Skip to main content

Intentionality Bifurcated: A Lesson from Early Modern Philosophy?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Contemporary Perspectives on Early Modern Philosophy

Part of the book series: Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ((AUST,volume 29))

Abstract

This paper examines the pressures leading two very different Early Modern philosophers, Descartes and Locke, to invoke two ways in which thought is directed at objects. According to both philosophers, I argue, the same idea can simultaneously count as “of” two different objects—in two different senses of the phrase ‘idea of’. One kind of intentional directedness is invoked in answering the question What is it to think that thus-and-so? The other kind is invoked in answering the question What accounts for the success of our proper methods of inquiry? For Descartes as well as Locke, the two kinds of “ofness” come apart as a result of strong rationalist commitments. However, I will suggest that even if we reject such commitments, we go wrong if we assume that a single kind of intentional directedness suffices to address both questions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See e.g. Perler (1996, 2010), Pasnau (1997), Hoffman (2002), Brown (2007), Clemenson (2007) and Carriero (2009).

  2. 2.

    I don’t mean to claim that these are the only contexts in which Descartes or Locke use what we might regard as notions of representation. For general discussion of representation in Descartes and Locke respectively, see Simmons (forthcoming) and Lennon (2007).

  3. 3.

    Shapiro (2012, 2010).

  4. 4.

    References in this format will be to the edition of Adam and Tannery (1964–1976, henceforth AT), and to the translations in Cottingham et al. (1984–1991, henceforth CSM and CSMK). Where I have significantly modified a translation, the original is provided in brackets.

  5. 5.

    Mori (2012) offers biographical, textual and philosophical evidence that the objector, whose letter Descartes received from Mersenne, was Hobbes.

  6. 6.

    Cf. Perler (1996, 13–14).

  7. 7.

    It may be objected that in the same letter Descartes rejects a distinction between two kinds of ideas, those “expressed by terms” and those expressed “by propositions” (AT 3:396, CSMK 3:186). For my purposes, however, it won’t matter whether we talk about a thought that God is infinite or a thought of God as infinite, as long as this specification immediately determines a truth condition for a possible judgment. Cf. Perler (1996, 257–61) and Nuchelmans (1983, 42–4). For the dialectical context of Descartes’s rejection of the above distinction, see Mori (2012).

  8. 8.

    Elsewhere, I have argued that this sense is essential to understanding one strand of Descartes’s epistemology: his view that we can delineate the natures of things by contemplation of what is contained in our clear and distinct ideas of them (Shapiro 2012, 396–8).

  9. 9.

    Lenz (2010a, 254, my translation).

  10. 10.

    Fodor (1998, 6).

  11. 11.

    The extensive literature on Descartes and material falsity is examined in Shapiro (2012); see also De Rosa (2010) and Naaman-Zauderer (2010). My reading of Descartes’s reply to Arnauld is most influenced by Margaret Wilson, who proposes that Descartes is distinguishing between two “senses of … ‘idea of’,” namely a “presentational” and a “referential” sense (Wilson 1990, 69–70, 73–4). But neither of Wilson’s two senses lines up with either of the two senses I attribute to Descartes (see Shapiro 2012, 401).

  12. 12.

    An exception is Wee (2006, 55–8).

  13. 13.

    For criticism of common readings according to which Descartes agrees with Arnauld that the scenario is incoherent, and denies that it is what he had in mind in the Third Meditation, see Shapiro (2012, 391–3).

  14. 14.

    Suárez (1597/1960–1966, 8.3.16/2:106) is cited by Wells (1984, 32n36). For similar passages from Pedro da Fonseca and Antonio Rubio, see Clemenson (2007, 43–5).

  15. 15.

    More precisely, I claim that Descartes uses the two locutions interchangeably when discussing the intentional directedness of ideas. I take no position on the contested ontology of objective being in Descartes: i.e. whether or not the act of the intellect that represents some object is really distinct from the object insofar as it is objectively in the intellect, what Descartes elsewhere call an idea “taken objectively” (AT 7:8, CSM 2:7). See e.g. Ayers (1998, 1067–8).

  16. 16.

    I defend this identification of what the idea in Descartes’s example represents in Shapiro (2012, 389–90). For a contrary position, see De Rosa (2010, 55, 69–79).

  17. 17.

    Hoffman (1996) and Nelson (1996).

  18. 18.

    For a recent discussion that includes a survey of the literature on Cartesian sensory ideas, see De Rosa (2010).

  19. 19.

    Compare Descartes’s description of the hypothetical materially false idea: “the obscurity of the idea gives me occasion to judge that this idea of the sensation of cold represents some object called ‘cold’ which is located outside me” (AT 7:234–5, CSM 2:164). Though the idea is in fact representationally of a sensation, I may take it to be representationally of its propositional object, namely the quality I called ‘cold’. Even if this mistake doesn’t amount to an explicit judgment (one only a philosopher could make!), it can account for my false judgment about that quality.

  20. 20.

    In Doyle (2001, 162–3 and 172–3); see also Wells (2003, 27–30).

  21. 21.

    Here I agree with Clemenson (2007, 71). See also Grüne (2010, 34–5n38), who sees this consequence of her reading as a difficulty.

  22. 22.

    See Wee (2006, 56–7).

  23. 23.

    For similar readings of clarity and distinctness see Alanen (2003, 159) and Clemenson (2007, 72–5).

  24. 24.

    See Lenz (2010b, 345ff; 2010a, 271–2) for a related attribution to Locke of two dimensions of content, which likewise stresses the role of Locke’s ideas in mental propositions.

  25. 25.

    In Shapiro (1999, 587–90), I proposed that Locke’s distinction between the nominal and real essences of substance kinds coincides with a distinction between kinds of content (cf. Prinz 2000). Here, I follow Shapiro (2010) in explaining that distinction in terms of propositional and representational intentionality.

  26. 26.

    References in this format will be to Locke’s Essay (by book, chapter, section, and page number in Locke 1975).

  27. 27.

    Though Locke insists that his usage of ‘species’ and ‘sort’ is a mere matter of Latin versus English (3.3.12:414, 3.5.9:434), ‘species’ typically expresses a contrast with ‘genus’ less often expressed by ‘sort’ (e.g. not at 3.3.15:417, 3.6.1:439). Locke’s English for ‘genus’ is ‘kind’ (2.32.6:386, 3.1.6:404), though this term too is often used without any intended contrast (2.32.24:393, 4.6.4:580). Here I will use ‘species’ as the Lockean term.

  28. 28.

    Perler (1996, 261n) notes that Locke’s theory of mental proposition has no counterpart in Descartes. This difference needn’t prevent us from isolating a common notion of propositional ofness in both philosophers: see note 7 above.

  29. 29.

    Ott (2012, 1087), stresses the connection between the truth of a Lockean mental proposition (the agreement of its component ideas) and what the ideas in the proposition are of: “whether ideas agree or disagree is a function of … what they are ideas of.” Though Ott’s discussion concerns simple ideas, his “of-ness” thus plays the role of what I am calling propositional ofness.

  30. 30.

    See esp. Ayers (1991, vol. 2: 75–7), Mattern (1986) and Atherton (2007).

  31. 31.

    There is an explicit cross-reference from the opening sentence of 3.9.12:482 to the opening sentence of 2.31.6:378. In both places, Locke contrasts the inadequacy he has in mind with a second inadequacy: substance ideas also count as inadequate when (inappropriately) regarded as revealing the “real essences” of species.

  32. 32.

    In several of these passages, Locke doesn’t expressly note that he is talking about species rather than individuals. Yet taken together, and in their contexts, they demand the former construal. In once instance, Locke clarifies his intention in the Essay’s fourth edition. Rather than speak of that person who “has the perfectest Idea of any particular Substance” he now speaks of that person who “has the perfectest Idea of any of the particular sorts of Substance” (2.23.7:299).

  33. 33.

    In two striking passages (analyzed in Shapiro 1999, 561–4), Locke complains of how “hard it is” to specify the species of which IDEA1 and IDEA2 are imperfect ideas without “cross[ing his] purpose” by using the word ‘gold’ rather than just mentioning it (3.6.19:449, 3.6.43:465–6).

  34. 34.

    In Shapiro (2010), I argue that the representational ofness of simple ideas diverges from their propositional ofness. For a similar view, see Ott (2012, 1089–93). Ott reserves the label “representation in the strict sense—the of-ness of an idea” for a notion that plays the propositional role (see note 29 above). He distinguishes this “of-ness” of ideas from their “role as marks or signs” that corresponds roughly to what I call Locke’s representational ofness. Since Ott and I recognize that Locke uses ‘represent’ in both ways (Shapiro 2010, 579n23), this difference is chiefly terminological. There remain two substantive differences. First, Ott’s Locke regards color-ideas, unlike shape-ideas, as “blank effects” lacking the “of-ness” that corresponds to my propositional ofness. On my reading, by contrast, color- and shape-ideas each possess both kinds of intentionality. Second, unlike Ott, I argue that Locke takes shape-ideas to be perfect “marks or signs” of powers to produce ideas (Shapiro 2010, 561). Locke doesn’t, implausibly, take these ideas to be perfect marks or signs of the very shapes they are propositionally of.

  35. 35.

    This claim would require serious qualification to be defensible. However, here is all Locke need be committed to: the more we “perfect” a substance idea, the more we may expect that there will be reliable generalizations concerning “coexistence” of the features collected in the idea with additional ones, and this expectation is relevant to induction.

  36. 36.

    Boyd (1991, 131–2). If this is right, Locke’s position resembles Boyd’s own conception of “natural kinds” (1999, 2010), as well as that of Millikan (2000).

  37. 37.

    On Locke’s use of ‘property’ to mean proprium in the sense derived from Porphyry, see e.g. Ayers (1991, vol. 2, 21, 67–74) and Pasnau (2011, 658–60). Contrary to Pasnau, I am arguing that Locke’s embrace of natural kinds in the Essay does “depend on the notion of an explanatory essence” from which a species’ observable properties flow.

  38. 38.

    Anstey (2011, ch. 11); cf. the section “Converging on a real essence” in Shapiro (1999, 576–82). Kornblith (1993, ch. 2) sketches a similar account of Locke’s implicit view of “chemical method,” but claims it contradicts Locke’s “official position.” Several interpreters besides Anstey and myself have argued that Locke officially embraces natural kinds. However, their conceptions differ from the one I intend. According to Conn (2002), what is required for there to be natural kinds is that (a) each set of perceptible features corresponds to some shared internal constitution. As I read Locke, he denies (a). Instead, he holds there to be natural kinds in the sense that (b) some ways of sorting objects by their perceptible features count as more natural than others, by coming closer to corresponding to a shared internal constitution. Though Stuart (1999, 285–91) discusses Boyd and Kornblith, I read him as attributing to Locke a qualified version of (a), not (b). On the other hand, Pasnau (2011, 642–7) attributes an embrace of natural kinds in a very strong sense, for which I find no evidence in the Essay: “there is a unique system of species (and higher genera) that best captures the similarities and differences among individuals.” For an analysis of Locke’s carefully reasoned ambivalence about whether there are any “prefixed Bounds” of species, any boundaries “made by Nature” (3.6.30:457–8, 3.6.43:466), see Shapiro (1999, 582–7).

  39. 39.

    A parallel claim hold for ideas of modes, such as the ideas of a triangle and of injustice.

  40. 40.

    Locke agrees with this claim in the case of simple ideas and ideas of modes. Here the idea serves not just as nominal essence of a species, but also as its real essence (3.3.18:418, 3.4.3:421, 3.5.14:436). To learn what makes an action an injustice or makes a body crimson, it suffices to inspect the respective ideas (provided, in the latter case, that one has learned the general lessons of Essay 2.8 about color-ideas). Of course, such inspection is a far cry from the serious intellectual work Descartes envisions.

  41. 41.

    See the previous note.

  42. 42.

    In conceding that Locke could even make sense of distinct complex ideas that share an object in the propositional sense, I am imagining that he would allow a qualification to (a) of Sect. 2.3.2. Consider the rare case in which distinct substance ideas mutually agree with respect to “necessary connexion,” whence the same objects must conform to each idea. In such a case, I presume, he would count both ideas as being of the same species in the propositional sense.

  43. 43.

    For a defense of sophisticated versions of both Lockean and Cartesian rationalism, based on an entirely different bifurcation of content, see Chalmers (2012).

  44. 44.

    See e.g. Brandom (2008, ch. 6).

  45. 45.

    See especially Brandom (1994, ch. 8).

  46. 46.

    Brandom has recently expressed openness to notions of “representation” that are distinct from the “discursive representational” notions that fall directly out of propositional intentionality (2011, 209–19). However, he doesn’t raise the question whether the same conceptually contentful item might “represent” distinct objects in the discursive and non-discursive senses.

  47. 47.

    Millikan (1993, 363).

  48. 48.

    See also Mark Wilson’s case studies in the history of science (2000, 2006). Wilson advocates “the ‘correlational point of view’: we objectively study how an unfolding reasoning process manages to arrange itself with respect to an independent reality…. This supplies a primitive notion of “truth condition” that is entirely erected upon the correspondences uncovered…” (2000, 384).

  49. 49.

    Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the Australian National University and the University of New South Wales. For helpful discussion, I would like to thank those audiences as well as the organizers and participants of the Berlin workshop that resulted in this volume, especially Martin Lenz, Antonia LoLordo, Dominik Perler and Anik Waldow. I dedicate the paper to the memory of Joseph L. Camp, Jr., who first made me want to learn from Early Modern theories of intentionality.

References

  • Adam, Charles, and Paul Tannery (eds.). 1964–1976. Oeuvres de Descartes. Paris: J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alanen, Lilli. 2003. Descartes’s concept of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anstey, Peter. 2011. Locke and natural philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Atherton, Margaret. 2007. Locke on essences and classification. In The Cambridge companion to Locke’s ‘Essay concerning human understanding’, ed. Lex Newman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayers, Michael. 1991. Locke: Epistemology and ontology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayers, Michael. 1998. Ideas and objective being. In The Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy, ed. D. Garber and M. Ayers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, Richard. 1991. Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosophical Studies 61: 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, Richard. 1999. Kinds as the ‘workmanship of men’: Realism, constructivism, and natural kinds. In Rationalität, Realismus, Revision, ed. J. Nida-Rümelin. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, Richard. 2010. Realism, natural kinds, and philosophical methods. In The semantics and metaphysics of natural kinds, ed. H. Beebee and N. Sabbarton-Leary. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing and discursive commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 2008. Between saying and doing: Towards an analytic pragmatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 2011. Pragmatism, expressivism, and anti-representationalism: Local and global possibilities. In his Perspectives on pragmatism: Classical, recent and contemporary. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Deborah. 2007. Objective being in Descartes: That which we know or that by which we know. In Representation and objects of thought in medieval philosophy, ed. H. Lagerlund. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carriero, John. 2009. Between two worlds: A reading of Descartes’s Meditations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David. 2012. Constructing the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clemenson, David. 2007. Descartes’s theory of ideas. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conn, Christopher Hughes. 2002. Locke on natural kinds and essential properties. Journal of Philosophical Research 27: 475–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cottingham, John, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch, and Anthony Kenny, trans. 1984–1991. The philosophical writings of Descartes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Rosa, Raffaella. 2010. Descartes and the puzzle of sensory representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Doyle, John, Trans. 2001. The Conimbricenses: Some questions on signs (includes translation of Book 1, chapter 1 of the Coimbran Dialectic of 1607). Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry. 1998. Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grüne, Stefanie. 2010. René Descartes. In Ideen: Repräsentationalismus in der frühen Neuzeit, vol. 2, ed. Dominik Perler and Johannes Haag. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, Paul. 1996. Descartes on misrepresentation. Journal of the History of Philosophy 34: 357–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, Paul. 2002. Direct realism, intentionality, and the objective being of ideas. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83: 163–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, Hilary. 1993. Inductive inference and its natural ground: An essay in naturalistic epistemology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennon, Thomas. 2007. Locke on ideas and representation. In The Cambridge companion to Locke’s ‘Essay concerning human understanding’, ed. Lex Newman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenz, Martin. 2010a. John Locke. In Ideen: Repräsentationalismus in der frühen Neuzeit, vol. 2, ed. Dominik Perler and Johannes Haag. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenz, Martin. 2010b. Locke’s Sprachkonzeption. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1975 [1689]. An essay concerning human understanding, ed. P. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mattern, Ruth. 1986. Locke on natural kinds as the ‘workmanship of the understanding’. Locke Newsletter 17: 45–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, Ruth. 1993. White Queen psychology; or, the last Myth of the Given. In her White Queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, Ruth. 2000. On clear and confused ideas: An essay about substance concepts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mori, Gianluca. 2012. Hobbes, Descartes, and ideas: A secret debate. Journal of the History of Philosophy 50: 197–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naaman-Zauderer, Noa. 2010. Descartes’ deontological turn: Reason, will, and virtue in the later writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, Alan. 1996. The falsity in sensory ideas: Descartes and Arnauld. In Interpreting Arnauld, ed. E. Kremer. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nuchelmans, Gabriel. 1983. Judgment and proposition: From Descartes to Kant. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ott, Walter. 2012. What is Locke’s theory of representation? British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20: 1077–1095.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pasnau, Robert. 1997. Theories of cognition in the later Middle Ages. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pasnau, Robert. 2011. Metaphysical themes: 1274–1671. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perler, Dominik. 1996. Repräsentation bei Descartes. Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Perler, Dominik. 2010. Einleitung. In Ideen: Repräsentationalismus in der frühen Neuzeit, vol. 1, ed. Dominik Perler and Johannes Haag. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, Jesse. 2000. The duality of content. Philosophical Studies 100: 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Lionel. 1999. Toward ‘perfect collections of properties’: Locke on the constitution of substantial sorts. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29: 551–593.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Lionel. 2010. Two kinds of intentionality in Locke. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 91: 554–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Lionel. 2012. Objective being and ‘ofness’ in Descartes. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 84: 378–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, Alison. Forthcoming. Representation. In The Cambridge Descartes lexicon, ed. L. Nolan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stuart, Matthew. 1999. Locke on natural kinds. History of Philosophy Quarterly 16: 277–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, Francisco. 1597. Disputationes metaphysicae. In Disputaciones metafísicas, ed. and trans. S. Rábade Romeo, S. Caballero Sánchez and A. Puigcerver Zanón. Madrid: Gredos, 1960–1966.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wee, Cecilia. 2006. Material falsity and error in Descartes’ meditations. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wells, Norman. 1984. Material falsity in Descartes, Arnauld, and Suarez. Journal of the History of Philosophy 22: 25–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wells, Norman. 2003. The Conimbricenses, Descartes, Arnauld, and the two ideas of the sun. Modern Schoolman 81: 27–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Margaret. 1990. Descartes on the representationality of sensation. Repr., in her Ideas and mechanism: Essays on early modern philosophy. 69–83. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Mark. 2000. Inference and correlational truth. In Circularity, definition and truth, ed. A. Chapuis and A. Gupta, 371–395. New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Mark. 2006. Wandering significance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lionel Shapiro .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Shapiro, L. (2013). Intentionality Bifurcated: A Lesson from Early Modern Philosophy?. In: Lenz, M., Waldow, A. (eds) Contemporary Perspectives on Early Modern Philosophy. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol 29. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6241-1_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics