Skip to main content

Do Historians Study the Mechanisms of History? A Sketch

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Explanation in the Special Sciences

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 367))

Abstract

In this exploratory sketch, I move across the boundaries of philosophy of historiography to social science and its philosophy. If we want to answer the central question of this chapter, we need to know what types of scientific problems historians are interested in, what history is, and what mechanisms are. I sketch the most prominent theories of social mechanisms in the context of wider ontological approaches. I investigate Mario Bunge’s “Emergentist Systemism,” “Critical Realism” in the tradition of Roy Bhaskar’s influential philosophy, and Daniel Little’s “Methodological Localism.” Since it turns out that mechanisms are taken to be rather different entities, the question is only answered trivially, but some problems are suggested that need to be separated if the debate shall not end up in “mechanism talk.” It is also suggested that philosophers of historiography can find in these debates what they are normally not interested in, that is, science-oriented philosophy of history.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Since the above is as much to be taken literally as it is polemic and, as I have been told, easily misunderstood, I should make explicit the following claims about the academic game around philosophy of historiography. First, philosophy of historiography cannot help us in answering the first part of the question because it is not interested in what historians do, that is, it does not care at all about research conducted by historians. Most philosophy of historiography is about “narratives.” Although there are more concepts of narrative around than there are narrativist philosophers, from the view taken here, these approaches are mostly irrelevant to a philosophy of Geschichtswissenschaft. (If you have no qualms about doing so, call it “historiography.”) Scientific historians simply do not get degrees for writing pleasant narratives but for solving scientific problems, although they might gain a Nobel Prize and the attention of philosophers of historiography by painting such “narratives.” Second, philosophers of historiography cannot tell us anything about history because the ontology of history was famously buried as speculative already in the 1950s and the concept was completely moved to methodology or exchanged with “the past.” See as a paradigm Marrou (1975 [1954], p. 29): “L’histoire est la connaissance du passé humain (…).” As anybody knows, this is no accident but the result of speculative metaphysics of the one history and its course. Put in a memorable yet unclear slogan, we can thus say that official philosophy of history is not about history. A presupposition of this paper is, to the contrary of the tradition in philosophy of historiography, that the concept of history belongs to ontology anyhow. If this presupposition is wrong, the question of this chapter does not make any sense. As we will see, it is doubtful that it does.

  2. 2.

    I use the label coined by Wan (2011a) to refer to Bunge’s system.

  3. 3.

    For further recent literature and different traditions of thinking about social mechanisms that I will not discuss directly on this occasion although they have in part intersections with the theories that I sketch and are equally relevant, see, for example, Lawson (1997), Hedström and Swedberg (1998), Tilly et al. (2001), Barberi (2004), Bennett and George (2005), Cherkaoui (2005), Manicas (2006), Pickel (2006), Schmid (2006), Wight (2006), Elster (2007), Glynos and Howarth (2007), Kurki (2008), Moessinger (2008), Elder-Vass (2010), Demeulenaere (2011), Wan (2011a).

  4. 4.

    This chapter might not be without interest to historians because these philosophies have hardly received attention in philosophy of historiography, which is my point of departure here, and they have not been discussed among historians themselves, although they deal with questions permanently discussed in their circles. Exceptions are to be found in (McLennan 1981; Gibbon 1989; Lloyd 1986) in the case of Roy Bhaskar’s work. Bunge’s work has been ignored so far, perhaps because of his claim that historiology is the most rigorous of all the social sciences and due to his robust ontological and epistemological realism; see, for example, Bunge (1985, 1988, 1998a).

  5. 5.

    On Bunge’s materialism, see Bunge (1977, 1981, 2002), Mahner (2001), Bunge and Mahner (2004). If not indicated otherwise, references in the text concern the work of the author mainly discussed in the respective section.

  6. 6.

    The basic slogan of this ontology is therefore (Bunge 2004a, p. 191): “everything in the universe is, was, or will be a system or a component of one.”

  7. 7.

    Cf. (Bunge 1996, p. 21): “The structure of a system is its key emergent property.” See also (Bunge 2010, p. 379).

  8. 8.

    Mere heaps are sometimes called “statistical wholes,” for example crowds, classes and institutions. Systems like gangs or firms are called “ontic wholes.” For this distinction and the examples, see (Bunge 2004b, p. 372). For Bunge’s concepts of group and class, see (Bunge 1995, Chap. 3).

  9. 9.

    On the problem concerning the boundaries of social systems, see (Bunge 1992a).

  10. 10.

    For the concept of a bond or link and similar notions, see Bunge (1977, p. 261, 1979a, p. 225, 1992a, b, 1993b); Bunge and Mahner (2004, p. 73).

  11. 11.

    We should note here that there is a family of concepts around the notion of emergence in ES that should be distinguished at this point. Emergent properties are, of course, properties (see below). Emergence is a process in which an emergent property comes into existence. An emergent is a thing possessing some emergent property.

  12. 12.

    These examples are all taken from Bunge’s work; see Bunge (1977, p. 97; 1979b, p. 20; 1996, 19f.; 1999, p. 8; 2003a, p. 13), Mahner (2001, p. 298).

  13. 13.

    On this account, expressions such as “historical events,” “historical processes,” “historical facts,” or “historical societies” are pleonasms and talk of “historicity” is trivial; cf., Bunge and Mahner (1997, p. 20).

  14. 14.

    Of course, in ES everything whatsoever has a history, whether it happens to be a boot maker or a coffee maker; cf., Bunge (1977, p. 255).

  15. 15.

    See Veyne (1996, 153f.), who happens to be a historian: “La France ne fait pas la guerre, car elle n’existe pas réellement; seul existent des Français (…). Pour un historien comme pour tout homme, ce qui est proprement réel, ce sont les individus.” Sztompka (1991, 188), who is a sociologist, does not nod: “[T]he army is more than soldiers, a corporation more than all those employed, and Poland more than all Poles.”

  16. 16.

    For reasons of space and complexity we cannot here discuss the whole story and this should remind us of the circumstance that my reading of Bunge is far from infallible. But first of all, Bunge has suggested for a long time that not every determinant of change is a causal determinant (Bunge 1982, 2009 [1959]). The structure of a social system (macro property) and even its subset of spatial relations, for instance, in a production line as a sub-system of a factory, might determine the output of the system (macro property). But in ES this is far from stating that these relations cause actions or changes in the properties of social systems, though they determine the possible state of the system before and while causation is going on through people’s hands. In some examples Bunge (1996, p. 280; 2000a) talks of macro-causation in terms which might turn out to be problematic, for example, when it is suggested that actions are causally stimulated or constrained by the place the individual holds in a system. Of course, this is not problematic if one remembers that such descriptions are most often short for complex interactions and their patterns, though the place or role an individual holds in a system is in ES emergent and systemic.

  17. 17.

    The examples are taken from Bunge’s work.

  18. 18.

    A quick look at the development of Bunge’s thinking on mechanisms and mechanismic explanation suggests that he started off with a theory that tended tacitly to conflate these categories, whereas his long-lived project of systems ontology lead to their strict separation yet systematization. See Bunge (2009a [1959], 1965, 1967, 1968, 1983, 1998b). If one is to believe Wan (2011a), it seems that the current literature on mechanisms moves in the opposite direction.

  19. 19.

    On Bunge’s concept of function, see Bunge and Mahner (2001).

  20. 20.

    Or more formally (Bunge 2006, p. 131; cf. 2004a; 2010): “Definition 1: If σ denotes a system of kind Σ, then (1) the totality of processes (or functions) in σ over the period T is π(σ) = The ordered sequence of states of σ over T; (2) the essential mechanism (or specific function) in σ over the period T, that is, M(σ) = πs(s) ⊆ π(s), is the totality of processes that occur exclusively in σ and its conspecifics during T. Definition 2: A social mechanism is a mechanism of a social system or part of it.”

  21. 21.

    Perfect knowledge of a system would also include its history and its laws; see Bunge (1979a, p. 8). The reader will have noticed that mechanisms have been included in the ideal model of a system in Bunge’s philosophy fairly recently, although he is thinking about mechanisms since the 1950s.

  22. 22.

    See, for example, Benton (1977), Outhwaite (1987a), Archer (1995), Danermark et al. (2002), Groff (2004), Manicas (2006), Frauley and Pearce (2007), Elder-Vass (2010), Sayer (2010a), Wan (2011a). In order to keep track of history, Bhaskar’s work is cited by the date of the original publication.

  23. 23.

    See Bhaskar (1978, p. 51): “The world consists of things, not events.” See also Bhaskar (1978, 47): “The world consists of mechanisms not events.”

  24. 24.

    See Bhaskar (1994, p. 74): “The human world is an irreducible and causally efficacious dependent mode of matter.”

  25. 25.

    On Bhaskar’s emergentism in comparison to that of Bunge, see Kaidesoja (2009).

  26. 26.

    See also Bhaskar (1978, p. 85): “Societies, people and machines are not collectivities, wholes or aggregates of simpler or smaller constituents.”

  27. 27.

    Sometimes similarities between both ontologies are noted though the differences are seldom made explicit. For comparisons see Kaidesoja (2007, 2009), Wan (2011a, 2011b).

  28. 28.

    Harré and Madden (1975, p. 47). I will here not address the problem of the relationship of Harré’s work to that of Bhaskar. But it is worth reminding that the concept of mechanism as used in CR has its basis in Harré’s work of the 1960s and early 1970s. See Harré (1961, 1970, 1972).

  29. 29.

    For a discussion of problems around these central notions in CR, see Fleetwood (2009, 2011).

  30. 30.

    The background of this ontology is of course an anti-positivist stance in form of the hypothesis that “the real” is not exhausted by perceptions of events or events, especially “[s]ociety is not a mass of separable events and sequences” (1979, p. 68). These assumptions are at the heart of the three ontological domains of CR (1978): “the real” (structures, powers, totalities etc.), “the actual” (events), and “the empirical” (observed events).

  31. 31.

    See Bhaskar (1989, p. 10) reminiscent of Marx: “In the constant conjunction form history grinds to a halt in the eternalized present. History is what there has been or is elsewhere but is no longer here now.”

  32. 32.

    See also another classic formulation by Bhaskar (1978, p. 50): “[T]he generative mechanisms of nature exist as the causal powers of things.”

  33. 33.

    In Sayer (2010a, p. 15; 2010b, p. 117) we find a slightly shorter schema: structures → mechanisms → events.

  34. 34.

    If we read “act as generative mechanisms” as “resulting in actual processes,” then we might already here get the hypothesis that mechanisms are processes, though this seems to be against the spirit of the letter. We get that result in the next footnote.

  35. 35.

    To round up the story, we have to add here that according to Bhaskar (1994, 257f.), processes or rhythms also have powers, and according to Hartwig (2007, p. 189), events might also “function as mechanisms,” which seems to amount to the claim that events possess powers of their own beyond the powers that are grounded in or emergent from the structure or essence of the thing that undergoes a change in the event. For short, events and processes might also be powerful dispositional mechanisms.

  36. 36.

    For example, Wight (2006, p. 31), affiliated to the tradition of CR, writes of “the causal power of mechanisms.”

  37. 37.

    Cf. Kurki (2008, p. 233).

  38. 38.

    On “rhythms” see Bhaskar (1993, 1994).

  39. 39.

    On the more narrow CR conception of society, it does not consist of individuals or groups or some such circumstances but of internal relations: “A relation aRb is internal if and only if a would not be what it is essentially unless it were related to b in the way that it is.” See Bhaskar (1993, 10); see, also Bhaskar (1994, 75; 1979, 32, 54). This theory has implications for the philosophy of social change (Bhaskar 1979, 52): “In social life only relations endure.”

  40. 40.

    Here we also have to admit that the story is far more complex. There has been a discussion about this point in CR that resulted in the acceptance of social powers or dispositions that do not just exist as exercised or actualized powers. Cf., Porpora 2007.

  41. 41.

    See Bhaskar (1978, p. 51): “Most things are complex objects, in virtue of which they possess an ensemble of tendencies, liabilities and powers.”

  42. 42.

    To grant “unobservables – such as ideas, rules and discourses,” a causal role, which seem to be “non-agent-like factors,” Kurki (2008, pp. 170–174) frames the concept of an “ontological object” that is not supposed to be a “‘thing’” (ibid. p. 169). Contrary to this, Kaidesoja (2007) argues that something like a Bungean complex thing is necessary to ascribe something a power and wants to correct CR in this direction.

  43. 43.

    See the criticism by Harré (2002), Harré and Varela (1996). Famously Lloyd (1993, p. 46) already distinguished two types of powers: “Persons have agential power, structures have conditioning power.”

  44. 44.

    For the claim that money has an essence, see Bhaskar (1978, p. 88).

  45. 45.

    He seems to have been influenced by the work of Rom Harré; see Little (1989; 1991). For the precursor of mechanisms, see Little (1986) and the “logic of an institution.”

  46. 46.

    As far as I can see, Little quotes only Bhaskar’s “Realist Theory of Science,” in which the TMSA was not developed; cf. Little (2011, p. 278).

  47. 47.

    To avoid misunderstanding, one should distinguish two claims under the heading social causation. The first is the claim that social macro stuff causes individual action. The second is that there is social macro-macro-causation whether through action or not; cf., already Sztompka (1991, p. 58). Of course, one could deny both claims. The easiest way to deny CR and ML styled social causation is to claim that “there are no structures” (Harré 2009, p. 138).

  48. 48.

    As is well known in CR, the sociologist Margaret Archer (1995) formulated a similar theory.

  49. 49.

    Although, as far as I can see, there is no concept analogous to structurally emergent properties in ES that accounts theoretically for this claim in ML. But this concept would not fit in here anyway because ML institutions or structures are, as it seems, not Bungean things or systems.

  50. 50.

    A difference to Bunge’s ontology is remarkable at this point, given that social states can be found neither in individuals’ brains nor in individual actions according to ES (Bunge 1996, p. 45). Whereas in ES poking one’s nose is not a social fact but an individual one, though poking another’s nose or each other’s noses are social facts, in ML the former is a social fact and a social action, as is eating breakfast cereals or smoking for oneself in private, since we have somehow acquired every taste or preference by someone; cf. Little (2007, p. 351f.).

  51. 51.

    To be more exact, Little writes (2007, p. 360, emphasis added): ML “is not equivalent to methodological individualism or reductionism because it admits that social arrangements and circumstances affect individual action. For it is entirely likely that a microfoundational account of the determinants of individual action will include reference to social relations, norms, structures, cognitive frameworks, etc.”

  52. 52.

    In ES this would be expressed by the claim that social systems (e.g., families) are as real as their members, face a social environment and might be the components of higher-level systems (e.g., villages), whereas it is apparently unclear what a village is in ML, given that it seems to be rather odd to say that it is a set of opportunities or a system of rules.

  53. 53.

    Let us take the risk to pose some naïve questions: Which is the disposition or power of, say, a mentality? Is a mentality, or a norm (or what have you), a property? If yes, of what? If it is not a property of something, where is it floating? In a different context, Sztompka (1991, p. 23) has seen clearly the problem we seem to face: “In modern sociology one may find such fashionable and influential notions as ‘habitus’ (Bourdieu), ‘historicity’ (Touraine), ‘figurations’ (Elias), ‘mobilization’ (Etzioni), ‘anomie’ (Merton), ‘duality of structure’ (Giddens), ‘agency’ (Archer) – and many others. It is not easy to say what exactly the referents of these concepts are, what kinds of objects are described, because clearly they are neither people nor systems.”

  54. 54.

    See the quote in note 51. Causation might be one thing, explanation quite another. To say the same more carefully, one should be careful not to slide into an ontological misinterpretation of the famous “Thomas Theorem,” which says “If men define situations as real they are real in their consequences” (quoted in Sztompka 1991, 83, emphasis added). Of course, there might be nothing social beyond or behind the heads of people that has “powers” or the former consequences, that is, that causes actions or social changes. Because of such worries Boudon (2010, 23) calls powers or causes such as mentalities or social structures “forces fantomatiques.” Again, this is only supposed to indicate that there is something problematic about social causation or social powers.

  55. 55.

    For such criticisms see again (Lewis 2000; Harré 2002; Manicas 2006; Kaidesoja 2007).

  56. 56.

    Little (1991, p. 15): “A causal mechanism (…) is a series of events governed by lawlike regularities that lead from the explanans to the explanandum.” That mechanisms are chains of events is still suggested in his recent work when he writes that mechanisms have two ends; cf. Little (2011, 278).

  57. 57.

    Nota bene, philosophers of historiography, many historians and sociologists constantly talk about such an overarching history or they never make explicit what they believe they are talking about while writing about history in a realist or ontic sense.

  58. 58.

    This also holds for formerly notorious questions about the role of “laws” in historico-social science. Whereas for Bunge “mechanisms without conceivable laws are called ‘miracles’” (2006, p. 135), Little’s ML claims to be something like a counterprogram to the usefulness of social “laws,” whereas critical realists seem to accept restricted (“historical”) tendencies as such “laws.” For problems critical realist have with the notion of a law, see Outhwaite (1987b). Recently, there has emerged a powerful tendency towards an affirmative consensus in twenty-first century philosophy of historiography concerning the claim that the people that are called historians constantly invoke “laws”; see, for example, Klinger (1997), Di Nuoscio (2004), Antiseri (2005), Frings (2007), Berry (2008), Leuridan and Froeyman (2012).

  59. 59.

    Bhaskar, of course, saw himself the problems that can occur in realist social ontologies (1982, 283): “Talk of ‘emergence’ can easily become vague and general, if not indeed laced with frankly idealist or romantic overtones.”

  60. 60.

    For lots of examples, see (Little 1989, 2010).

  61. 61.

    Since we cannot discuss all the differences in these frameworks and I do not claim to be a metaphysician anyhow, let us list which notions are at stake in this debate: thing, property, types of properties, social property, change and transformation, event (historical), process, history, mechanism, structure, system, society, organization, institution, fact, social fact, causation and determination, energy and causal power, laws, agency, agents and action, levels, micro-x vs. macro-x, emergence, etc.

  62. 62.

    Because this variety of ontology of history would take its stock of questions from debates among historians and social scientists, on the one hand, and the implications or presuppositions of their research, on the other hand, I call it loosely “science-oriented”.

References

  • Antiseri, D. (2005). Epistemologia e didattica della storia. Le ragioni della storiografia locale. In E. Di Nuoscio (Ed.), Conoscere per tracce. Epistemologia e storiografia. Milano: Edizioni Unicopli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archer, M. (1995). Realist social theory: The morphogenetic approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barberi, F. (2004). Meccanismi sociali. Elementi di sociologia analitica. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, A., & George, A. L. (2005). Case studies and theory development in the social sciences. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benton, T. (1977). Philosophical foundations of the three sociologies. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berry, S. (2008). Laws in history. In A. Tucker (Ed.), A companion to philosophy of history and historiography (pp. 162–171). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (1979). The possibility of naturalism. A philosophical critique of the contemporary human sciences. Brighton: The Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (1982). Emergence, explanation, and emancipation. In P. F. Secord (Ed.), Explaining human behavior. Consciousness, human action and social structure (pp. 275–310). Beverly Hills: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (1983). Beef, structure and place: Notes from a critical naturalist perspective. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 13, 81–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (1994). Plato etc. The problems of philosophy and their resolution. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (2008 [1978]). A realist theory of science. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (2008 [1993]). Dialectic. The pulse of freedom. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (2009 [1986]). Scientific realism and human emancipation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (2011 [1989]) Reclaiming reality. A critical introduction to contemporary philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (2001). How to change reality: Story v. structure – a debate between Rom Harré and Roy Bhaskar. In J. Lopez & G. Potter (Eds.), After postmodernism. An introduction to critical realism (pp. 22–39). London: The Athlone Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blaikie, N. (1993). Approaches to social enquiry. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudon, R. (2010). La sociologie comme science. Paris: La Découverte.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1965). Phenomenological theories. In M. Bunge (Ed.), The critical approach to science and philosophy (pp. 234–254). London: The Free Press of Glencoe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1967). Scientific research (Vol. 2). Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1968). The maturation of science. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Problems in the philosophy of science (pp. 120–137). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1974). Les présupposés et les produits métaphysiques de la science et de la technique contemporaines. Dialogue, 13, 443–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1977). The furniture of the world. Treatise on basic philosophy, Ontology I (Vol. 3). Dordrecht: D Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1979a). A world of systems. Treatise on basic philosophy, Ontology II (Vol. 4). Dordrecht: D Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1979b). A systems concept of society: Beyond individualism and holism. Theory and Decision, 10, 13–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1981). Scientific materialism. Dordrecht: D Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1982). The revival of causality. In G. Floistad (Ed.), Contemporary philosophy. A new survey, philosophy of science (Vol. 2, pp. 133–155). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1983). Understanding the world. Treatise on basic philosophy, epistemology & methodology II (Vol. 6). Dordrecht: D Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1984). Das Leib-Seele-Problem. Ein psychobiologischer Versuch. Tübingen: J C B Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1985). Life science, social science and technology. Treatise on basic philosophy, epistemology & methodology III: Philosophy of science and technology (Vol. 7). Dordrecht: D Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1988). The scientific status of history. In U. Hinke-Dörnemann (Ed.), Die Philosophie in der modernen Welt. Gedenkschrift für Prof. Dr. med. Dr. phil. Alwin Diemer, Teil 1 (pp. 592–602). Frankfurt: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1992a). System boundary. International Journal of General Systems, 20, 215–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1992b). Systems everywhere. In C. V. Negoita (Ed.), Cybernetics and applied systems (pp. 23–41). New York: M Dekker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1993a). Realism and antirealism in social science. Theory and Decision, 35, 207–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1993b). Social systems. In R. R. Delgado & B. H. Banathy (Eds.), International systems science handbook (pp. 210–221). Madrid: Systemic Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1995). Sistemas sociales y filosofía. Buenos Aires: Editorial Sudamericana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1996). Finding philosophy in social science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1997). Mechanism and explanation. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 27, 410–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1998a). Social science under debate: A philosophical perspective. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1998b). Philosophy of science (Vol. 2). New Brunswick: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (1999). The sociology-philosophy connection. New Brunswick: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2000a). Systemism: The alternative to individualism and holism. Journal of Socio-Economics, 29, 147–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2000b). Ten modes of individualism – none of which works – and their alternatives. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 30, 384–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2001a). Systems and emergence, rationality and imprecision, free-wheeling and evidence, science and ideology: Social science and its philosophy according to van den Berg. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 31, 404–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2001b). Philosophy in crisis. The need for reconstruction. Amherst: Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2002). Ser, saber, hacer. México: Paidós.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2003a). Emergence and convergence. Qualitative novelty and the unity of knowledge. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2003b). Cápsulas. Barcelona: Gedisa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2003c). Philosophical dictionary. Amherst: Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2004a). How does it work? The search for explanatory mechanisms. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34, 182–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2004b). Clarifying some misunderstandings about social systems and their mechanisms. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34, 371–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2006). Chasing reality. Strife over realism. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2007). Review of Dissecting the social. On the principles of analytical sociology, by Peter Hedström. American Journal for Sociology, 113, 258–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2008). Filosofía y sociedad. México: Siglo XXI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, MA. (2009a [1959]). Causality and modern science. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2009b). Political philosophy. Fact, fiction and vision. New Brunswick: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A. (2010). Soziale Mechanismen und mechanismische Erklärungen. Berliner Journal für Soziologie, 20, 371–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A., & Mahner, M. (1997). Foundations of biophilosophy. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A., & Mahner, M. (2001). Function and functionalism. A synthetic perspective. Philosophy of Science, 68, 75–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. A., & Mahner, M. (2004). Über die Natur der Dinge. Materialismus und Wissenschaft. Stuttgart: S Hirzel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cherkaoui, M. (2005). Invisible codes. Essays on generative mechanisms. Oxford: The Bardwell Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood, RG. (1994 [1946]). The idea of history. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danermark, B., Ekström, M., Jokobson, L., & Karlsson, J. C. (2002). Explaining society. Critical realism in the social sciences. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demeulenaere, P. (Ed.). (2011). Analytical sociology and social mechanisms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Nuoscio, E. (2004). Tucidide come Einstein? La spiegazione scientifica in storiografia. Soveria Mannelli: Rubbettino Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder-Vass, D. (2010). The causal power of social structures. Emergence, structure and agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (2007). Explaining social behavior. More nuts and bolts for the social sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fleetwood, S. (2009). The ontology of things, properties and powers. Journal of Critical Realism, 8, 343–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleetwood, S. (2011). Powers and tendencies revisited. Journal of Critical Realism, 10, 80–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frauley, J., & Pearce, F. (Eds.). (2007). Critical realism and the social sciences. Heterodox elaborations. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frings, A. (2007). Rationales Handeln und historisches Erklären. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 38, 31–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbon, G. (1989). Explanation in archaeology. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glynos, J., & Howarth, D. (2007). Logics of critical explanation in social and political theory. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Groff, R. (2004). Critical realism, post-positivism and the possibility of knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1961). Theories and things. A brief study in prescriptive metaphysics. London: Sheed and Ward.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1970). The principles of scientific thinking. London: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (1972). The philosophies of science. An introductory survey. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (2002). Social reality and the myth of social structure. European Journal of Social Theory, 5, 111–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (2009). Saving critical realism. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 39, 129–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., & Madden, E. H. (1975). Causal powers. A theory of natural necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., & Varela, C. M. (1996). Conflicting varieties of realism: Causal powers and the problems of social structure. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 26, 313–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartwig, M. (Ed.). (2007). Dictionary of critical realism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Swedberg, R. (Eds.). (1998). Social mechanisms: An analytical approach to social theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaidesoja, T. (2007). Exploring the concept of causal power in a critical realist tradition. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 37, 63–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaidesoja, T. (2009). Bhaskar and Bunge on social emergence. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 39, 300–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klinger, W. (1997). Legge e spiegazione in storia: un approccio naturalistico, Dissertation, Università degli Studi di Trieste.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurki, M. (2008). Causation in international relations. Reclaiming causal analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, T. (1997). Economics and reality. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leuridan, B., & Froeyman, A. (2012). On lawfulness in history and historiography. History and Theory, 51, 172–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. (2000). Realism, causality and the problem of social structure. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 30, 249–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (1986). The scientific Marx. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (1989). Understanding peasant China. Case studies in the philosophy of social science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (1991). Varieties of social explanation. An introduction to the philosophy of social science. Boulder: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (1998). Microfoundations, method, and causation: on the philosophy of the social sciences. New Brunswick: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (2007). Levels of the social. In S. P. Turner & M. W. Risjord (Eds.), Philosophy of anthropology and sociology (pp. 343–371). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (2009). The heterogenous social: new thinking about the foundations of the social sciences. In C. Mantzavinos (Ed.), Philosophy of the social sciences. Philosophical theory and scientific practice (pp. 154–178). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (2010). New contributions to the philosophy of history. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (2011). Causal mechanisms in the social realm. In P. Illari, F. Russo, & J. Williamson (Eds.), Causality in the sciences (pp. 273–295). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, C. (1986). Explanation in social history. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, C. (1993). The structures of history. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M. (Ed.). (2001). Scientific realism. Selected essays of Mario Bunge. Amherst: Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manicas, P. T. (2006). A realist philosophy of social science. Explanation and understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marrou, HI. (1975 [1954]). De la connaissance historique. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLennan, G. (1981). Marxism and the methodologies of history. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moessinger, P. (2008). Voir la sociéte. Le micro et le macro. Paris: Hermann Éditeurs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Outhwaite, W. (1987a). New philosophy of social science. Realism, hermeneutics and critical theory. Houndmills: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Outhwaite, W. (1987b). Laws and explanation in sociology. In R. J. Anderson, J. A. Hughes, & W. W. Sharrock (Eds.), Classic disputes in sociology (pp. 157–183). London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickel, A. (2006). The problem of order in the global age. Systems and mechanisms. New York: Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Porpora, D. V. (2007). Social structure. In M. Hartwig (Ed.), Dictionary of critical realism (pp. 422–425). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sayer, A. (2010a [2000]). Realism and social science. London: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sayer, A. (2010b). Method in social science. A realist approach. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, M. (2006). Die Logik mechanismischer Erklärungen. Wiesbaden: VS-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sewell, W. H. (2005). Logics of history. Social theory and social transformation. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sztompka, P. (1991). Society in action. The theory of social becoming. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tilly, C., McAdam, D., & Tarrow, S. (2001). Dynamics of contention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Topolski, J. (1976). Methodology of history. Dordrecht: D Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, A. (2012). Sciences of historical tokens and theoretical types: History and the social sciences. In H. Kincaid (Ed.), The oxford handbook of the philosophy of social science (pp. 274–297). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veyne, P. (1996 [1975]). Comment on écrit l’histoire. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wan, P. Y.-z. (2011a). Reframing the social. Emergentist systemism and social theory. Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wan, P. Y.-z. (2011b). Analytical sociology: A Bungean appreciation. Science and Education. doi:10.1007/s11191-011-9427-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wight, C. (2006). Agents, structures and international relations. Politics as ontology. Cambridge: Cambrige University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This study has been made possible by a grant of the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG) and was realized in the project Explanation, Laws and Causality in Historical Science, a subunit of the research group Causation, Laws, Dispositions and Explanation at the Intersection of Science and Metaphysics. I thank Oliver R. Scholz for saving me from the biggest nonsense in history. The flowers go, as always, to Eileen.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Plenge .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Plenge, D. (2014). Do Historians Study the Mechanisms of History? A Sketch. In: Kaiser, M.I., Scholz, O.R., Plenge, D., Hüttemann, A. (eds) Explanation in the Special Sciences. Synthese Library, vol 367. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7563-3_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics