Skip to main content

It’s Complicated – Moral Nativism, Moral Input and Moral Development

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy ((LOET,volume 31))

Abstract

The paper provides a critical discussion of certain limitations of current nativist approaches to the question of moral development. The aim of the paper is to warn against a lingering reductive tendency found among certain contemporary moral nativists: a tendency to exaggerate the importance of innate mechanisms for moral development while simultaneously downplaying the importance of other factors in this process. The paper argues that the morally relevant input available in the social and cultural environment of human beings is much richer and more varied than typically acknowledged by moral nativists. By ignoring this richness the nativist runs the risk of distorting our understanding of the phenomenon we want to explain.

Caveat: In several places this paper refers to Marc Hauser’s writings. As I was finishing the paper Hauser was accused of and found solely responsible for eight counts of scientific misconduct. Furthermore Gilbert Harman has accused him of having plagiarized parts of his book Moral Minds from John Mikhail. To the best of my knowledge none of the problematic experiments are relevant for the argument of this paper. The general nativist position I discuss is shared by a number of people and is not necessarily dependent on Hauser’s work. As for Moral Minds I still think that it provides a reasonable overview of much current empirical research on moral psychology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    People sometimes distinguish between (moral) innatism and (moral) nativism, with innatism being the doctrine that the human mind is born with certain ideas and knowledge, and nativism being a specific modern version of this doctrine, which uses genetics, cognitive science and evolutionary biology to explain the existence of such innate ideas/knowledge. In this paper I use nativism indiscriminately to refer to all theories which take the human mind to be endowed with innate ideas/principles/mechanisms.

  2. 2.

    See Hauser (2006) for a comprehensive overview of the biological, evolutionary and cognitive theories which inform contemporary moral nativism.

  3. 3.

    Noam Chomsky is often credited as being the first to formulate (a version of) the poverty of the stimulus argument. Chomsky’s argument (see Chomsky 1957, 1959) did not concern morals, but was directed against empiricist accounts of language acquisition such as B.F. Skinner’s. Moral nativists such as Susan Dwyer, Marc Hauser and John Mikhail have later adopted Chomsky’s argument and directed it against empiricist accounts of moral development. It is worth noting however that already Plato formulated and made use of (a version of) what is nowadays known as the POS argument. See Meno 82A-86C, where Socrates gradually elicits sophisticated mathematical reasoning from a slave who has no previous experience with mathematics, and uses this as proof that knowledge is not something taught or learned, but something which is always-already embedded in the human mind, albeit in inarticulate and implicit form.

  4. 4.

    The DDE can be more formally stated as follows: ‘A person may licitly perform an action that he foresees will produce a good and a bad effect provided that four conditions are verified at one and the same time: (1) that the action in itself from its very object be good or at least indifferent; (2) that the good effect and not the evil effect be intended; (3) that the good effect be not produced by means of the evil effect; (4) that there be a proportionately grave reason for permitting the evil effect’ (Mangan 1949, p. 43).

  5. 5.

    One reviewer questioned the relevance of Hoffman’s work for discussions of moral nativism, since the primary focus of Hoffman’s research is on empathy and how to foster and develop pro-social motives whereas moral nativists are primarily concerned with moral cognition and the development of the capacity for moral judgment. However, the aspect of Hoffman’s research appealed to in this paper concerns the pervasiveness and complexity of disciplinary encounters in moral development. As such it can be fairly clearly separated from Hoffman’s research on pro-sociality (although the two are clearly linked). And research on disciplinary encounters is relevant for discussions of moral nativism because explicit parental admonitions, which nativists often take to be the most important moral input children are exposed to in moral upbringing, is a common and crucial form of disciplinary encounter.

  6. 6.

    All citations and references to Hegel’s Outlines of the Philosophy of Right are to the numbered paragraphs in this work. Hegel’s additions (Zusatzen) to these paragraphs are indicated by a ‘Z’.

  7. 7.

    Contrary to what many people might think Hegel is perfectly willing to admit the importance of (uncultivated) human nature in explaining and understanding the moral development of human beings. Hegel’s analysis of socially mediated affective and cognitive development is firmly grounded in a detailed account of human beings as part of and embedded within nature. For Hegel human beings are importantly (but not simply and not only) embodied and desiring creatures; creatures who want and need material things in order to survive and who utilize and develop their capacity for reason as a way of acquiring that which they desire. See e.g. Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit (Hegel 1971) or his philosophical anthropology as presented in part three of his Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (Hegel 2007).

References

  • Aquinas, Thomas. 1988. Summa Theologica II-II, Q. 64, art. 7, ‘Of killing’. In On law, morality, and politics, ed. W.P. Baumgarth and R.J. Regan, 226–227. Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, R.J.R. 1995. A cognitive-developmental approach to morality: Investigating the psychopath. Cognition 37(1): 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. 1957. Syntactic structures. London: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. 1959. A review of B.F. Skinner’s verbal behavior. Language 35(1): 26–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, S. 1999. Moral competence. In Philosophy and linguistics, ed. K. Murasugi and R. Stainton, 169–190. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, S. 2006. How good is the linguistic analogy? In The innate mind, Vol. 2: Culture and cognition, ed. P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, and S. Stich, 237–256. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, S. 2009. Moral dumbfounding and the linguistic analogy: Methodological implications for the study of moral judgment. Mind and Language 24(3): 274–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, S., B. Huebner, and M. Hauser. 2010. The linguistic analogy: Motivations, results, and speculations. Topics in Cognitive Science 2(3): 486–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. 1967. The problem of abortion and the doctrine of double effect. Oxford Review 5: 5–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, M. 2006. Moral minds. How nature designed our universal sense of right and wrong. New York: Ecco Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, M., L. Young, and F. Cushman. 2008. Reviving Rawls’s linguistic analogy. In Moral psychology, Vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 107–143. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 2000. Moral philosophy and linguistics. In Explaining value and other essays in moral philosophy, 217–226. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. 1971. Phenomenology of spirit. Trans. A.V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. 2007. Hegel’s philosophy of mind. Part three of Hegel’s encyclopaedia of the philosophical sciences (1830). Trans. W. Wallace and A.V. Miller, rev. with introduction and commentary by Michael Inwood. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. 2008. Outlines of the philosophy of right. Trans. and ed. T.M. Knox, rev. with introduction by Stephen Houlgate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, M. 2001. Empathy and moral development: Implications for caring and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. 2013. The many moral nativisms. In Cooperation and its evolution, eds. K. Sterelny, R. Joyce, B. Calcott, and B. Fraser, 549–572. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. 2007. The responsibility of the psychopath revisited. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology 14(2): 129–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., and R. Mallon. 2010. Evolution of morality. In The moral psychology handbook, ed. J. Doris and Moral Psychology Research Group. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mangan, J. 1949. A historical analysis of the principle of double effect. Theological Studies 10: 41–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, B., and L. Le Sage. 2009. Are psychopaths morally sensitive? Journal of Moral Education 38(1): 75–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail, J. 2002. Aspects of the theory of moral cognition: Investigating intuitive knowledge of the prohibition of intentional battery and the principle of double effect. Social Science Research Network. http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=762385. Accessed 28 June 2012.

  • Mikhail, J. 2007. Universal moral grammar: Theory, evidence, and the future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11(4): 143–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail, J. 2008. The poverty of the moral stimulus. In Moral psychology, Vol. 1: The evolution of morality: Innateness and adaptation, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 353–360. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail, J. 2011. Elements of moral cognition: Rawls’s linguistic analogy and the cognitive science of moral and legal judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, K.R., and E.S. Spelke. 2008. Foundations of cooperation in preschool children. Cognition 108(1): 222–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plato. Meno, Trans. Benjamin Jowett (1871). Project Gutenberg: http://www.gutenberg.org/files/1643/1643-h/1643-h.htm

  • Prinz, J. 2008. Resisting the linguistic analogy: A commentary on Hauser, Young, and Cushman. In Moral psychology, Vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 157–170. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rochat, P., M.D.G. Dias, L. Guo, T. Broesch, C. Passos-Ferreira, A. Winning, and B. Berg. 2009. Fairness in distributive justice by 3- and 5-year-olds across 7 cultures. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 40(3): 416–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roskies, A. 2003. Are ethical judgments intrinsically motivational? Lessons from ‘acquired sociopathy’. Philosophical Psychology 16(1): 51–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smetana, J. 1983. Social cognitive development: Domain distinctions and co-ordinations. Developmental Review 3(2): 131–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. 2006. The evolution and evolvability of culture. Mind and Language 21(2): 137–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. 2010. Moral nativism: A skeptical response. Mind and Language 25(3): 279–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turiel, E. 1983. The development of social knowledge: Morality and convention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M., and S. Nichols. 2007. Psychopaths and moral knowledge. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology 14(2): 157–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Emily Hartz for comments and corrections on an earlier version of this paper. Also thanks to the anonymous reviewer who gave helpful suggestions and criticism. Finally thanks to the Centre for Subjectivity Research, University of Copenhagen, for the postdoc funding that enabled me to write this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carsten Fogh Nielsen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Nielsen, C.F. (2013). It’s Complicated – Moral Nativism, Moral Input and Moral Development. In: Musschenga, B., van Harskamp, A. (eds) What Makes Us Moral? On the capacities and conditions for being moral. Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy, vol 31. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6343-2_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics