Skip to main content

Environmental Grain, Organism Fitness, and Type Fitness

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Entangled Life

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 4))

Abstract

Natural selection is the result of organisms’ interactions with their environment, but environments vary in space and time, sometimes in extreme ways. Such variation is generally thought to play an important role in evolution by natural selection, maintaining genetic variation within and between populations, increasing the chance of speciation, selecting for plasticity of responses to the environment, and selecting for behaviors such as habitat selection and niche construction. Are there different roles that environmental variation plays in natural selection? When biologists make choices about how to divide up an environment for the sake of modeling or empirical research, are there any constraints on these choices? Since diverse evolutionary models relativize fitnesses to component environments within a larger environment, it would be useful to understand when such practices capture real aspects of evolutionary processes, and when they count as mere modeling conveniences. In this paper, I try to provide a general framework for thinking about how fitness and natural selection depend on environmental variation. I’ll give an account of how the roles of environmental conditions in natural selection differ depending the probability of being experienced repeatedly by organisms, and how environmental conditions combine probabilistically to help determine fitness. My view has implications for what fitness is, and suggests that some authors have misconceived its nature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Odling-Smee et al. (2003) treat habitat selection—cases in which organisms “choose” their subenvironment—as a form of niche construction. I use the latter term in a narrower sense requiring modification of the environment by organisms (cf. Sterelny 2005).

  2. 2.

    For example, the intensity with which a house sparrow nestling begs, influencing parents’ feeding behavior and subsequent nestling survival, seems to be the result of an earlier gene-environment interaction (Dor and Lotem 2009).

  3. 3.

    Smith and Varzi (e.g. (2002)) also discuss a concept of “environment,” which they take as equivalent to “niche,” but their discussion concerns issues which have little relevance here. More generally, niche concepts bring up issues other than those which are my focus (cf. Abrams 2009c).

  4. 4.

    This assumption is uncontroversial for many philosophers and biologists, but “statisticalist” philosophers of biology have challenged it (e.g. Walsh 2010; Matthen and Ariew 2009). Their arguments are addressed in many other publications, including some of my own.

  5. 5.

    The constrained arbitrariness of population definitions is illustrated by contemporary research using the Human Genome Diversity Panel (Li et al. 2008). For example, Thompson et al. (2004) divides this whole-genome data (from roughly 1,000 individuals) into 52 populations, while Moreno-Estrada et al. (2009) cluster the same data into 39 populations for some analyses, and seven populations for others.

  6. 6.

    I use “token fitness” rather than “individual fitness” because some biologists use the latter for a property of heritable types. For example, Michod (1999, 9). writes that “…fitness is often defined as the expected reproductive success of a type …. I refer to this notion of fitness as individual fitness.” I avoid “organism fitness” for related reasons, although it made sense to include it in the title of the paper.

  7. 7.

    I intend “evolutionary success” to be vague, capturing the idea of increase in frequency in future generations, or at least maintenance of a type in the population; this vague notion will be sufficient for my purposes here. See (Abrams 2009b) for relevant discussion.

  8. 8.

    Stearns (1976) and de Jong (1994) survey a variety of statistical type fitness concepts.

  9. 9.

    The “statistical”/“parametric” terminology is derived from the use of “statistic” and “parameter” in statistics, and is not directly related to the distinction between “statisticalist” and “causalist” views about evolutionary “forces.”

  10. 10.

    My argument is related to some given by Sober (1984) and Hodge (1987), who argue that overall individual fitness is not causal, but my argument is different. My argument is also related to arguments in Ariew and Ernst (2009) but is more general, and makes it clear that it is not the propensity interpretation of fitness per se that is the problem.

  11. 11.

    Lewontin suggests that these three conditions are necessary and sufficient for evolutionary change by natural selection. In fact they are neither necessary nor sufficient for natural selection (Godfrey-Smith 2009). However, they capture the core of the notion of natural selection sufficiently well for my purposes here.

  12. 12.

    Actually, the notion of “allele” that Williams and Dawkins used was unusual, but this subtlety needn’t concern us.

  13. 13.

    Wimsatt (1980b, 1981) argued that when there are nonlinear interactions between alleles, it’s inappropriate to treat alleles as units of selection. Analogously, one might argue that when there are nonlinear interactions between heritable types of any sort, its inappropriate to assign fitness values to each type as such. However, given a probability distribution over possible combinations of types, fitness values for any one type can in principle be computed (Abrams 2009b). This is in effect to treat those alternative types, which might be combined with a particular type whose fitness is to be calculated, as the alternative environmental states discussed in Sect. 3 (cf. Dawkins 1976; Sterelny and Kitcher 1988).

  14. 14.

    In Brandon’s (1990, chapter 2) terms, I am arguing that his assumption that there are broad regions of the space of environmental conditions which are objectively homogeneous or which vary only gradually with respect to probabilities relevant to fitness is incorrect, when we consider environmental variation in sufficient detail.

  15. 15.

    There are some similarities between aspects of Ramsey’s (2006) concept of a fitness environment and some of my own ideas (Abrams 2009a,b,c), but the latter focus on type fitnesses.

  16. 16.

    Glymour (2006, 2011) seems to focus on different questions about environments than I do, but his approach seems broadly complementary to and compatible with mine.

  17. 17.

    For example, suppose fitness is expected number of offspring O a for type a, i.e. \(\mathsf{F}\,(a) = \mathsf{E}\,(O_{a}) =\sum _{k}k\,\mathsf{P}(O_{a} = k)\). The probability of having k offspring is the average across subenvironments E j , weighted by probability of E j : \(\mathsf{P}(O_{a} = k) =\sum _{j}\mathsf{P}(O_{a} = k\vert E_{j})\mathsf{P}(E_{j})\). Together these equations imply that \(\mathsf{F}\,(a) = \mathsf{E}\,(\,\mathsf{F}\,(a\vert E_{\bullet }))\), as in the text.

  18. 18.

    I read parts of chapter 1 of Brandon (1990) as concerned with token fitness, and chapter 2 seems to allude to token fitness, e.g. on page 47, when it mentions the environment of an individual. However, the primary focus of chapter 2 is on environments of populations of organisms and these environments’ effects on the fitnesses of types.

  19. 19.

    Using the first, additive model in Sect. 3, b is fitter than a overall if

    $$\displaystyle{\mathsf{F}\,(a\vert E_{1})P(a\mbox{ in }E_{1})+\mathsf{F}\,(a\vert E_{2})P(a\mbox{ in }E_{2})\;\; <\;\; \mathsf{F}\,(b\vert E_{1})P(b\mbox{ in }E_{1})+\mathsf{F}\,(b\vert E_{2})P(b\mbox{ in }E_{2})\;.}$$

    Suppose F(a | E 1) = 10, F(a | E 2) = 2, P(a in E 1) = . 1, F(b | E 1) = 5, F(b | E 2) = 1, and P(b in E 1) = . 9. Then \(\mathsf{F}\,(a) = 10 \times .1 + 2 \times .9 = 2.8\) and \(\mathsf{F}\,(b) = 5 \times .9 + 1 \times .1 = 4.6\).

  20. 20.

    That is, b could be fitter in the sense that it has a greater probability of evolutionary success, increased frequency, etc., in either/both the short term and/or the long term.

  21. 21.

    To be precise, Brandon gives an example in which organisms of different types always choose specific subenvironments, thus in effect creating a uniform “selective environment”—in that each type competes with the other relative to constant environmental conditions. However, it’s not difficult to see how to extend this generalization of the concept of a selective environment to cases in which types have different non-extremal probabilities of encountering various ecological environments.

  22. 22.

    Note that much of Brandon’s discussion is driven by concerns other than those that are my focus.

  23. 23.

    Recall that my focus in this paper is on tendential token fitness and parametric type fitness. It’s not necessarily a mistake to estimate parametric type fitness using the average of measurable token fitnesses of actual organisms (Abrams 2012c).

  24. 24.

    For those interested in pursuing alternative interpretations of probability that may be relevant to evolutionary processes, I suggest if the complex system constituted by a biological population and its environment satisfied conditions required for what are known as mechanistic, microconstant, or natural range probabilities (Rosenthal 2010, 2012; Strevens 2011; Abrams 2012a,b) it could turn out that type fitnesses would not derive from token fitnesses. This is a topic better left for later work, but I mention the possibility here for interested readers.

References

  • Abrams, Marshall. 2007. Fitness and propensity’s annulment? Biology and Philosophy 22(1):115–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, Marshall. 2009a. Fitness “kinematics”: Altruism, biological function, and organism-environment histories. Biology and Philosophy 24(4):487–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, Marshall. 2009b. The unity of fitness. Philosophy of Science 76(5):750–761.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, Marshall. 2009c. What determines fitness? The problem of the reference environment. Synthese 166(1):21–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, Marshall. 2012a. Mechanistic probability. Synthese 187(2):343–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, Marshall. 2012b. Chapter 9. Mechanistic social probability: How individual choices and varying circumstances produce stable social patterns. In Oxford handbook of philosophy of social science, ed. Harold Kincaid, 184–226. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, Marshall. 2012c. Measured, modeled, and causal conceptions of fitness. Frontiers in Genetics 3(196):1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Ted R. 2006. Biology of the ubiquitous house sparrow. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, André, and Zachary Ernst. 2009. What fitness can’t be. Erkenntnis 71(3):289–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barkow, Jerome, Leda Cosmides, and John Tooby (eds.). 1992. The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, John, and Susan Finsen. 1989. Rethinking the propensity interpretation: A peek inside Pandora’s box. In What the philosophy of biology is, ed. Michael Ruse, 17–30. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard, Frédéric, and Alexander Rosenberg. 2004. Fitness, probability, and the principles of natural selection. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55(4):693–712.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, Robert N. 1978. Adaptation and evolutionary theory. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 9(3):181–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, Robert N. 1990. Adaptation and environment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Catoni, C., A. Peters, and H.M. Schaefer. 2009. Dietary flavonoids enhance conspicuousness of a melanin-based trait in male blackcaps but not of the female homologous trait or of sexually monochromatic traits. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 22:1649–1657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crozier, Gillian. 2010. A formal investigation of cultural selection theory: Acoustic adaptation in bird song. Biology and Philosophy 25(5):781–801.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, Richard. 1976. The selfish gene, 1st ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Jong, Gerdien. 1994. The fitness of fitness concepts and the description of natural selection. Quarterly Review of Biology 69(1):3–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dor, Roi, and Arnon Lotem. 2009. Heritability of nestling begging intensity in the house sparrow (Passer domesticus). Evolution 63(3):738–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Karl L., Kevin J. Gaston, Stuart P. Sharp, Andrew McGowan, and Ben J. Hatchwell. 2009. The effect of urbanisation on avian morphology and latitudinal gradients in body size. Oikos 118:251–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewens, Warren J. 2004. Mathematical population genetics, I. Theoretical introduction, 2nd ed. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gillespie, John H. 2004. Population genetics: A concise guide, 2nd ed. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, Bruce. 2006. Wayward modeling: Population genetics and natural selection. Philosophy of Science 73:369–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, Bruce. 2011. Modeling environments: Interactive causation and adaptations to environmental conditions. Philosophy of Science 78(3):448–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2009. Darwinian populations and natural selection. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M.J.S. 1987. Natural selection as a causal, empirical, and probabilistic theory. In The probabilistic revolution, vol. 2, ed. Lorenz Krüger, Gerd Gigerenzer, and Mary S. Morgan, 233–270. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hu, Yang, and Goncalo C. Cardoso. 2009. Are bird species that vocalize at higher frequencies preadapted to inhabit noisy urban areas? Behavioral Ecology 20(6):1268–1273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschel, Alexander N.G., Daniel T. Blumstein, Rachel E. Cohen, Wolfgang Buermann, Thomas B. Smith, and Hans Slabbekoornc. 2009. Birdsong tuned to the environment: Green hylia song varies with elevation, tree cover, and noise. Behavioral Ecology 20(5):1089–1095.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klimentidis, Yann C., Marshall Abrams, Jelai Wang, Jose R. Fernandez, and David B. Allison. 2011. Natural selection at genomic regions associated with obesity and type-2 diabetes: East Asians and sub-Saharan Africans exhibit high levels of differentiation at type-2 diabetes regions. Human Genetics 129:407–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins, Richard. 1968. Evolution in changing environments. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, Richard C. 1966. Is nature probable or capricious? BioScience 16(1):25–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, Richard C. 1970. The units of selection. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 1:1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Li, Jun Z., Devin M. Absher, Hua Tang, Audrey M. Southwick, Amanda M. Casto, Sohini Ramachandran, Howard M. Cann, Gregory S. Barsh, Marcus Feldman, Luigi L. Cavalli-Sforza, and Richard M. Myers. 2008. Worldwide human relationships inferred from genome-wide patterns of variation. Science 319(5866):1100–1104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, Mohan, and André Ariew. 2009. Selection and causation. Philosophy of Science 76(2):201–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michod, Richard E. 1999. Darwinian dynamics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Susan, and John Beatty. 1979. The propensity interpretation of fitness. Philosophy of Science 46(2):263–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno-Estrada, Andrés, Kun Tang, Martin Sikora, Toms Marquès-Bonet, Ferran Casals, Arcadi Navarro, Francesc Calafell, Jaume Bertranpetit, Mark Stoneking, and Elena Bosch. 2009. Interrogating 11 fast-evolving genes for signatures of recent positive selection in worldwide human populations. Molecular Biology and Evolution 26(10):2285–2297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagylaki, Thomas. 1992. Introduction to theoretical population genetics. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee, F. John, Kevin N. Laland, and Marcus W. Feldman. 2003. Niche construction: The neglected process in evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, Susan, Paul E. Griffiths, and Russell D. Gray. 2001. What is developmental systems theory? In Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution, ed. Susan Oyama, Paul E. Griffiths, and Russell D. Gray, 1–11. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prasad, Anisha, Melanie J.F. Croydon-Sugarman, Rosalind L. Murray, and Asher D. Cutter. 2011. Temperature-dependent fecundity associates with latitude in Caenorhabditis briggsae. Evolution 65(1):52–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, George R. 1970. Selection and covariance. Nature 227:520–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, Grant. 2006. Block fitness. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37(3):484–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, Peter J., and Robert Boyd. 2005. Not by genes alone. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ringsby, Thor Harald, Bernt-Erik Saether, Jarle Tufto, Henrik Jensen, and Erling Johan Solberg. 2002. Asynchronous spatiotemporal demography of a house sparrow metapopulation in a correlated environment. Ecology 83(2):561–569.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, Jacob. 2010. The natural-range conception of probability. In Time, chance, and reduction: Philosophical aspects of statistical mechanics, ed. Gerhard Ernst and Andreas Hüttemann, 71–90. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, Jacob. 2012. Probabilities as ratios of ranges in initial-state spaces. Journal of Logic, Language, and Inference 21:217–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roughgarden, Jonathan. 1979. Theory of population genetics and evolutionary ecology: An introduction. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheinfeldt, Laura B., Shameek Biswas, Jennifer Madeoy, Caitlin F. Connelly, and Akey Joshua. 2011. Clusters of adaptive evolution in the human genome. Frontiers in Genetics 2:50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Barry, and Achille C. Varzi. 2002. Surrounding space: The ontology of organism-environment relations. Theory in Biosciences 121(2):139–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, Elliott. 1984. The nature of selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stearns, Stephen C. 1976. Life-history tactics: A review of the ideas. Quarterly Review of Biology 51(1):3–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, Kim. 2005. Made by each other: Organisms and their environment. Biology and Philosophy 20(1):21–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, Kim, and Philip Kitcher. 1988. The return of the gene. Journal of Philosophy 85:339–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, Michael. 2011. Probability out of determinism. In Probabilities in physics, ed. Claus Beisbart and Stephann Hartmann, 339–364. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Emma E., Hala Kuttab-Boulos, David Witonsky, Limei Yang, Bruce A. Roe, and Anna Di Rienzo. 2004. CYP3A variation and the evolution of salt-sensitivity variants. The American Journal of Human Genetics 75(6):1059–1069.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, Andreas. 2005. Robustness and evolvability in living systems. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, Denis M. 2007. The pomp of superfluous causes: The interpretation of evolutionary theory. Philosophy of Science 74:281–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, Denis M. 2010. Not a sure thing: Fitness, probability, and causation. Philosophy of Science 77(2):141–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, George C. 1966. Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, William C. 1980a. Randomness and perceived randomness in evolutionary biology. Synthese 43:287–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, William C. 1980b. Reductionistic research strategies and their biases in the units of selection controversy. In Scientific discovery: Case studies, ed. Thomas Nickles, 213–259. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, William C. 1981. The units of selection and the structure of the multi-level genome. In PSA 1980, vol. 2, 122–183. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, Michigan, University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, William C. 2007. Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: Piecewise approximations to reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I’m very grateful for helpful feedback from the editors of this volume: Trevor Pearce, Gillian Barker, and Eric Desjardins; and for feedback, on related presentations in Groningen (2009), Toronto (2009), and London, Ontario (2010), from Denis Walsh, Jan-Willem Romeijn, Robert Makowsky, Yann Klimentidis, Bruce Glymour, Greg Cooper, John Beatty, André Ariew, and others who gave equally helpful comments. Some ideas in this paper grew from seeds planted by discussions with Bill Wimsatt many years ago. None of these individuals should be assumed to agree with my claims. Olivia Fanizza made early versions of the figures.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marshall Abrams .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Abrams, M. (2014). Environmental Grain, Organism Fitness, and Type Fitness. In: Barker, G., Desjardins, E., Pearce, T. (eds) Entangled Life. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 4. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7067-6_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics