects for Learning Mathematics via Primary Historical Sources. Plenary address. Proceedings from the HPM International Congress in Korea, 2012. http://www.hpm2012.org/Proceeding/Plenary/PL3.pdf

  • Barnett, J., Lodder, J., Pengelley, D., Pivkina, I. and Ranjan, D. (2011). Designing student projects for teaching and learning discrete mathematics and computer science via primary historical sources. In V. Katz and C. Tzanakis (eds.). Recent developments on introducing a historical dimension in mathematics education, Washington, DC: Mathematical Association of America, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckmann, A. (2009). A Conceptual Framework for Cross-Curricular Teaching. The Montana Mathematics Enthusiast, 6, Supplement 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. (1973). Mathematical Truth. The Journal of Philosophy, 70, 661–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. (1965). What numbers could not be. The Philosophical Review, 74, 47–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P & Putnam H. (1983). Philosophy of Mathematics Selected Readings. Cambridge University Press, (2. ed.), NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blomhøj, M. & Kjeldsen, T.H. (2009). Project organised science studies at university level: exemplarity and interdisciplinarity. ZDM – International Journal on Mathematics Education, 41 (1–2), 2009, 183–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1994). What can the sociologist say about 2 + 2 = 4? In Ernest (1994), pp. 21–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenthal, O. (1935). Lebensgeschichte. In D. Hilbert. Gesammelte Abhandlungen vol. 3, (pp. 388–435), Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton, L (2004). Confidence is Everything - Perspectives of Teachers and Students on Learning Mathematics. Journal of Mathematics Teacher Education, 7, 357–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. (2004). Ontology and mathematical practice. Philos. Math., 12, 244–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. (2006). A less radical constructivism. Nomad 11, 5–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. (2008). Categories for the working mathematician. Making the impossible possible. Synthese, 162, 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. (2013). Mathematical Objects: Representations and context. Synthese. doi: 10.1007/s11229-012-0241-5.

  • Chassapis, D. (2007). Integrating the Philosophy of Mathematics in Teacher Training Courses. In: François & Van Bendegem (eds.) (2007), pp. 61–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Corfield, D. (2003). Towards a Philosophy of Real Mathematics. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epple, M. (1999). Die Entstehung der Knotentheorie: Kontexte und Konstruktionen einer modernen mathematischen Theorie. Wiesbaden: Vieweg.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Epple, M. (2004). Knot Invariants in Vienna and Princeton during the 1920s: Epistemic Configurations of Mathematical Research. Science in Context, 17, 131–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epple, M. (2011). Between Timelessness and Historiality. On the Dynamics of the Epistemic Objects of Mathematics. Isis, 102, 481–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ernest, P. (ed.) (1994). Mathematics, Education and Philosophy, London: Falmer Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ernest, P. (1998). Social Constructivism as a Philosophy of Mathematics, Albany, New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ernest, P. (2004). What is the Philosophy of Mathematics Education? Philosophy of mathematics Education Journal 18, http://people.exeter.ac.uk/PErnest/pome18/PhoM_%20for_ICME_04.htm Accessed 1 July 2012.

  • Ernest, P. (2009). What is first philosophy in mathematics education? In: M. Tzekaki et al. (eds.) Proceedings of the 33rd Conference of the International Group for the PME, Vol 1, 25–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferreirós, J. and Gray, J. (eds.) (2006). The Architecture of Modern Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1980). Science Without Numbers, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fink, H. (2001). Fra Filosofikum til Studium Generale. http://udd.uvm.dk/200103/udd03-10.htm Accessed 28 June 2012.

  • François, K. & Van Bendegem, JP. (eds.) (2007). Philosophical Dimensions in Mathematics Education. Springer Science and Business Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • François, K. & Van Bendegem, JP. (2010). Philosophy of mathematics in the mathematics curriculum, questions and problems raised by a case study of secondary education in Flanders. Contribution to Mathematics Education and Society 6. http://www.ewi-psy.fu-berlin.de/en/v/mes6/documents/research_papers/Francois_VanBendegem_MES6.pdf?1286354771. Accessed 1 July 2012.

  • Godiksen, R.B., Jørgensen, C., Hanberg, T.M. & Toldbod, B. (2003). Fourier and the concept of a function – the transition from Euler’s to Dirichlet’s concept of a function. (In Danish). IMFUFA, text 416, Roskilde University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, J. (2008). Plato’s Ghost: The Modernist Transformation of Mathematics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grattan-Guinness, I. (2008). Solving Wigner’s mystery: The Reasonable (Though Perhaps Limited) Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences. The mathematical intelligencer, 30, 7–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heinz, B. (2000). Die innenwelt der mathematik. Zur kultur und Praxis einer beweisenden disziplin. Wien: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellmann, G. (1996). Structuralism without structures. Philos. Math., 4, 129–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hersh, R, (1979). Some proposals for revising the philosophy of mathematics. Advances in Mathematics, 31, 31–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1899). Grundlagen der Geometrie. B.G. Täubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1902). Mathematical Problems, Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 8, no. 10 (1902), 437–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, B.E. (2003). Historie – livsverden og fag. Copenhagen: Gyldendal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, B.E. (2010). Hvad er historie (in Danish). Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, V.J. (2009). A History of Mathematics. An Introduction. Boston: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E.F. (2002). Making Sense of Life. Cambridge Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, T.H. (2009). Egg-forms and Measure Bodies: Different Mathematical Practices in the Early History of the Development of the Modern Theory of Convexity. Science in Context, 22(01), 85–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, T.H. (2010). History in mathematics education - why bother? Interdisciplinarity, mathematical competence and the learning of mathematics. In B. Sriraman, and V. Freiman (eds.): Interdisciplinarity for the 21st Century: Proceedings of the 3rd International Symposium on Mathematics and its Connections to Arts and Sciences (pp. 17–48). Information Age Publishing, incorporated.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, T.H. (2011a). History in a competency based mathematics education: a means for the learning of differential equations. In Katz, V., & Tzanakis, C. (eds.). Recent developments on introducing a historical dimension in mathematics education, Washington, DC: Mathematical Association of America, 2011, 165–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, T.H. (2011b). Hvad er matematik? Copenhagen: Akademisk forlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, T.H. (2012). Uses of History for the Learning of and about Mathematics. Towards a theoretical framework for integrating history of mathematics in mathematics education. Plenary address. Proceedings from the HPM International Congress in Korea, 2012. http://www.hpm2012.org/Proceeding/Plenary/PL1.pdf

  • Kjeldsen, T.H. & Blomhøj, M. (2009). Integrating history and philosophy in mathematics education at university level through problem-oriented project work. ZDM Mathematics Education, Zentralblatt für Didaktik der Mathematik, 41(1–2), 2009, 87–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, T.H. & Blomhøj, M. (2012). Beyond Motivation - History as a method for the learning of meta-discursive rules in mathematics. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 80 (3), 2012, 327–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, T.H. & Blomhøj, M. (2013). Developing Students’ Reflections about the Function and Status of Mathematical Modeling in Different Scientific Practices: History as a Provider of Cases. Science & Education, 22 (9), 2013, 2157–2171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, T.H. & Carter, J. (2012). The growth of mathematical knowledge - introduction of convex bodies. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 43, 359–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kjeldsen, T.H. & Petersen, P.H. (forthcoming). Bridging History of the Concept of a Function with Learning of Mathematics: Students’ meta-discursive rules, concept formation and historical awareness. Science & Education doi: 10.1007/s11191-013-9641-2.

  • Knoebel, A., Laubenbacher, R., Lodder, J. & Pengelley, D. (2007). Mathematical Masterpieces: Further Chronicles by the Explorers. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kragh Sørensen, H. (2012). Making philosophy of science relevant for science students. RePoSS: Research Publications on Science Studies 18. Aarhus: Centre for Science Studies, University of Aarhus, Jan. 2012. URL: http://www.ivs.au.dk/reposs

  • Lakatos, I. (1970). History of science and its rational reconstructions. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 1970, 91–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and Refutations. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landry, E. & Marquis, J-P. (2005). Categories in context: Historical, Foundational and Philosophical. Philos. Math., 13, 1–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laubenbacher, R. & Pengelley, D. (1992). Great problems of mathematics: A course based on original sources. American Mathematical Monthly, 99, 313–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laubenbacher, R., Pengelley, D. and Siddoway, M. (1994). Recovering motivation in mathematics: Teaching with original sources. Undergraduate Mathematics Education Trends 6, No. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laubenbacher, R., & Pengelley, D. (1999). Mathematical Expeditions: Chronicles by the Explorers. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lerman (1990). Alternative Perspectives on the Nature of Mathematics and their Influence on the Teaching of Mathematics. British Educational Research Journal 16 (1), 53–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lützen, J. & Purkert, W. (1989). Conflicting Tendencies in the Historiography of Mathematics: M. Cantor and H. G. Zeuthen. In D. E. Rowe, J. McCleary, and E. Knobloch (eds.): The History of Modern Mathematics. Vol. 3. Proceedings of the Symposium on the History of Modern Mathematics (pp. 1–42), Vassar College, Poughkeepsie, New York, June 20–24, 1989. 3 volumes. Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lützen, J. & Ramskov, K. (1999). Kilder til matematikkens historie. Department of Mathematics, Copenhagen University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (1990). Realism in Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (1998): From Brouwer to Hilbert. The debate on the Foundations of mathematics in the 1920's. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (ed.) (2008). The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLarty, C. (2005). Mathematical Platonism’ Versus Gathering the Dead: What Socrates teaches Glaucon. Philosophia Mathematica 13, 115–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niss, M. (2001). University mathematics based on problem-oriented student projects: 25 years of experience with the Roskilde model. In D. Holton (Ed.), The teaching and learning of mathematics at University level: An ICMI study (pp. 153–165). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niss, M. (2004). The Danish “KOM” Project and possible consequences for teacher education. In Strässer, R., Brandell, G., Grevholm, B., & Helenius, O. (eds.). Educating for the Future: Proceedings of an International Symposium on Mathematics Teacher Education: Preparation of Mathematics Teachers for the Future. Malmö University, Sweden, 5–7 May 2003 (pp. 179–190). Göteborg: The Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niss, M. & Højgaard, T. (2011). Competencies and Mathematical Learning. Ideas and inspiration for the development of mathematics teaching and learning in Denmark. IMFUFA-text 485. http://milne.ruc.dk/ImfufaTekster/

  • Otte, M. (2007). Mathematical history, philosophy and education. Educational Studies of Mathematics, 66, 243–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poulsen, E. T. (2001). Matematikken og virkeligheden. In Niss (ed.) Matematikken og Verden. Fremads debatbøger — Videnskaben til debat (pp. 19–36). København: Fremad.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pengelley, D. (2002). The Bridge between the continuous and the discrete via original sources. In O. Bekken et al. (eds.) Study the Masters: The Abel-Fauvel Conference. National Center for Mathematics Education, University of Gothenburg, Sweden.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prediger, S. (2007). Philosophical reflections in mathematics classrooms. In K. François & JP. Van Bendegem (eds.) (2007), 43–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Restivo, S. (1993). The social life of mathematics. In Restivo et al. (eds.); Math worlds. Philosophical and Social Studies of Mathematics and Mathematics Education. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rashevsky, N. (1934). Physico-mathematical aspects of cellular multiplication and development. Cold Spring Harbor symposia on quantitative biology, II (pp. 188–198). Long Island, New York: Cold Spring Harbor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, M. (1999). Mathematics as a Science of Patterns. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H-J. (1997). Towards a History of Epistemic Things: Synthesizing Proteins in the Test Tube. Standford: Standford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salling Olesen, H. & Højgaard Jensen, J. (1999). Can ‘the university’ be revived in ‘late modernity’? In H. Salling Olesen and J. Højgaard Jensen (Eds.), Project studies: A late modern university reform? (pp. 9–24). Roskilde: Roskilde University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sannino (2009). Universe’s Bright and Dark Side. http://cp3-origins.dk/content/uploads/2009/09/Bright-Dark-Article-060920091.pdf Accessed 1 July 2012.

  • Sfard, A. (2000). On reform movement and the limits of mathematical discourse. Mathematical Thinking and Learning, 2(3), 157–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sfard, A. (2008). Thinking as Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1997). Philosophy of Mathematics. Structure and Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (2000). Thinking about mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skovmose, O. (2004). Critical mathematics education for the future. Regular lecture at ICME 10. http://www.icme10.dk/proceedings/pages/regular_pdf/RL_Ole_Skovsmose.pdf Accessed 1 July 2012.

  • Tappenden, J. (2006). The Riemannian Background to Frege’s Philosophy. In Ferreirós & Gray (2008), 97–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Timmermann, S. & Uhre, E. (2001). Generalizations in the theory of integration – an investigation of the Lebesgue integral, the Radon integral and the Perron integral. (In Danish). IMFUFA, text 403, Roskilde University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thurston, W. (1994). On Proof and progress in mathematics. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 30, 161–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toft, B. (2001). Matematik løser problemer. In: M. Niss (Ed.) Matematikken og Verden. Fremads debatbøger — Videnskaben til debat (pp. 158–179). København: Fremad.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tymoczko, T. (ed.) (1985). New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics. Boston: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Heijenoort, J. (1967): From Frege to Gödel. A source book in mathematical logic 1879–1931. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Kerkhove, B. & Van Bendegem, J.P. (2007). Perspectives on mathematical practices. Bringing Together Philosophy of Mathematics, Sociology of Mathematics, and Mathematics Education. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science Vol. 5, Springer-Verlag, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Kerkhove, B., De Vuyst & Van Bendegem (2010). Philosophical Perspectives on Mathematical Practices. Texts in Philosophy 12, College Publications, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. (1960). The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences. Communications in Pure and Applied Mathematics 13, 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tinne Hoff Kjeldsen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kjeldsen, T.H., Carter, J. (2014). The Role of History and Philosophy in University Mathematics Education. In: Matthews, M. (eds) International Handbook of Research in History, Philosophy and Science Teaching. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7654-8_26

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics