Advertisement

Orthodox Property Dualism+The Linguistic Theory of Vagueness=Panpsychism

  • Philip GoffEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Studies in Brain and Mind book series (SIBM, volume 6)

Abstract

This paper attempts to show that orthodox property dualists, if they are committed to the linguistic theory of vagueness, are obliged to hold that it can never be vague whether or not a given thing is conscious. Together with the commonsense assumption that some but not all macroscopic objects are conscious, this entails that the psycho-physical laws governing the emergence of consciousness are utterly precise such that a slight adjustment to a fundamental particle can make the difference between a macroscopic object having or lacking consciousness. I argue that this is a deeply implausible consequence, and hence that the orthodox property dualist who accepts the linguistic theory of vagueness must reject the commonsense assumption that some but not all macroscopic objects are conscious. Given her realism about consciousness, the property dualist is obliged to hold that all macroscopic objects are conscious.

Keywords

Linguistic Theory Phenomenal Property Phenomenal Concept Macroscopic Object Vague Predicate 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Antony, Michael V. 2006. Vagueness and the metaphysics of consciousness. Philosophical Studies 128(3):515–538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Chalmers, D. 1996. The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Chalmers, D. 2002. Consciousness and its place in nature. In Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings, ed. D. Chalmers, 247–272. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Chalmers, D. 2009. The two-dimensional argument against physicalism. In Oxford handbook to the philosophy of mind, ed. Brian P. McLaughlin, 313–339. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Coleman, S. 2006. Being realistic: Why panpsychism may entail panexperientialism. Journal of Consciousness Studies 13(10–11): 40–52.Google Scholar
  6. Coleman, S. 2009. The mind that abides. In Mind under matter, 83–107. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  7. Feigl, H. 1958/1967. The ‘mental’ and the ‘physical. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 2: 370–497. Reprinted (with a postscript) as Thementaland thephysical’. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  8. Goff, P. 2011. A posteriori physicalists get our phenomenal concepts wrong. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89(2): 191–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Goff, P. MS. Taking consciousness seriously.Google Scholar
  10. Goff, P., and D. Papineau. forthcoming. What’s wrong with strong necessities? Philosophical Studies Google Scholar
  11. Griffin, D.R. 1998. Unsnarling the world-knot: Consciousness, freedom, and the mind-body problem. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  12. Jackson, F. 1982. Epiphenomenal qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly 32: 127–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Lewis, D. 1986. On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  14. Lewis, D. 1994. Reduction of mind. In Companion to the philosophy of mind, ed. S. Guttenplan. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  15. Lockwood, M. 1989. Mind, brain, and the quantum. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Maxwell, G. 1979. Rigid designators and mind-brain identity. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9: 365–403.Google Scholar
  17. Nida-Rümelin, M. 2007. Grasping phenomenal properties. In Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge. New essays on consciousness and physicalism, ed. T. Alter and S. Walter, 307–349. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Papineau, D. 2002. Thinking about consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Russell, B. 1927. The analysis of matter. Repr., New York: Dover, 1954Google Scholar
  20. Schroer, R. 2010. Where’s the beef? Phenomenal concepts as both demonstrative and substantial. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88(3): 505–522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Sider, T. 2001. Four dimensionalism. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Stoljar, D. 2001. Two conceptions of the physical. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62: 253–281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Strawson, G. 2006. Realistic monism: Why physicalism entails panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies: Controversies in Science and the Humanities 13(10–11): 3–31.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of LiverpoolLiverpoolUK

Personalised recommendations