Skip to main content

Legal Vices and Civic Virtue: Vice Crimes, Republicanism and the Corruption of Lawfulness

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Aristotle and The Philosophy of Law: Theory, Practice and Justice

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 23))

  • 2095 Accesses

Abstract

The most powerful advocates of the position that the law must nurture good character often draw on Aristotelian theories of virtue to ground the connection between law and virtue. While Aristotle believed that law and character were linked, it is ironic to note that he did not argue for the position evidenced in our vice laws that law was likely to succeed in instilling virtue. Indeed, Aristotle thought the project of using law to instill private virtue was nearly certain to fail. Aristotle’s deep concern was not for the way law protected private virtue within each person but the way law had to protect civic virtue between citizens.

This article argues that even from its foundations, the project of vice crimes as moral instruction is misconceived. The use of law for overly instrumental or narrow reasons opens law and legal institutions to abuse and factionalism. Lawyers, judges and others specially connected to law must first and foremost aim at addressing “legal vices,” vices internal to the institutions of law. Particularly, increasing factionalism and instrumentalism which disconnects law from the pursuit of the common good threatens our civic bonds. Most importantly, where civic bonds are disrupted, citizens have no reason to remain law abiding. The striking lesson, captured both in ancient philosophy and modern history, is that when legal vices grow unchecked and factions use the law to pursue narrow interests, ultimately law abidingness is corrupted and interest groups harm themselves as much as others.

Published in 7 Crim. Law and Phil. 61 (2012).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It nearly goes without saying that much of this is contentious. The distinction offered between moral and ethical is not uncontroversial, though I think conventional. Further, many liberals have importantly argued for forms of liberalism which take into account the development of personal virtues. In political theory, a famous example is Raz (1986). In criminal theory, Anthony Duff (2012) leads the way in finding a balance between the demands of liberalism and communitarian and virtue oriented goals.

  2. 2.

    Just as liberals strive to find a place for the concern of virtue in a liberal system, virtue theorists have worked mightily to balance the drive of virtue theories with the demands of liberal theories. See Yankah (2009: 1192–1197).

  3. 3.

    An outstanding explication of this concept can be found in William A. Edmundson (2006).

  4. 4.

    All future references to Aristotle’s Politics refer to the same translation.

  5. 5.

    All future references to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics refer to the same translation.

  6. 6.

    For an excellent example of the way criminal prohibitions contribute to and turn on virtue, see Kyron Huigens (1995: 1444–1449). In subsequent work, Huigens has moved away from virtue qua virtue and has disavowed his earlier republicanism and focused on an Aristotelian based view of practical reasoning instead.

  7. 7.

    Here, I avoid for the moment the engaging debate surrounding the tension between Book X of the Nicomachean Ethics and much of what comes earlier in the text. See EN X.8. What is clear is that in contrast with Plato, who viewed engagement in politics as sullying the philosopher, Aristotle views political engagement as part of the good for man. See Hitz (2011); Kraut (2002: 132–133).

  8. 8.

    It cannot be denied that even on this picture civic virtue is exclusionary because it extends only weakly to those outside our polity. It is important to repeat, however, that those outside our civic community retain a broad array of human rights. Further, even Aristotle’s conception of civic rights maintained a minimum amount of regard for the well-being of those who fall outside of citizenship, a concept I hope to develop further in the future (Pol. I.6.; III.6.). I am grateful to the referee for pressing this point.

  9. 9.

    Though I do think that Cohen’s intuition that there is republican virtue in feeling compelled to contribute more personal wealth to civic society when one understands that the polity’s distributive justice scheme is plainly unjust is entirely correct (Cohen 2008).

  10. 10.

    The exact requirements of civic duty will obviously differ from community to community, country to country. At various times in countries such as Israel and Germany, all or some citizens have been required to serve in national or military service for a year. In New Zealand, citizens are required to vote by law. While I would not import any particular practice wholesale into the United States, it is critical to note that both these examples show how different communities require civic duty while ensuring that citizens maintain ample space to pursue their life plans.

  11. 11.

    163 U.S. 537, 540 (1896).

Bibliography

  • Aristotle. 1941a. Politica. In The basic works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, 1113–1316. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1941b. Nicomachean ethics. In The basic works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, 927–1112. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braithwaite, John, and Philip Pettit. 1990. Not just deserts: A republican theory of criminal justice. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat, M. 1980. Aristotle on learning to be good. In Essays on Aristotle’s ethics, ed. A. Rorty, 69–92. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chishti, Mazaffar A. 2006. Immigration reform: Balancing enforcement and integration: Enforcing immigration rules: Making the right choices. New York University Journal of Legislation and Public Policy 10: 451, 452–455.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. 2008. Rescuing justice and equality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, John. 2005. Political animals and civic friendship. In Aristotle’s politics: Critical essays, ed. Richard Kraut and Steven Skultety, 65–89. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dagger, Richard. 2009. Republicanism and crime. In Legal republicanism: National and international perspectives, vol. 184, ed. Samantha Besson and José Luis Martí, 147–166. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Duff, Anthony. 2001. Punishment, communication, and community. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, Anthony. 2007. Answering for crime. Portland: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, Anthony. 2013. Virtue, vice and criminal law: A response to Huigens and Yankah. In Law, virtue and justice, ed. Amalia Amaya, and Hock Lai Ho. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edmundson, William A. 2006. The virtue of law-abidance. Philosopher’s Imprint 6: 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, Lon. 1964. The morality of law. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gararella, Robert. 2009. Tough on punishment: Criminal justice, deliberation and legal alienation. In Legal republicanism: National and international perspectives, vol. 184, ed. Samantha Besson and José Luis Martí, 167–184. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, Aaron. 2010. Rights, equality, and justice: A conference inspired by the moral and legal theory of David Lyons: Courage, political resistance, and self-deceit political law’s ethos: Reflections on the public practice of illegality. Boston University Law Review 90: 1771.

    Google Scholar 

  • George, R.P. 1993. Making men moral: Civil liberties and public morality. New York/Oxford: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, Jean. 1998. Punishment, feminism, and political identity: A case study in the expressive meaning of the law. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 11: 23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitz, Zena. 2011. Aristotle on self-knowledge and friendship. Philosopher’s Imprint 11: 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huigens, K. 1995. Virtue and inculpation. Harvard Law Review 108: 1423, 1444–1449

    Google Scholar 

  • Huigens, Kyron. 2002. Homicide in aretaic terms. Buffalo Criminial Law Review 6: 97, 104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, J., B. Bradford, M. Hough, A. Myhill, P. Quinton, and T.R. Tyler. 2012. Why do people comply with the law? Legitimacy and the influences of legal institutions. Electronic copy available at: http:// ssrn.com/abstract=1994490.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, Richard. 2002. Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, N. 1998. State punishment. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, David. 2008. The legal entrenchment of illegality. In The legacy of H.L.A. Hart, ed. M. Kramer, C. Grant, B. Colburn, and A. Harzistavrou, 29–43. Oxford: Oxford Scholarship Online.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1985. After virtue. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, S.E., and R.A. Duff. 1998. Criminalization and sharing wrongs. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 11: 7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martí, José Luis. 2009. The republican democratization of criminal law and justice. In Legal republicanism: National and international perspectives, vol. 184, ed. Samantha Besson and José Luis Martí, 123–146. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Jeffrie. 1973. Marxism and retribution. Philosophy & Public Affairs 2: 217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 1997a. Republicanism: A theory of freedom and government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 1997b. Republican theory and criminal punishment. Utilitas 9: 57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2002. Keeping republican freedom simple: On a difference with Quentin Skinner. Political Theory 30: 339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Postema, Gerald J. 2010. Rights, equality, and justice: A conference inspired by the moral and legal theory of David Lyons: Law’s ethos: Reflections on the public practice of illegality. Boston University Law Review 90: 1847, 1856.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1986. The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin. 1978. The foundations of modern political thought, vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin. 1984. The idea of negative liberty: Philosophical and historical perspectives. In Philosophy in history, ed. R. Rorty, J.B. Schneewind, and Q. Skinner, 193–221. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solum, Lawrence B. 2006. Natural justice. American Journal of Jurisprudence 51: 65, 89–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tierney, Brian. 1963. The prince is not bounded by the laws: Accursius and the origins of the modern state. Comparative Studies in Society and History 5: 378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tyler, T.R., and J. Fagan. 2008. Legitimacy and cooperation: Why do people help the police fight crime in their communities? Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 6: 231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 1994. Why law – Efficacy, freedom or fidelity. Law and Philosophy 13: 259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wishnie, Michael J. 2008. The low wage worker: Legal rights—Legal realities: Labor law after legalization. Minnesota Law Review 92: 1446.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yankah, Ekow N. 2004. Good guys and bad guys: Punishing character, equality and the irrelevance of moral character to criminal punishment. Cardozo Law Review 25: 1019.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yankah, Ekow N. 2009. Virtue’s domain. University of Illinois Law Review: 1167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yankah, Ekow N. 2011. A paradox in overcriminalization. New Criminial Law Review 14: 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yankah, Ekow N. 2012. Crime, freedom and civic bonds: Arthur Ripstein’s force and freedom: Kant’s legal and political philosophy. Criminal Law and Philosophy 6: 255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yankah, Ekow N. 2013. Liberal virtue law. In Virtue and justice, ed. Amalia Amaya, and Hock Lai Ho. Oxford: Hart Publishing, Forthcoming 2013.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ekow N. Yankah .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Yankah, E.N. (2013). Legal Vices and Civic Virtue: Vice Crimes, Republicanism and the Corruption of Lawfulness. In: Huppes-Cluysenaer, L., Coelho, N. (eds) Aristotle and The Philosophy of Law: Theory, Practice and Justice. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 23. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6031-8_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics