Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 107))

Abstract

The topic of legal objectivity rotates around the determination of the status of the norms that constitute the major premise of the practical syllogism representing the formal scheme of judicial decisions' justification. Those who deny the objectivity of law believe that the existence and meaning of legal norms depend on the opinion of judges and jurists considered individually. The different versions of the objectivity of law reject this sceptical conclusion. The strongest versions of objectivity accepted by the different doctrines of natural law presuppose metaphysical realism and rule out the idea that what seems correct to someone can determine what is effectively correct; the weakest versions, upheld by legal positivism, believe—at least in relation to the existence of legal social practice—that what seems correct to most members of a community determines what is effectively correct. Does a space exist between these two versions of objectivity? In this essay arguments are put forward in support of a negative answer.

In 1977, John Leslie Mackie published an essay on Ronald Dworkin, entitled “The Third Theory of Law”. In this essay, Mackie presents Dworkin’s theory of law's thought as an unsuccessful attempt to indicate a theory of law that was alternative both to legal positivism and to natural law theories. The criticisms that I make here of a conception of aspiring to occupy an intermediary space between strong conceptions and “conventionalist” legal objectivity ones are in line with Mackie’s arguments, and this explains the title of this paper.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The term ‘descriptivism’ refers to the epistemological conception according to which the task of the language of knowledge is to represent the world “as it is.” To use a well-known metaphor by Richard Rorty (1980, 12–13), the descriptivists believe that the human mind works like a mirror able “to mirror reality.” See also Villa (2004, 141–156).

  2. 2.

    On holism, see Duhem (1954), Quine (1953a, 20–46, b, 47–64, 1960), Gargani (1985).

  3. 3.

    In this connection, Andrei Marmor (1992, 79) observes that “holism, however, does not necessarily lead to a coherence theory. It is a negative view in the sense that it provides no answer to the question of a substitute for foundationalism, for which status a coherence theory of knowledge is only one candidate.”

  4. 4.

    There are also weaker conceptions of holism than that presented by Raz. See Iglesias Vila (1999, 215–217), Maniaci (2008, 219–220).

  5. 5.

    Rawls, for instance, mentions both Nelson Goodman, who uses an argumentative scheme similar to his own to explain inductive and deductive inference, and Joel Feinberg, who compares the argumentative method of philosophical discussion to discussions in courts of justice, where principles and legal precedents are continually adjusted to one another. See Goodman (1973, 64), Feinberg (1973, 34).

  6. 6.

    After introducing the role that reflective equilibrium plays in moral philosophy, Rawls (1971, 49) writes: “but there is a contrast, say, with physics. To take an extreme case, if we have an accurate account of the motions of the heavenly bodies that we do not find appealing, we cannot alter these motions to conform to a more attractive theory. It is simply good fortune that the principles of celestial mechanics have their intellectual beauty (Hanen 1983).”

  7. 7.

    I use the expression ‘post-analytical constructivism’ to refer to the epistemological perspective that derives from Wittgenstein’s later reflections. See Hanen (1983). For a full presentation of this philosophical conception see Villa (1993, 187–228).

  8. 8.

    I here follow Pino (1998, 187–228).

  9. 9.

    Peczenik (1990, 178) clarifies his statement as follows: “If the norm- or value-system in question is more coherent than any competing system, then it is prima facie better justified and more rational than any competing system. If the norm- or value-system in question is more coherent than any competing system, then there exists a prima facie reason that it is correct.”

  10. 10.

    MacCormick (2005, 276). For a criticism of the recent developments of MacCormick’s theory of legal reasoning, see Schiavello (2011, 139–154).

  11. 11.

    The fundamental thesis of metaphysical realism is that every utterance is made true or untrue by an objective reality whose existence is independent of our knowledge. See, Dummett (1981, 434). Hirst (1967, 77) defines realism as “the view that material objects exist externally to us and independently of our sense experience. Realism is thus opposed to idealism, which holds that no such material objects or external realities exist apart from our knowledge or consciousness of them, the whole universe thus being dependent on the mind or in some sense mental”.

  12. 12.

    This option is accepted by MacCormick (2005, 277) among others: “The kind of reasoning which goes forward in legal decision-making, legal argumentation, and indeed in legal thought in all its forms and levels is, as this book in common with other contemporary authors maintains, a form of practical reasoning. All practical reasoning works on the presuppositions that there may be some matters upon which opinion can be right or wrong. It proceeds under a pretension to correctness, an implicit claim to being correct, not just to being boldly or confidential asserted”.

  13. 13.

    On the role of coherence in law, see Raz (1994, 277–325), Schiavello (2001, 233–243), Pérez Bermejo (2013 in this volume).

  14. 14.

    This objection was presented particularly effectively by Ronald Dworkin (1977, 46–80) in the context of his critical analysis of Hart’s theory of obligation. See Hart’s replies in Hart, (1994, 254–259). Dworkin refines his criticism of conventionalism in Dworkin (2006, 4 ff.).

  15. 15.

    Dworkin in some writings develops a “deflationist” attitude to objectivity. He maintains that it is not appropriate to talk of objectivity in relation to interpretation, since the correctness or otherwise of affirmations in this sphere of discourse entirely depends on questions that are internal to the practice in question and not on questions that are in some way to be connected to a reality external to the practice. In other words, in the specific case of interpretative practices he considers ‘objectivity’ and ‘truth’ as redundant words. Dworkin uses this argument to criticize that form of scepticism that he defines as external or Archimedean. The external sceptic, for instance, thinks that it cannot be affirmed that the utterance ‘slavery is unjust’ is true since in the universe something like the injustice of the slavery does not exist. According to Dworkin, the mistake of external scepticism is not understanding that “the game being played” does not have among its rules that of correspondence with the reality; it consists, rather, in presenting the best possible arguments in support of one’s opinions or beliefs. Therefore, when external scepticism maintains that our convictions are not “real”, it affirms a true thing but also an obvious one without any utility. These observations by Dworkin are nevertheless hardly compatible with his criticism of conventionalism and his “one right answer” thesis. See Dworkin (1983, 287–313), Id. (1996, 87–139), Coleman (1995, in particular 48–61), Stavropoulos (1996, in particular 160–162).

  16. 16.

    Dworkin (1977, 105). See also Greenawalt (1992, 208–212).

  17. 17.

    A convincing in-depth analysis of this theme can be found for example in Foster Wallace (2006, 66–127).

  18. 18.

    MacCormick (1994, 287–288) for example observes: “That there can be common patterns of criticism of conduct or states of affairs depends upon our conceiving that some patterns are willed as common patterns for all people in given circumstances. We can conceive of that independently of our own will in the matter, but not independently of our beliefs about the will of other members of our social group…”. Cf. Duff (1980, 68–73), Id. (1986, 74–98).

  19. 19.

    Raz (1996, 260). See Bertea (2007, 67–81).

  20. 20.

    “…to the extent that the law is determinate (as it is, for example, in easy cases), the correct answers must be objectively correct”. (Coleman and Leiter 1995, 246. Authors’ italics).

References

  • Bermejo, J.M.P. 2007. Alcune osservazioni sul valore della coerenza nei sistemi giuridici. Diritto e Questioni Pubbliche 7: 43–59. www.dirittoequestionipubbliche.org.

  • Bermejo, J.M.P. 2013. Coherence: an outline in six metaphors and four rules. In Coherence: insights from philosophy, jurisprudence and artificial intelligence, eds. M. Araszkiewicz, J. \( \check{\rm S} \)avelka, --. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertea, S. 2007. A critique of inclusive-positivism. Archiv für Rechts- und Sozial Philosophie 93(1): 67–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bobbio, N. 1993. Teoria generale del diritto. Torino: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J.L. 1983. Negative and positive positivism. In Ronald Dworkin and contemporary jurisprudence, ed. M. Cohen, 28–48. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J.L. 1995. Truth and objectivity in law. Legal Theory 1: 33–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J.L., and B. Leiter. 1995. Determinacy, objectivity, and authority. In Law and interpretation. Essays in legal philosophy, ed. A. Marmor, 203–278. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R.A. 1980. Legal obligation and the moral nature of law. The Juridical Review 25: 61–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R.A. 1986. Trials & punishments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. 1954. The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press. or. ed. 1914.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. 1981. The interpretation of Frege’s philosophy. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1977. Taking rights seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1983. My reply to Stanley Fish (and Walter Benn Michaels): Please don’t talk about objectivity any more. In The politics of interpretation, ed. W.J.T. Mitchell, 287–313. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s empire. London: Fontana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1996. Objectivity and truth: You’d better believe it. Philosophy and Public Affairs 25: 87–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 2006. Justice in robes. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1973. Social philosophy. New York: Englewood Cliffs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster Wallace D. 2006. Authority and American usage. In Id., Consider the lobster and other essays, 66–127. New York: Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gargani, A.G. 1985. Lo stupore e il caso. Roma-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. 1973. Fact, fiction and forecast. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenawalt, K. 1992. Law and objectivity. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanen, M. 1983. Justification as coherence. In Law, morality, and rights, ed. M.A. Stewart, 67–92. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 1994. The concept of law. In with postscript, 2nd ed, ed. P.A. Bulloch and J. Raz. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1st ed. 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, R.J. 1967. Realism. In The encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. P. Edwards. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1969. Convention. A philosophical study. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 1994. Legal reasoning and legal theory, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon. 1st ed. 1978.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 2005. Rhetoric and the rule of law. A theory of legal reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J.L. 1977. The third theory of law. Philosophy and Public Affairs 1/1: 3–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maniaci, G. 2008. Razionalità ed equilibrio riflessivo nell’argomentazione giudiziale. Torino: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. 1992. Interpretation and legal theory. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. 1998. An essay on the objectivity of law. In Analyzing law: New essays in legal theory, ed. B. Bix. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, M.S. 1995. Interpreting interpretation. In Law and interpretation. Essays in legal philosophy, ed. A. Marmor, 1–29. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. 1990. On law and reason. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. 2005. Scientia juris. Legal doctrine as knowledge of law and as a source of law. Dordrecht/Berlin/Heidelberg/New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pino, G. 1998. Coerenza e verità nell’argomentazione giuridica. Alcune riflessioni. Rivista internazionale di filosofia del diritto, IV serie, LXXV, 1: 84–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. 1953a. Two dogmas of empiricism. In Id., From a logical point of view, 20–46. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. 1953b. The problem of meaning in linguistics. In Id., From a logical point of view, 47–64. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. 1960. Word and object. Cambridge: The M.I.T. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1993. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1999. A theory of justice. Revised edition. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 1994. The relevance of coherence. In Id., Ethics in the public domain. Essays in the morality of law and politics, 277–325. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 1996. Intention in interpretation. In The autonomy of law. Essays on legal positivism, ed. R.P. George, 249–286. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. 1980. Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, A. 1958. On law and justice. London: Stevens & Sons Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiavello, A. 2001. On coherence and law: An analysis of different models. Ratio Juris 14: 233–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiavello, A. 2011. Neil MacCormick’s second thoughts on legal reasoning and legal theory. A defence of the original view. Ratio Juris 24: 139–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stavropoulos, N. 1996. Objectivity in law. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vila, M.I. 1999. El problema de la discreción judicial. Una aproximación al conocimiento jurídico. Madrid: Centro de Estudios Políticos y Constitucionales.

    Google Scholar 

  • Villa, V. 1993. Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo. Torino: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Villa, V. 2004. Il positivismo giuridico: metodi, teorie e giudizi di valore. Lezioni di filosofia del diritto. Torino: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Viola, F. 1990. Il diritto come pratica sociale. Milano: Edizioni Universitarie Jaca.

    Google Scholar 

  • Viola, F., and G. Zaccaria. 1999. Diritto e interpretazione. Lineamenti di teoria ermeneutica del diritto. Roma-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. 1992. The irrelevance of moral objectivity. In Natural law theory. Contemporary essays, ed. R.P. George, 158–187. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aldo Schiavello .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schiavello, A. (2013). The Third Theory of Legal Objectivity. In: Araszkiewicz, M., Šavelka, J. (eds) Coherence: Insights from Philosophy, Jurisprudence and Artificial Intelligence. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 107. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6110-0_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics