Skip to main content

Learning to Listen or Why Morality Calls for Liberal Politics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Ethics or Moral Philosophy

Part of the book series: Contemporary Philosophy: A New Survey ((COPH,volume 11))

Abstract

Facing the various current phenomena of crisis, many people have come to think that politics, including decisions with regard to economy, needs to be based upon morality. Significantly, this opinion implies some kind of separation: As the cultivation of a moral attitude is considered a prerequisite for sound politics, morality itself is assumed to be independent from politics. The intention of the chapter is to challenge this assumption. The first part explains, referring to Kant, that the moral demand to respect everybody as a ‘person’ implies that we must consider the uniqueness of the individual. On this basis it is argued, firstly, that we cannot adequately answer the needs of others unless we learn to listen carefully to the ways in which individual perspectives are being expressed; secondly, that the diversity of individual experiences and expectations cannot be properly voiced unless there exists a legal framework that secures freedom of expression. Consequently, the point is that liberal politics constitutes a prerequisite for a comprehensive implementation of moral guidelines. Explaining this thesis, the chapter refers to contemporary conceptions of ‘world citizenship’ and ‘global democracy’.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Kant (1964) . (Henceforth cited as gm, p. 96.)

  2. 2.

    For a more thorough analysis of Kant ’s conception of “autonomy” see Nagl-Docekal (2010).

  3. 3.

    For a study focusing on the relevance of Kant ’s conception of “dignity” in the contemporary debate on “human rights” see Tiedemann (2007).

  4. 4.

    For a detailed account of the “duties to oneself,” see Kant (1991a) . (Henceforth cited as mm).

  5. 5.

    The relevance of these considerations for a philosophical theory of feminist politics is discussed in Nagl-Docekal (2004a) .

  6. 6.

    While the term “the rights of man” used in this English translation has a masculine frame, this is not the case with Kant ’s German expression: The term “Rechte der Menschen” is gender neutral. See Kant (1963) .

  7. 7.

    Arendt (1998). (Henceforth cited as ah .)

  8. 8.

    Explaining this matter, Arendt refers to the theological conception of creatio ex nihilo. See Arendt (1979). A detailed account of her analysis of action is provided in Brunkhorst (1999) .

  9. 9.

    Drawing upon Kant ’s “duties of kindness” also allows us to tackle the care versus justice controversy that has been one focus of the debate on feminist ethics. On the basis of the categorical imperative the two approaches that have been considered mutually exclusive – an ethics of care and a universalist concept of morality – prove to be not only reconcilable but rather necessarily intertwined. For a more thorough elaboration on this issue see Nagl-Docekal (1997) .

  10. 10.

    A precise philosophical assessment of paternalism is provided by Gadamer (1982) .

  11. 11.

    In German: “logische Egoisterei.” See Kant (1910–1968).

  12. 12.

    See, for instance, Arendt (1961).

  13. 13.

    Kant (1952) . (Henceforth cited as cj.)

  14. 14.

    See Kant (1983a) . (Henceforth cited as we .)

  15. 15.

    The remaining maxims are: “(1) to think for oneself,” and “(3) always to think consistently” (cj: 152). Kant explains: “We may say: the first of these is the maxim of understanding, the second that of judgement, the third that of reason” (cj: 153).

  16. 16.

    Arendt (1982) . (Henceforth cited as lk .)

  17. 17.

    Seyla Benhabib observes that in Arendt ’s reading of Kant , “judging becomes a […] capacity for presenting to oneself the perspectivality of the world, of taking cognizance of the many points of view through which a matter must be seen and evaluated.” See Benhabib (1996) .

  18. 18.

    See Habermas (1994).

  19. 19.

    Rawls (1971). (Henceforth cited as tj.)

  20. 20.

    For a recent reflection on this matter see Pogge (2010).

  21. 21.

    Unfortunately, this way of reading Kant has predominated with authors advocating the approaches of Transcendental Pragmatics and Communicative Action.

  22. 22.

    Kant (1998b) . (Henceforth cited as rr.)

  23. 23.

    Kant (1983b) . (Henceforth cited as uh .) For a comment on Kant ’s reflections on the moral progress of humanity see Anderson-Gold (2001) and Kleingeld (1995).

  24. 24.

    A more detailed explanation of this difference is provided in Nagl-Docekal (2004b) . (Henceforth cited as ru.)

  25. 25.

    Kant (1983c) . (Henceforth cited as pp .)

  26. 26.

    A recent debate has raised doubts whether the two core concepts of political theory – freedom and equality – can be brought into a balanced relation. But this debate was based upon a more specific reading of the two concepts and did, therefore, not concern Kant ’s formal understanding – and his mode of linking – them. For an overview see Pauer-Studer and Nagl-Docekal (2003).

  27. 27.

    Guyer (2004) . Guyer also points out that Rawls ’s conception of the social contract is clearly more restricted than Kant ’s.

  28. 28.

    See Habermas (1996). (Henceforth cited as fn.)

  29. 29.

    See Habermas (1984) .

  30. 30.

    Wingert (2002) . (“Reasons are propositions, stated in using concepts, that seek to reach consent which is based upon comprehension, i.e., consent to that for which the propositions claim to provide the reasons. Justifying reasons are the signposts along the path that we need to take in order to achieve comprehension.” Transl. h. n.-d.)

  31. 31.

    The term “globalization ” is used here in a wide sense which covers relations in a variety of fields, including science and culture. In current everyday language, this term often has a more narrow meaning with a clearly negative ring; in that case it refers to the economic and political dynamic defined by neo-liberal conceptions.

  32. 32.

    Benhabib (2002). (Henceforth cited as cc .)

  33. 33.

    Pogge (2002). (Henceforth cited as wp.) Pogge refers here, i.e., to the arguments developed in Singer (1972) . Pogge insists that all our obligations to help and support distant strangers can be derived from the concept of ‘negative’ duties. There is, however, no need for such a theoretical restriction since, as pointed out in this chapter, the concept of (wide) ‘duties of kindness,’ as introduced by Kant , is well argued. In her critical assessment of both Singer ’s and Pogge ’s approaches Bleisch also draws upon Kant ’s ‘duties of kindness.’ See Bleisch (2010).

  34. 34.

    See for instance Nussbaum (2000) and Nussbaum and Glover (1995).

  35. 35.

    See, for instance, the data provided in wp. For a specific focus on the deterioration of the situation of women in the global South see Jaggar (2002).

  36. 36.

    For a careful analysis of Kant ’s conception from a contemporary point of view see Rademacher (2010).

  37. 37.

    Kant (1991b) . (This edition is used here because the translation of Kant ’s Perpetual Peace from which the other quotations are taken does not contain this sentence.)

  38. 38.

    For a lucid comment see Brandt (1995) .

  39. 39.

    See, for instance, the account provided in Jaggar (2003).

  40. 40.

    See Kleingeld (2004) and Höffe (2001) .

  41. 41.

    Held (1995). (Henceforth cited as dg.)

  42. 42.

    Benhabib (2004); see also cc.

  43. 43.

    See the chapter “On Duties to Oneself as Such” (mm: 214–242).

  44. 44.

    For details on the differences between – and the parallel structures of – the “political” and the “ethical” state in Kant , see ru.

  45. 45.

    Earlier versions of this chapter were read at the University of Riga, Latvia (May 7, 2010), and at the 29th Annual Conference of the International Association for Philosophy and Literature (iapl) in Helsinki, Finland (June 7, 2005). I am much obliged for the comments made in the dicussions following these presentations.

Reference

  • Anderson-Gold, S. (2001). Unnecessary evil: History and moral progress in the philosophy of Immanuel Kant. Albany: State University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson-Gold, S. (2004). Evil and enlightenment in the philosophy of Immanuel Kant. In H. Nagl-Docekal & R. Langthaler (Eds.), Recht – Geschichte – Religion. Die Bedeutung Kants für die Gegenwart (pp. 113–122). Berlin: Akademie.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson-Gold, S. (2005). Kantische Grundlagen des gegenwärtigen Kosmopolitismus. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 53, 97–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1961). Between past and future: Six exercises in political thought. New York: Meridian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1979). Vom Leben des Geistes: Vol. 2. Das Wollen. München: Pieper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1982). Lectures on Kant’s political philosophy. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1998). Arbeiten, Herstellen, Handeln. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 46, 997–1009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. (1996). The reluctant modernism of Hannah Arendt. Thousand Oaks/London/New Delhi: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. (2002). The claims of culture. Equality and diversity in the global era. Princeton/Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. (2004). The rights of others. Aliens, citizens and residents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bleisch, B. (2010). Pflichten auf Distanz. Weltarmut und individuelle Verantwortung. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, R. (1995). Vom Weltbürgerrecht. In O. Höffe (Ed.), Klassiker Auslegen: Immanuel Kant, Zum ewigen Frieden (pp. 133–148). Berlin: Akademie.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunkhorst, H. (1999). Hannah Arendt. München: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H.-G. (1982). Truth and method. New York: Cross Road.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, P. (2004). Civic responsibility and the kantian social contract. In H. Nagl-Docekal & R. Langthaler (Eds.), Recht – Geschichte – Religion. Die Bedeutung Kants für die Gegenwart (pp. 27–47). Wien/München/Berlin: Oldenbourg/Akademie.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1984). The theory of communicative action: Vol. 1. Reason and rationalization of society (T. McCarthy, Trans.). Boston: Beacon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1994). Post-metaphysical thinking: Between metaphysics and the critique of reason. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1996). Between facts and norms. Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Held, D. (1995). Democracy and the global order. From the modern state to cosmopolitan governance. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Höffe, O. (2001). ‘Königliche Völker.’ Zu Kant’s kosmopolitischer Rechts- und Friedenstheorie. Frankfurt a. M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Höffe, O. (2004). Wirtschaftsbürger, Staatsbürger, Weltbürger. Politische Ethik im Zeitalter der Globalisierung. München: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaggar, A. M. (2002). A feminist critique of the alleged southern debt. In B. Christensen et al. (Eds.), Knowledge – power – gender. Philosophy and the future of the ‘condition féminine’ (pp. 19–40). Zürich: Chronos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaggar, A. M. (2003). Gegen die weltweite Benachteiligung von Frauen. Einige Prioritäten für die westliche Philosophie. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 51, 585–609.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1910–1968). Logik Blomberg. Kants Gesammelte Schriften (Vol. xxiv). Berlin: Preussische/Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1952). Critique of judgement (J. C. Meredith, Trans.). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1963). Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten. In W. Weischedel (Ed.), Werke in sechs Bänden (Vol. iv, pp. 7–102). Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1964). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals (H. P. Paton, Trans.). New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1983a). An answer to the question: What is enlightenment? In I. Kant (Ed.), Perpetual peace and other essays on politics, history and morals (T. Humphrey, Trans., pp. 41–60). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1983b). Idea for a universal history with a cosmopolitan intent. In I. Kant (Ed.), Perpetual peace and other essays (T. Humphrey, Trans., pp. 19–39). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1983c). To perpetual peace. A philosophical sketch. In I. Kant (Ed.), Perpetual peace and other essays on politics, history and morals (T. Humphrey, Trans., pp. 107–143). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1991a). The metaphysics of morals (M. Gregor, Trans., pp. 214–242). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1991b). Perpetual peace: A philosophical sketch. In H. Reiss (Ed.), Kant’s political writings (2nd ed., pp. 98–112). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998a). What does it mean to orient oneself in thinking? In I. Kant (Ed.), Religion within the boundaries of mere reason and other writings (A. Wood & G. di Giovanni, Trans., pp. 1–14). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998b). Religion within the boundaries of mere reason. In I. Kant (Ed.), Religion within the boundaries of mere reason and other writings (A. Wood & G. di Giovanni, Trans., pp. 31–191). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleingeld, P. (1995). Fortschritt und Vernunft: Zur Geschichtsphilosophie Kants. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleingeld, P. (2004). Kant’s Argumente für den Völkerbund. In H. Nagl-Docekal & R. Langthaler (Eds.), Recht – Geschichte – Religion. Die Bedeutung Kants für die Gegenwart (pp. 99–112). Wien/München/Berlin: Oldenbourg/Akademie.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nagl-Docekal, H. (1997). Feminist ethics: How it could benefit from Kant’s moral philosophy. In R. M. Schott (Ed.), Feminist interpretations of Immanuel Kant (pp. 101–124). University Park: The Pennsylvania University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagl-Docekal, H. (2004a). Feminist philosophy (K. Vester, Trans.). Boulder: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagl-Docekal, H. (2004b). Eine rettende Übersetzung? Jürgen Habermas interpretiert Kants Religionsphilosophie. In R. Langthaler & H. Nagl-Docekal (Eds.), Glauben und Wissen. Ein Symposium mit Jürgen Habermas (pp. 93–116). Wien/München/Berlin: Oldenbourg/Akademie.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagl-Docekal, H. (2010). Über Selbstgesetzgebung und das Glück. Autonomie bei Kant. In E. List & H. Stelzer (Eds.), Grenzen der Autonomie (pp. 33–54). Weilerswist: Velbrück.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2000). Women and human development: The capabilities approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C., & Glover, J. (Eds.). (1995). Women, culture, and development. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (1985). Constructions of reason: Explorations of Kant’s practical philosophy (Chapter “Between consenting adults”, pp. 105–125). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pauer-Studer, H., & Nagl-Docekal, H. (Eds.). (2003). Freiheit, Gleichheit und Autonomie. Wien/München/Berlin: Oldenbourg/Akademie.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. (2002). World poverty and human rights. Cambridge/Oxford/Malden: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. (2010). Politics as usual: What lies behind the pro-poor rhetoric. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rademacher, T. (2010). Kants Antwort auf die Globalisierung. Das kantsche Weltbürgerrecht als Prinzip einer normativen politischen Theorie des weltpolitischen Systems zur Steuerung der Globalisierung. Berlin: Logos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlothfeldt, S. (2009). Individuelle oder gemeinsame Verpflichtung? Das Problem der Zuständigkeit bei der Behebung gravierender Übel. Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence and morality. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1, 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiedemann, P. (2007). Menschenwürde als Rechtsbegriff. Eine philosophische Klärung. Berlin: Wissenschafts-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Volk, C. (2009). Demokratie in der Weltgesellschaft? Normative Grundlagen legitimer Herrschaft in einer globalen politischen Ordnung. Berlin/New York: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wingert, L. (2002). Jürgen Habermas: Faktizität und Geltung – Der Prozess des Rechts in den Satzungen der Macht. In R. Brandt & T. Sturm (Eds.), Klassische Werke der Philosophie. Von Aristoteles bis Habermas (pp. 345–378). Leipzig: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Herta Nagl-Docekal .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Nagl-Docekal, H. (2014). Learning to Listen or Why Morality Calls for Liberal Politics. In: Fløistad, G. (eds) Ethics or Moral Philosophy. Contemporary Philosophy: A New Survey, vol 11. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6895-6_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics