Skip to main content

Philosophy and the Secondary School Mathematics Classroom

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Abstract

Although much has been written about the philosophy for children programme in the academic literature (and the press), there is very little on philosophy and the mathematics classroom, and the little there is has tended to treat mathematics within the context of this programme. By contrast, however, this chapter proposes a radically different perspective whereby the mathematics teacher is the dominant authority and directs the discourse from the front of the class. The aim of this perspective is to move the class towards a deeper understanding of mathematics through philosophy that specifically involves a cultural-historical approach. To place this perspective in context, this chapter begins with a critique of the philosophy for children programme as presented in the literature and critiques the use of philosophy as a bolt-on to the mathematics already learnt.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   749.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Unfortunately this chapter does not discuss philosophy and undergraduate mathematics as this deserves a chapter in its own right. At this level there is not only a change in content (with an emphasis on formalism and rigour) but also a variety of teaching/learning methods that may not be so appropriate at the secondary school level. Nevertheless Pincock’s (2012) Mathematics and Scientific Representation would be most appropriate as a text for this level.

  2. 2.

    Although there were great mathematical advances prior to the Greeks, the Greeks created deductive proof and the necessary theoretical objects to accomplish it, culminating in the axiomatic framework of the Elements. There was nothing like it beforehand and nothing like it until the nineteenth century when much of mathematics was rewritten in axiomatic form. Prior human achievements in mathematics notwithstanding, Greek deductive geometry was the most stunning advance, and there is a sense in which ‘history’ begins two and a half thousand years ago – especially since over that period to learn mathematics was to learn the Elements (to the delight or chagrin of many pupils).

    This is not by any means to undervalue the educational potential in introducing the mathematics of, for example, the Babylonians (is the 360° in the angle measure of a circle now a matter of convention or was there an objective reason for adopting it? Is there a need for base-ten compared with base-60? What prompted their recipe for what is today expressed as the quadratic formula?). However, this article is primarily about engaging pupils consciously with justification and proof, the abstract theoretical objects that were created for the purpose and the impact both culturally and cognitively.

  3. 3.

    For a theoretical overview of this perspective see Carson and Rowlands (2007); for validation see Rowlands (2010).

  4. 4.

    Perhaps this whole debate concerning schoolchildren, philosophy and religious belief can be resolved if religious education and worship are thrown out of schools. Perhaps the UK should adopt the US model whereby state education excludes any form of worship and religious instruction. The school should be seen as an induction into rationality and reason to which faith and indoctrination have no place.

  5. 5.

    Although most of the mathematics of the NC supposedly reflects mathematical practice in the real world, as Noss (1997) and Dowling and Noss (1990) point out, it does not even do that.

  6. 6.

    From a sample of adults performing a classification task, Wason (1977) shows how even adults deny the relevance of facts or contradict themselves, and how conceptual conflict can arise when the force of a contradictory assertion is denied. This implies that even adults do not acquire the rules of logic just because they speak. The Lipman and colleagues assertion is therefore unwarranted.

  7. 7.

    According to Vygotsky (1987), concepts are not absorbed ready-made by the child but undergo a process of development. Initially, the concept may begin as a complex; for example, the child might use ‘dog’ not as a member of ‘animal’ but as an ‘associative complex’ extended to inanimate objects with fur. A complex often relies on perceptual features. For example, children who think in complexes may successfully complete a classification problem involving geometrical shapes, so the child might appear to think in concepts – until the child attempts a borderline example, such as a trapezium looking very much like a parallelogram, in which the child classifies as a parallelogram without thinking of how a parallelogram is defined (see Vygotsky 1987). The point being the child might not even think in concepts, let alone concepts that may be deemed philosophical.

  8. 8.

    ‘Many [children] found convincing a view which could well be labelled constructivist – that infinity is not something we imagined as complete, but was a result of the fact that there was no stopping point, that infinity just kept going on. We then turned to measuring infinity and, having detoured through Cantor’s proof that the number of integers was equivalent to the number of even integers, ended on a note of indecision’ (De la Garza et al. 2000).

  9. 9.

    This is not, however, an instructional unit on philosophy and mathematics (Jankvist’s modules approach) nor is it a course that pursues a particular philosophy of mathematics (Jankvist’s philosophy approach).

  10. 10.

    Of course a little historical excursion can reveal how the Sophists used indivisibles and how the school allied to Plato used Eudoxus’ method of exhaustion. The two can be compared in Archimedes’s various proofs for the quadrature of the parabola (and the Palimpsest, the book where Archimedes uses indivisibles, has itself a wonderful history).

  11. 11.

    At the secondary level the aim has more to do with developing an understanding of mathematics itself (and its place in terms of impact) than it has with understanding its history. The same with philosophy; for example, a secondary school mathematics teacher doesn’t raise Plato’s distinction between knowledge and belief because it happens to be a good thing to know, but because it illuminates the concept of proof.

  12. 12.

    And as far as the majority of English and Welsh classrooms are concerned, proof no longer exists and perhaps because many teachers and curriculum designers can remember the negative experience of having to regurgitate proof in examinations. For some educationalists, proof means rote learning.

  13. 13.

    Even social constructivists such as Paul Ernest love and rely on Godel’s proof, even though they don’t like proofs in general (Ernest goes so far as to regard proof as Eurocentric and its glorification racist). This and other social constructivist contradictions can be found in Rowlands et al. (2010).

References

  • Barnes, J. (1987), Early Greek Geometry. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boden, M. A. (1994), What is Creativity? In (M. A. Boden, ed.) Dimensions of Creativity. London: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carson, R. N. & Rowlands, S. (2007), Teaching the conceptual revolutions in geometry. Science & Education 16, pp. 921–954.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, A. F. (1982), What is this thing called science? (second edition). Milton Keynes: the Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clegg, B (2003), A brief history of infinity: the quest to think the unthinkable. London: Constable and Robinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniel, M. F., Lafortune, L., Pallascio, R. & Sykes, P. (2000), A primary school curriculum to foster thinking about mathematics, Encyclopaedia of Philosophy of Education. http://www.ffst.hr/ENCYCLOPAEDIA (accessed 06/06/2011).

  • De La Garza, M. T., Slade-Hamilton, C. & Daniel, M. F. (2000), Philosophy of mathematics in the classroom: aspects of a tri-national study, Analytic Teaching, 20(2), 88–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowling, P. & Noss, R. (1990), Mathematics versus the National Curriculum. London: Falmer Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. (2005), Teaching children to think (second edition). Cheltenham: Nelson Thornes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gombrich, E. H. (1960), Art and Illusion. London: Phaidon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goos, M (2004), Learning mathematics in a classroom community of inquiry. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 35(4), pp. 258–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hand, M. (2008), Can children be taught philosophy? In (M. Hand & C. Winstanley, eds.) Philosophy in Schools. pp. 3–17. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iversen, S. M. (2009), Modeling interdisciplinary activities involving mathematics and philosophy, in (B. Sriraman, V. Freiman & N. Litette-Pitre, eds.) Interdisciplinarity, Creativity and learning: Mathematics with Literature, Paradoxes, History, Technology, and Modeling. pp. 85–98. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jankvist, U. T. (2012), History, applications, and philosophy in mathematics education: HAPh – A use of primary sources. Science & Education (online).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, N. S. (2007), From philosophical to mathematical inquiry in the classroom. Childhood & Philosophy, 3(6). http://www.filoeduc.org/childphilo/n6/Nadia_Kennedy.pdf. (Accessed 15/07/2011)

  • Kline, M. (1972), Mathematics in Western Culture. Harmondsworth: Pelican.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kunimune, S., Fujita, T. & Jones, K. (2009), “Why do we have to prove this?” Fostering students’ understanding of ‘proof’ in geometry in lower secondary school, in (F-L. Lin, F-J. Hsieh, G. Hanna, & M. de Villers, eds.), Proof and proving in mathematics education ICMI study 19 conference proceedings, Vol. 1, pp. 256–261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Law, S. (2008), Religion and philosophy in schools. In (M. Hand & C. Winstanley, eds.) Philosophy in Schools. pp. 41–57. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenton, D. & Vidion, B. (2011), Is philosophy what you think it is? PTU Focus article. Primary Teacher Update. Number 1, October. MA Education Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lightfoot, L. (2011), Time to take the won’t out of Kant, Tespro (number 3), supplement to The Times Higher Education Supplement, 30th September, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipman, M., Sharp, A. M. & Oscanyon, F. S. (1980), Philosophy in the classroom (second edition). Philadelphia: Temple University press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, G. (1980), Philosophy and the Young Child, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, G. (2008), Getting beyond the deficit conception of childhood: thinking philosophically with children. In (M. Hand & C. Winstanley, eds.) Philosophy in Schools. pp. 27–40. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCall, C. C. (2009), Transforming thinking: philosophical inquiry in the primary and secondary classroom. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noss, R. (1997), "Call to end ‘dumbing-down' of school mathematics". http://www.ioe.ac.uk/media/R071097A.HTM Accessed, 15/03/2003.

  • Pincock, C. (2012), Mathematics and Scientific Representation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prediger, S. (2007), Philosophical reflections in mathematics classrooms, in (K François & J. P. Van Bendegem, eds.) Philosophical Dimensions in Mathematics Education, pp. 43–58. Mathematics Education Library volume 42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, S. & Davies, A. (2006), Mathematics Masterclass: Is mathematics invented or discovered? Mathematics in School (journal of the Mathematics Association), 35(2), pp. 2–6. Also reprinted in Mathematics in Schools, 2011, 40(2), pp. 30–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, S. (2009), The importance of cultivating a meta-discourse in deliberate support of metacognition, in (C. B. Larson, ed.) Metacognition: New research developments. pp. 1–22. New York: Nova.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, S. (2010), A pilot study of a cultural-historical approach to teaching geometry. Science & Education, 19, pp. 55–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, S., Graham, T. and Berry, J. (2010). Problems with fallibilism as a philosophy of mathematics education. Science & Education (online)

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, S. (2011), Discussion article: Disciplinary boundaries for creativity, Creative Education, 2(1), pp. 47–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schoenfeld, A. H. (1989), What’s all the fuss about metacognition? In (A. H. Schoenfeld, ed.) Cognitive science and mathematics education. pp. 189–215. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegal, H. (2008), Why teach epistemology in schools? In (M. Hand & C. Winstanley, eds.) Philosophy in Schools. pp. 78–84. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skemp, R. R. (1971), The Psychology of Learning Mathematics. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skemp, R. R. (1976), Relational understanding and instrumental understanding, Mathematics Teaching, 77, pp. 20–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tall, D. & Gray, E. (1994), Duality, ambiguity and flexibility: A proceptual view of simple arithmetic, The Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 26(2), pp. 115–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. (1987), The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky: Problems of general psychology, including the volume thinking and speech. New York: Plenum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. (1994), The Vygotsky Reader, ed. by R. van der Veer & J. Valsiner. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wason, P. C. (1977), Self contradiction, in (P. N. Johnson-Laird & P. C. Wason. eds), Thinking: Readings in cognitive science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stuart Rowlands .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rowlands, S. (2014). Philosophy and the Secondary School Mathematics Classroom. In: Matthews, M. (eds) International Handbook of Research in History, Philosophy and Science Teaching. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7654-8_22

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics