Skip to main content

Harmonizing the Poles: A Note on Leibniz’s Notion of Justice

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Perspectives on Theory of Controversies and the Ethics of Communication

Part of the book series: Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning ((LARI,volume 2))

  • 821 Accesses

Abstract

Developing his new definition of justice in the six drafts of the Elements of Natural Law (1670–1671), Leibniz endeavors to settle two seemingly excluding assumptions underlying his preconception of justice. The first is that justice demands an active concern for the good of others. To be just, Leibniz insists, one must seek the good of others for its own sake, considering it an independent end and not only a means to one’s own benefit. The second assumption is that “there is no one who deliberately does anything except for the sake of his own good.” Adhering to the egoistic psychology of Hobbes and Carneades, Leibniz holds that “we seek the good also of those whom we love for the sake of the pleasure which we ourselves get from their happiness.” In the fourth draft, Leibniz appears to find the key to the solution of his problem. “The answer,” he writes, “certainly depends upon the nature of love.” “To love,” as he states earlier in this essay, “is to find pleasure in the happiness of another.” In this chapter I attempt of analyze the solution that Leibniz offers in this early essay and to question its coherency. I will argue further that an interesting hint of a possible solution to the problem may be drawn from his later writings on justice, where his notion of disinterested love becomes more explicit.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In this short lecture I discuss quite concisely Leibniz’s early definition of justice and his dialectical method. Obviously, there is much to be said about both issues, and a more developed analysis will have to wait for another article now in the works.

  2. 2.

    I am indebted to Ursula Goldenbaum for introducing me to this important issue a long time ago and for providing me with her scholarly studies on the topic (see her 2002: 209–231, 2003). For further various perspectives of the issue, see, for instance, Mulvaney (1968: 60ff.), Hostler (1975: 47–54, 57–59), Dascal (1993: 394–396, 1994: 113–115), Brown (1995: 411–441, esp. pp. 416–417, 425–426, 2011: 265–303), Riley (1996: 144–152), Piro (1999), and Naaman-Zauderer (2006).

  3. 3.

    According to Grua, Leibniz’s mature definition of justice as caritas sapientis occurred not before 1677 (Grua 1953: 2–3). See also Mulvaney (1968: 60, 72) and Riley (1996: 145).

  4. 4.

    In the Preface to the Codex Iuris Gentium of 1693, Leibniz writes that love “signifies rejoicing in the happiness of another, or, what is the same thing, converting the happiness of another into one’s own” (D IV, 295/ R 171). And he sometimes formulates his definition of love in terms of perfection, stating that “to love is to find pleasure in the perfection of another” (e.g., R 83).

  5. 5.

    “All people sense this, whatever they may say; or at least they act according to it, whatever they may believe” (A.VI.1: 464/ L136). As Christia Mercer has shown, moreover, the reflective nature of the mind and the image of the mind as a mirror, which Leibniz first develops between late 1669 and 1671 in the Elements of Natural Law, bears significant ethical implications for the increase in the goodness of other minds. See Mercer (2001: 219). The relevant passage which she addresses from the Elements of Natural Law is the following: “Pleasure, however, is doubled by reflection, whenever we contemplate the beauty within ourselves which our conscience make, not to speak of our virtue. But as a double refraction can occur in vision, once in the lens of the eye and once in the lens of a tube, the latter increasing the vision of the former, so there is a double reflection in thinking. For every mind is something like a mirror, and one mirror is in our mind, another in the mind of someone else. So if there are many mirrors, that is, many minds recognizing our good, there will be a greater light, the mirrors blending the light not only in the eye but also among each other” (A.VI.1: 464/L137). For the manner in which “Reflective Harmony,” in Mercer’s wording, enhances goodness of other minds, see Mercer (2001, ch. 6, 214–220).

  6. 6.

    Gregory Brown has recently objected to this interpretation, for various reasons, and has offered a different account of the dilemma that Leibniz attempts to resolve in this essay and of how this can be done (2011). Discussing his arguments would require me to exceed the scope of this paper and is left for a future article on the topic.

  7. 7.

    Fontenelle (1740: 448–449), cited in Garber (2009: xvi).

References

  • Brown, G. 1995. Leibniz’s moral philosophy. In The Cambridge companion to Leibniz, ed. N. Jolley, 411–441. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, G. 2011. Disinterested love: Understanding Leibniz’s reconciliation of self and other-regarding motives. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19(2): 265–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, M. 1993. One Adam and many cultures: The role of political pluralism in the best of possible worlds. In Leibniz and Adam, ed. M. Dascal and E. Yakira, 387–409. Tel Aviv: University Publishing Projects.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, M. 1994. Strategies of dispute and ethics: Du tort and La place d’autruy. In VI. Internationaler Leibniz-Kongress, 108–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, M., Q. Racionero, and A. Cardoso. (Trans and eds.). 2008. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz: The art of controversies, The new synthese historical library, vol. 60. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fontanelle, Berbard Le Bouvier de. 1740. Eloge de Monsieur Leibnitz. In Eloge des academiciens avec l’histoire de l’academic royale des sciences en M. DC. XCIC…, 424–480. The Hague: Isaac van der Kloot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, D. 2009. Leibniz: Body, substance, monad. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenbaum, U. 2002. All you need is love … Leibniz’s Vermittlung von Hobbes’ Naturrecht und christlicher Nächstenliebe als Grundlage seiner Definition der Gerechtigkeit. In Neuzeitliches Denken: Festshrift für Hans Poser zum 65. Geburtstag, ed. Günter Abel, Han-Jürgen Engfer, and Christoph Hubig, 209–231. Berlin/New York: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldenbaum, U. 2003. Leibniz’ concepts of love and justice as result of his struggle with Hobbes’ naturalism. Paper for the conference at Rice University at Easter 2003. Forthcoming as Sonderheft der Studia Leibnitiana, in M. Kulstad and M. Laerke (eds.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Grua, G. 1953. Jurisprudence universelle et théodicée selon Leibniz. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hostler, J. 1975. Leibniz’s moral philosophy. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercer, C. 2001. Leibniz’s metaphysics: Its origins and development. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mulvaney, R.J. 1968. The early development of Leibniz’s concept of justice. Journal of the History of Ideas 29: 53–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naaman-Zauderer, N. 2006. Rethinking Leibniz’s notions of justice, love and human motives. In Einheit in der Vielheit, VIII Internationaler Leibniz Kongreß, Hanover, 671–676.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naaman-Zauderer, N. 2008. The place of the other in Leibniz’s rationalism. In Leibniz: What kind of rationalist? ed. M. Dascal, 315–327. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Piro, F. 1999. Leibniz and ethics: The years 1669–1672. In The young Leibniz and his philosophy (1646–76), ed. S. Brown, 147–167. Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Riley, P. 1996. Leibniz’ universal jurisprudence: Justice as the charity of the wise. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Noa Naaman-Zauderer .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Abbreviations

Abbreviations

A :

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 1923–, Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe, Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin (eds.), Berlin: Akademie Verlag. References include series, volume, and page.

D :

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 1768, Opera Omnia, L. Dutens (ed.), de Tournes, Geneva.

DM :

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, Discourse on Metaphysics. References include section.

G :

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 1875–1890, Die philosophischen Schriften, C.I. Gerhardt (ed.), 7 vols., Berlin: Weidmann. References include volume and page.

GR :

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 1948, Textes inédits, G. Grua (ed.), Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

L :

 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 1969, Philosophical Papers and Letters, L. E. Loemker (trans. and ed.), 2nd edn, Dordrecht: Reidel.

NE :

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, New Essays Concerning Human Understanding. References include book, chapter, and section.

R :

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 1988, Political Writings, P. Riley (Trans. and ed.), 2nd edn, New York: Cambridge University Press.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Naaman-Zauderer, N. (2014). Harmonizing the Poles: A Note on Leibniz’s Notion of Justice. In: Riesenfeld, D., Scarafile, G. (eds) Perspectives on Theory of Controversies and the Ethics of Communication. Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning, vol 2. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7131-4_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics