Skip to main content

Animal Morality and Human Morality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy ((LOET,volume 31))

Abstract

Nowadays many people attribute a morality to various social animal species, morality that goes far beyond ‘morality’ in the sense of an analogous system for the regulation of social behaviour. They are convinced by the huge amount of observations and stories collected by students of animal behaviour, and presented to them in popularizing books by authors such as Marc Bekoff, Marc Hauser, and Frans de Waal. The definition of morality from which criteria for classifying a system for the regulation of social behaviour as a morality must be derived is discussed in Sect. 6.2. Section 6.3 categorizes the moral behaviour patterns of animals identified by animal behavioural scientists in four clusters. Section 6.4 deals with what capacities are needed for moral behaviour. Sections 6.5 and 6.6 consider when behaviour can be said to be rule governed. In Sect. 6.7, I examine whether animals can have moral motives. Section 6.8 goes into the occurrence of social disapproval as a criterion for norm violation. Section 6.9 discusses the relation between animal morality and human morality, and argues that animal morality regulates behaviour automatically and unconsciously. However, a large part also of human morality is non-reflective and functions in the same manner as animal morality. In contradistinction to animal morality, human morality makes use of both System I processes and System II processes and can be both non-reflective and reflective. Section 6.10 contains some reflections on the moral status of animals belonging to a species that has a morality. Section 6.11 offers some concluding remarks.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In The criminal prosecution and capital punishment of animals ([1906] 1987) Edward Evans documented more than 191 prosecutions and excommunications of animals between the ninth and twentieth centuries. Research shows that the majority of secular prosecutions were concentrated in the southern and eastern parts of France and in adjacent parts of Germany, Italy, and Switzerland.

  2. 2.

    There is now considerable agreement on the characteristics that distinguish the two systems. The operations of System I are fast, automatic, effortless, associative, and difficult to control or to modify. The operations of System II are slower, serial, effortful, and deliberately controlled; they are also relatively flexible and potentially rule-governed.

  3. 3.

    In Primates and philosophers De Waal states: ‘The same process [i.e. evolution, BM] may not have specified our moral rules and values, but it has provided us with the psychological makeup, tendencies, and abilities to develop a compass for life’s choices that takes the interests of the entire community into account, which is the essence of human morality’ (De Waal 2009, p. 58).

  4. 4.

    Railton speaks here of discomfort, not of shame and guilt which are more specific moral feelings.

  5. 5.

    The correct spelling of the name of Dostoevsky’s prince in The idiot (1868) is ‘Mysjkin’, but I will follow Rowlands’s spelling. After a long stay abroad, prince Myshkin returns to Russia where he finds people under the spell of money. Myshkin is called the idiot because of his epileptic seizures.

  6. 6.

    Rowlands’s Mishkin is someone whose morality seems to operate completely on the sub-conscious level. Hubert and Stuart Dreyfus (1991) would characterize him as a ‘moral expert’, the product of successful moral education and training whose judgments and decisions are the product of intuitive thinking. I don’t have problems with Rowlands’s characterization of Mishkin as a moral subject, but his picture of Mishkin is over-simplified. Even moral experts sometimes have to reason consciously, e.g., when their intuitions conflict or are indeterminate. Moreover, it is hard to imagine that a person is never challenged to give reasons for his judgments and actions. Therefore Mishkin must be capable to reflect on his motivation. Mishkin may most of the time function as a moral subject, but he must be capable of moral agency.

  7. 7.

    An important implication of this view is for me that moral animals cannot be used for food, nor for research purposes.

References

  • Bargh, J.A. 1996. Automaticity in social psychology. In Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles, ed. E.T. Higgins and A.W. Krugalski, 169–183. New York: Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J.A., and T.L. Chartrand. 1999. The unbearable automaticity of being. American Psychologist 54: 462–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bekoff, M., and J. Pierce. 2009. Wild justice. The moral lives of animals. Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blair, R.J.R. 1995. A cognitive developmental approach to morality: Investigating the psychopath. Cognition 57: 1–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair, R.J.R. 1997. Moral reasoning and the child with psychopathic tendencies. Personality and Individual Difference 22: 731–739.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Call, J., and M. Tomasello. 1998. Distinguishing intentional from accidental actions in orangutans, chimpanzees, and human children. Journal of Comparative Psychology 112: 192–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 2012. The fragmentation of reasoning. http://www.philosophy.umd.edu/Faculty/pcarruthers/The%20Fragmentation%20of%20Reasoning.pdf. In La coevolución de mente y lenguaje. Ontogénesis y filogénesis, ed. P. Quintanilla. Lima: Fondo Editorial de la Pontificia Universidad Católica del Perú.

  • De Waal, F.B.M. 2009. In Primates and philosophers. How morality evolved, ed. S. Macedo and J. Ober. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H.L., and S.E. Dreyfus. 1991. Towards a phenomenology of ethical expertise. Human Studies 14: 229–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberg, N. 2000. Emotion, regulation, and moral development. Annual Review of Psychology 51: 665–697.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, E. [1906]/1987. The criminal prosecution and capital punishment of animals. Whitefield: Kessinger Publications Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flack, J.C., and F.B.M. De Waal. 2000. ‘Any animal whatever’. Darwinian building blocks of morality in monkeys and apes. Journal of Consciousness Studies 7: 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C.R., and J. Gibbon. 2001. Time, rate and conditioning. Psychological Review 108: 289–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C.R., and A. King. 2009. Memory and the computational brain. New York/Chichester/Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Girgen, J. 2003. The historical and contemporary prosecution and punishment of animals. Animal Law 9: 97–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 1961. The concept of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, M.L. 2000. Empathy and moral development: Implications for caring and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Koski, S.E., and E.H.M. Sterck. 2009. Empathetic chimpanzees. A proposal of the levels of emotional and cognitive processing in chimpanzee empathy. European Journal of Development Psychology 7: 38–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R., J. Banks, and N. Ogawa. 1963. Role of facial expression in ‘cooperative-avoidance conditioning’ in monkeys. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 67: 24–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. 2004. The sentimental rules. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, D. 2011. The moral lives of animals. New York: Bloomsbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Premack, D., and G. Woodruff. 1978. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1: 516–526.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston, S.D., and F.B.M. De Waal. 2002. Empathy. Its ultimate and proximate bases. Behavioural and Brain Sciences 1: 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. 2006. Normative guidance. In Oxford studies in metaethics, vol. 1, ed. R. Shafer-Landau, 3–35. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. 2011. Animals that act for moral reasons. In The Oxford handbook of animal ethics, ed. T.L. Beauchamp and R.G. Frey, 519–547. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sloman, S.A. 1996. The empirical case for two systems of reasoning. Psychological Bulletin 119: 3–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich, K.E., and R.F. West. 2000. Individual differences in reasoning: Implications for the rationality debate? Behavioural and Brain Sciences 23: 645–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., and J. Call. 1997. Primate cognition. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., and M. Carpenter. 2007. Shared intentionality. Development Science 10: 121–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turiel, E. 1983. The development of social knowledge: Morality and convention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turiel, E., M. Killen, and C. Helwig. 1987. Morality: Its structure, functions, and vagaries. In The emergence of morality in young children, ed. J. Kagan and S. Lamb, 155–244. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Rohr, C.R., J. Burkart, and C. van Schaik. 2011. Evolutionary precursors of social norms in chimpanzees: A new approach. Biology and Philosophy 26: 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warnock, G.J. 1971. The object of morality. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bert Musschenga .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Musschenga, B. (2013). Animal Morality and Human Morality. In: Musschenga, B., van Harskamp, A. (eds) What Makes Us Moral? On the capacities and conditions for being moral. Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy, vol 31. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6343-2_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics