Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Research Ethics Forum ((REFF,volume 1))

  • 1304 Accesses

Abstract

Any justification of WWR will have to do with the war that frames context for the episode of WR at issue. The war itself will most likely not be the whole question, but it will be at least part of the question. Thus an important part of any justification of WWR will be the justification of the war in which the episode takes place – this much is clear. In examining this assumption, I have argued that any theory about the morality of war that includes an ad bellum proportionality condition will prohibit WWR and I have argued that all acceptable theories of this kind will include such a condition. However, at the end of the last chapter I noted that there are other traditions and theories about war, about why nations and states fight wars and about what wars are, which have more currency than JWT. For example, there are many people who study war in the discipline of International Relations (IR), the main academic field for the study of war in the modern world, where the prevailing view is realism, sometimes called realpolitik or power politics. And I said that this perspective is relevant to the present inquiry, because it provides an alternative way of looking at war, and (hence) at WR. One of the conclusions to be established is that, so far, the weapons researcher must be concerned about how the products of her work will be used, and especially that they will be used for unjustified wars and harmings, and hopes that they will not; but once she adopts the realist perspective, she should expect that these things will tend to happen.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There is more that one kind of realism. For the moment I will discuss realism as if it were a single coherent body of theory. It will not be necessary for us to look at all the variants of realism, but only the main tenets. Also, I noted that IR is the main field for the study of war in the modern world. Of course, IR overlaps with modern history, and for most of our understanding of past wars we have to consult the historian, and we rarely find history written for the point of view of JWT. I should acknowledge again that realism is not the only approach to be found in contemporary IR; the main alternatives are liberalism and constructivism. For a useful summary of these alternatives, and how they differ from realism, see Nexon (2009: 28–40).

  2. 2.

    In the first chapter of his book, Clark gives a good overview of thoughts about war, and about the relationship between the state and war, and about the evolution of the nation state and war. He notes that Midlarsky is one of the few writers who sees war as a failure of the normal form of commerce between states, and hence, in contrast to the received account, a kind of discontinuity in the relations between states. See Clark (1988: 18–19). Hagan and Bickerton, who I mention in the text, are recent additions to this small group.

  3. 3.

    A new translation of On War, by Michael Howard and Peter Paret, came out in 1976, with commentary by the authors, essays by Bernard Brodie, and an especially commissioned index. This event, no doubt, stimulated much current interest in Clausewitz. Paret sees Clausewitz as a forerunner of what he called in 1991 the New Military History, a way of writing military history that saw attention turned away from the role of great captains, tactics and strategy and towards with interaction of war with the economy, politics and culture, see Paret (1993: 220–226), especially 225.

  4. 4.

    To force other states to its will, rather than negotiate with them, bargain with them, bribe them, cajole them, persuade them, trick them, etc., actions which make up the normal ways in which states deal with one another.

  5. 5.

    Not least because states are the only ones with the resources to commission WR.

  6. 6.

    Bull thinks that we should (therefore) take Clausewitz as making a recommendation about how wars should be conducted, rather than as a general description that covers all war, Bull (1977: 186), and thus the account would be seen to have a normative element, and the fact that all wars do not appear to be a continuation of state policy should not count against it.

  7. 7.

    This is a similar conclusion to that reached when we considered the full significance of ad bellum proportionality.

  8. 8.

    The Swedish phase ended with the battle of Nördlingen. Richelieu was keen to continue the war after the death of the king of Sweden two years earlier and France played an increasingly important role after the Swedish withdrawal.

  9. 9.

    There is, as ever, debate in the literature about just exactly why these countries entered the war, and there has been debate in particular over Sweden’s decision to participate. There is no doubt that Sweden did well out of the war, though at the cost of the life of their great king Gustav Adolf at the battle of Lützen: they secured access to the Baltic and were recognised as a ‘great power’. Ringmar suggests that the material gains won by Sweden were not its main objective and it was really after recognition as a great power, see Ringmar (1996). The entry of France, already a great power, is easier to understand.

  10. 10.

    A succinct summary of these issues can be found in Chapter 1 of Craig and George (1990). With reference to the Netherlands, Sweden and France, they write “It is perhaps no coincidence that these particular states were so successful, for they were excellent examples of the process that historians have described as the emergence of the modern state, the three principal characteristics of which were effective armed forces, an able bureaucracy and a theory of the state that …defined political interest in practical terms”, Craig and George (1990: 5). Also we may note that the term “composite state” has been applied to describe some of the ‘states’ of early modern Europe, such as those held by the Hapsburgs. The name implies that the states in question had diverse holdings, lands that had little to unite them except that they were acquired by the sovereign in a variety of ways. This is why it is customary to say that the House of Hapsburg, rather than Spain, Austria-Hungary, etc., was the principal in the war. Note also that the rulers of such states were concerned above all with maintaining their dynasties, which is why so much effort was expended in finding heirs, arranging marriages, etc., all of which is totally foreign to a modern states.

  11. 11.

    For instance, the status of Alsace as French or German was the cause of much friction between the two countries.

  12. 12.

    If it were, then the state would change when the government changes, but that does not usually take place. For instance when one party loses an election and another takes over, there is no change of state. A change of state takes place when the major institutions for the use and limitation of power change in significant ways, for instance when an absolute monarchy becomes a constitutional monarchy.

  13. 13.

    There is a great deal written on the subject, see Rogers (1995). For a good discussion of the series of weapons innovations involved, see also the essays in Steele and Dorland (2005).

  14. 14.

    The idea has a long history and can be understood in various other ways. What I have done here is to chose what Wight calls the ‘original meaning’, see Wight (1978: 173) and Chap. 17.

  15. 15.

    The situation is, however, an improvement on the stalemate of the Cold War era.

  16. 16.

    E.H.Carr sees war as more than merely possible in the states system; he sees it as always there, ‘lurking’ in the background. “The supreme importance of the military instrument lies in the fact that the ultima ratio of power in the international system is war…[w]ar lurks in the background of international politics” (Carr 1946: 109).

  17. 17.

    Other realists, like Hans Morgenthau and Carr, make similar remarks about ethics. To quote E.H.Carr again “no ethical standards are applicable to the relations between states” (Carr 1946: 153).

  18. 18.

    Orend cites Britain’s attempt to abolish the slave trade as a counter-example to the realist thesis that states pursue only their self-interest (Orend 2006: 226). Britain did this because an influential group of its citizens believed slavery was wrong and wanted it abolished – thus it was in the interest of Britain to try to end the slave trade. I see no inconsistency with realism here.

  19. 19.

    Thus Wight tells us “There are certain things that a power deems to be essential to its continued independence; these are its vital interests, which it will go to war to defend” (Wight 1986: 95). Wight also tells us that such language did not become standard until the nineteenth century.

  20. 20.

    It does not follow, however, that A could never be said to have just cause when it protects its vital interests by waging war. It would do so, for example, if were the victim of aggression – see below.

  21. 21.

    McGeorge Bundy, who was himself deeply engaged in the crisis, tells the story in Bundy (1990: 428–439). The US missiles were quietly withdrawn in exchange for the turnabout of the ships carrying the Soviet missiles.

  22. 22.

    One could have mentioned here the entry of Sweden and France into the Thirty Years War, to use our previous example. However, at least a case could have been made there in favour of religious or political alliances, rather than pure desire for gain as was clearly the motive for Frederick.

  23. 23.

    And this even extends to acquisition of, and power over, lands far distant from the home country. We may cite Germany, whose participation in the ‘scramble for Africa’ in the second half of the nineteenth century, the imperial phase of European conquest of the continent, was couched in terms of its security interest, and this is to be understood vis-à-vis the other interested European powers, namely France and Britain.

  24. 24.

    And it will still be hard if the obvious method, asking the populace what they want, does not give a clear result.

  25. 25.

    This is not necessarily how all socialists would have seen the situation. There were many different varieties of socialism, having different implications for the relationship between socialist and capitalist states.

  26. 26.

    The dependence of perception on belief has been a theme in post-empiricist philosophy. This was manifested, for example, in philosophy of science by criticisms of the idea that the scientific method began with observation and that theories were formulated by inductive generalisation from observation statements. The received view now is that observation is conditioned by theory.

  27. 27.

    The idea that if one state in Asia ‘falls’ to communism, then neighbouring states will collapse like dominos under communist insurgency was proposed first under the Eisenhower administration, Bundy (1990: 261). Vietnam was thought to be a ‘crucial’ domino in South East Asia. The consensus now is that the Vietnamese were simply resisting aggression from outside, as they had done in the past against French colonial rule.

  28. 28.

    Before that time, states were the main customers of WR, and hence weapons manufacturers needed to make goods that would be attractive to their consumers – I will have more the say about this in the next chapter. And as mentioned above, the emergence of the states system was marked by a big increased in the size and scale of weapons systems, notably ships of war.

  29. 29.

    It is conceivable that matters would not turn out this way, where there are great benefits from C’s conducting WWR for others – C would not take these into account in its own cost-benefit calculation – but such a scenario is hardly plausible. It is hardly plausible, in other words, that a given WWR programme conducted by C will have great benefits for A, B, etc., which then do not figure in C’s cost-benefit analysis under realism but would have done so under JWT.

  30. 30.

    Gordin believes this received account of the matter is wrong, and that the US did not expect Japan or surrender on August 14 and thought that more atomic weapons and an invasion of Japan would be necessary, see Gordin (2007: 5). This view seems at odds with the fact that the US was not planning to make any more atomic bombs – none were being made at Los Alamos and there was no more fissionable material available. The point made above, however, that the US was willing to bomb non-combatants in order to end the war as quickly as possible remains, whether the bombing was nuclear or conventional.

  31. 31.

    Some estimates are massively higher, with a million or more non-combatants killed in the war as a whole.

  32. 32.

    Totalitarian states are, however, much more likely to use the products of WR on their own citizens.

  33. 33.

    To reinforce this point, one need only mention the Abu Grabe and Guatanamo Bay prisons.

  34. 34.

    Other weapons technologies are closely guarded secrets. There has been no direct or formal transfer of nuclear weapons technology, even between the US and its ally Britain, but there have been clandestine transfers by individuals.

  35. 35.

    Thus if C is the object of unjustified aggression, as the US was at Pearl Harbour, and if C believes it needs to conduct ‘policy by other means’ and go to war given that it believes that this is the best way to protect its vital interests, and if it goes to war in order to resist aggression, has approval from the proper authority and so, as the US also did, then in fact C will be fighting a just war. Thus it certainly looked as if the US was fighting a just war against Japan until 1945, when it did not abide by jus in bello. So now we have an option for S who, by hypothesis, believes that states act according to the dictates of realism but wants only to undertake WWR when the war is just.

  36. 36.

    India and Israel are undeclared nuclear states, but everyone knows that they have nuclear weapons.

  37. 37.

    Which can be explained by the fact that Waltz is talking at the level of grand strategy rather than of mission or tactics.

  38. 38.

    Waltz has not given up on the idea: he has just (August 2012) argued that it would be a good idea for Iran to get nuclear weapons. See Waltz (2012).

  39. 39.

    Lundendorff is clearly anti-Semitic, and refers to the enemies of the German nation as the Jewish people and the Roman Church. Hitler substituted the Bolsheviks for the latter.

  40. 40.

    I am talking here about so-called general nuclear war when the ‘central systems’ are used. Some have suggested that there could be limited nuclear war; others believe that ‘escalation’ to general war would be inevitable. I side with the latter opinion.

  41. 41.

    There have been a number of recent re-evaluations of the relevance of Clausewitz in the nuclear age and also in the age of terror. For instance, the collection edited by Strachen and Herberg-Rothe (2009) argues for his continuing relevance.

References

  • Bull, H. 1977. The anarchical society. London: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bundy, M. 1990. Danger and survival. Melbourne: Schwartz and Wilkinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, E.H. 1946. The twenty years crisis. London: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, I. 1988. Waging war. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, G., and A. George. 1990. Force and statecraft, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forge, J. 2002. Corporate responsibility revisited. International Journal of Applied Ethics 16: 13–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giddens, A. 1989. Sociology. Oxford: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordin, M. 2007. Five days in August. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hagan, K., and I. Bickerton. 2007. Unintended consequences: The United States at war. London: Reaktion Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, P. 1987. The rise and fall of the great powers. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lebow, R. 2003. The tragic vision of politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ludendorff, E. 1936. The nation at war. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nexon, D. 2009. The struggle for power in early modern Europe. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orend, B. 2006. The morality of war. Peterborough: Broadview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paret, P. 1993. Understanding war. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ringmar, E. 1996. Identity, interest and action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, C. (ed.). 1995. The military revolution debate. Boulder: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steele, B., and T. Dorland. 2005. The heirs of Archimedes. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strachen, H., and A. Herberg-Rothe. 2009. Clausewitz in the twenty-first century. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Clausewitz, C. 1984. On war, ed. and trans.: M. Howard and P. Paret. Indexed edition. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waltz, K. 1981. The spread of nuclear weapons: More may be better. London: IISS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waltz, K. 2012. Why Iran should get the bomb. Foreign Affairs 91(4): 2–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wight, M. 1986. Power politics. Harmonsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Appendix: Total War and the Transcendence of War

Appendix: Total War and the Transcendence of War

In this appendix I will consider a view about the obsolescence of war, according to which states become so well-armed that they are too terrified to fight, and this may seem to be a reason in favour of WR. This position, as we might expect, is informed by the development of nuclear weapons. However, there are other considerations that are important here as well, including ideas of total war in the conventional (i.e. non-nuclear) sense, which I will also address in this section. These all represent challenges to Clausewitz’ view that war is the continuation of policy by other means if this is taken to be a complete account of all actual and possible war. What I think they do show is that there are different concepts of war, some of which have been instantiated in practice, and some, like general nuclear war, that are so far only possibilities, and not all conform to the Clausewitz dictum. We know that in the nuclear age, the period since 1945, there have been many wars and that some of these have been fought by nuclear-armed states. In fact the majority of nuclear armed states – US, USSR, Britain, France, India and Israel – have fought wars, though not against one another.Footnote 36 Chinese troops have fought against US and British forces in Korea, but China did not have nuclear weapons at the time. With the (possible) exception of the (short) Arab-Israeli wars, none of these wars were ‘total’ wars from the perspective of the nuclear-armed state.

A number of writers have said that nuclear war could not be in the interest of anyone and hence could not be ‘policy carried on by other means’. Even a limited nuclear war, with only a few weapons being used, would cause unprecedented casualties – the two tiny, by modern standards, atomic bombs used on Japan killed hundreds of thousands of people and utterly destroyed the cities of Hiroshima and Nagasaki. One single modern ICBM, with its payload of up to 14 warheads, could kill many millions. A fairly small number of such weapons therefore have the capacity to kill the majority of citizens of a country almost immediately and leave the survivors with few resources on which to live. A state that was the victim of such an attack would have most of its population killed and its territory rendered uninhabitable, and thus the state itself would cease to exist. It is unclear what could be gained by this, save for the elimination of an enemy that would seek to do the same – there is no other political gain that could be achieved by eliminating another state. The effects of nuclear weapons made it difficult, as we saw in Chap. 5, to enunciate any credible nuclear doctrine about when the weapons would be used, except as a deterrent. In which case, as sensible observers pointed out, would it not be better to get rid of them and hence ensure that they were not used by accident? Unfortunately, two side-benefits were claimed in the debate about nuclear weapons: that not only would nuclear armed states not fight each other with nuclear weapons, they would also not fight each other with conventional weapons – nuclear weapons would keep the peace – and also that nuclear armed states could extend their deterrence protection over non-nuclear armed states. Much discussion of these issues took place in the Cold War era.

With some of these ideas in mind, Waltz argued that it may be better for more states to be nuclear armed, an alarming claim that went against efforts to prevent the spread of nuclear weapons (so-called horizontal proliferation), but one that seems to sit well with the realist outlook. Waltz’ argument was simply that states possessing nuclear weapons would be very reluctant to fight – for the reasons given above – and hence the more states that had them, the more states that would refrain from waging war. I quote the following from his article, where he says that he reaches his “unusual conclusion” for six reasons (I cite two of these six):

First, international politics is a self-help system… Fifth, nuclear weapons can be used for defence as well as for deterrence. Some have argued that an apparently impregnable nuclear defence can be mounted. The Maginot Line has given defence a bad name. It nevertheless remains true that the incidence of wars decreases as the perceived difficulty of winning them increases. No one attacks a defence believed to be impregnable. Nuclear weapons may make it possible to approach the defensive ideal. If so, the spread of nuclear weapons will further help to maintain peace. (Waltz 1981: 30)

The first reason is a statement the basic tenet of realism that states have to look out for themselves. The fifth reason speculates that nuclear weapons are the ultimate defensive weapon, turning upside down the usual view that they are the ultimate offensive weapon.Footnote 37 Waltz’ view represents an apotheosis of realism, in which states are to ensure their security be acquiring the means to annihilate any potential enemy, and the states system is left in a multi-sided balance of terror – states would not merely present as pit-bulls, but as super-duper nuclear-armed Armageddon-style pit bulls.Footnote 38

The problem with this proposal, and with others that advocate any increase in nuclear weapons, is the price to pay if anything goes wrong. It is obvious that the more nuclear weapons there are and the more states that have them, the higher the likelihood of accidental or deliberate use. There is here, as there often is with discussions of nuclear weaponry, an air of paradox: Waltz proposes to make the world safer in the nuclear age by having more states acquire the means for nuclear annihilation, but surely by any normal calculation the more nuclear weapons there are, the less safe we will be. This apparent paradox is due to the tension between what appears rational from the perspective of an individual state and from the point of view of the system as a whole. If no one had nuclear weapons, then there could be no nuclear war and everyone, the system as a whole, would well be better off in the sense that no nuclear Armageddon was possible. But once some states have nuclear weapons, then others (might) feel threatened – as indeed they probably should if realism is right – and so want to have them for themselves. The original nuclear weapons states may then feel correspondingly less secure and so decide to get more and better weapons, and so on and on. This is the security dilemma again, in which moves intended to enhance the security of one state provoke a response from other states, which raises the quantity and quality of armaments, and so makes everyone less secure, and provokes another round of the arms race. But the fact that international politics is a self-help system does not mean that states never co-operate – they do so when it is in their self-interest. And there has been much co-operation in preventing nuclear proliferation, with many states that could easily develop such weapons refraining from doing so because, contra Waltz, they do not think that more would be better.

I said above that the advent of nuclear weapons calls into question Clausewitz’ view if this is taken to be a description of all war, because nuclear war could not fulfil any political aim short of annihilating a rival, which in turn is not a continuation of states’ dealings with one another by ‘different means’ and forcing the opponent to submit. This ‘transcendence of war’, as far as war using nuclear weapons is concerned, is a consequence of the existence of these weapons. We should note that there are concepts of total war which have also been proposed in opposition of Clausewitz, but for a different reasons. There are in fact two senses of “total war” in the literature, and they are related. Total war normally refers to a war in which at least one side tries to maximise the use of its resources, human, economic, etc., to the prosecution of the conflict. Total wars have only become possible with the ability of states to centralise administration and organise and mobilise society and the economy. Total war was thus not possible before the middle of nineteenth century, hence after Clausewitz time. One issue here is the scope of non-combatant immunity in total war. For instance, if munitions or armaments workers live in an area surrounding an arms or munitions factory, as Alfred Krupp’s workers did, are they, as well as the factory, legitimate targets for enemy bombers? Various positions have been taken on this question, but they are not directly relevant to our present concern.

Another idea about total war expressed by one of the German commanders of WW1, Erich Ludendorf mentioned in the main text above, about the second sense of the term, suggests that there are really no non-combatants in modern war. Ludendorf believed that Clausewitz was out-dated – his theories should be “thrown overboard” (Ludendorff 1936: 24) – because he underestimated the way in which a state could fight. Ludendorff speaks of the nation, not merely the state, being engaged in a life and death struggle when it fights a modern war – obviously, his experiences in WW1 informed his views. One reason it is worth referring to Ludendorff here is that he was a Nazi sympathiser, an associate of Hitler’s in the 1920s, and perhaps it is no coincidence that plans and directives for the war on the Eastern Front in WW2 contained echoes of his ideas on total war.Footnote 39 The American Civil War, from the South’s point of view at any rate, and WW2, certainly from the perspective of the Soviet Union, Japan and Germany, were total wars in Ludendorf’s sense. With these experiences in mind, it looks as if total war will, in practice, be a struggle for survival. If a state is willing to put all of its resources into fighting a war and it loses, then it appears to follow that it has lost all of its resources, used up in the fighting, and hence as these begin to run out, the conflict does become a struggle for survival. This was the experience of Germany in both world wars, although it had the good sense to choose to surrender in WW1. States that lose total wars do not survive. The South did not survive the American Civil War, the German Empire did not survive WW1, the Third Reich did not survive WW2, and so forth. The people and the land did survive in these cases, and form new political organisations and so new states. There is some similarity here with the idea of nuclear war. With nuclear war it is guaranteed that states will not survive and neither will the majority of the people, and hence nuclear war is total war where many do not survive, and as such is again a kind of limiting case.Footnote 40

According to Clausewitz’ notion, even general or absolute war is more limited than this. And with its vital interest in security, it is not rational for a state to risk its survival for any political objective, though Clausewitz acknowledges that wars can be fought for the survival of the state. He was aware that weaponry would improve and wars become more deadly, but he could not have anticipated the advent of nuclear weapons. Moreover, Ludendorf’s idea of total war is clearly at odds with Clausewitz, at least in the sense that the latter thought that wars should always be in accordance with the political process. In the three examples just mentioned, the loser started the war, by making the first move. Those who start wars do not do so thinking that they will become enmeshed in a total war that they will eventually lose, though Germany started both world wars because it thought it had a better chance of winning if it decided when to start wars that it thought it had to fight. However, some states fight total wars and win when its enemy does not commit all of its resources to the war, and hence when their enemy does not engage in total war. The Vietnam War from the North’s point of view was such a war. The North fought with all it had, and the South and its US ally eventually gave up – one might say that the policy conducted by the US ‘by other means’ was in the end not worth pursuing. What this example makes clear is that states fighting total wars really have no choice, for if they give up, they will cease to exist. Had the South and the US prevailed in the Vietnam War, the communist North Vietnam would not have been allowed to continue. We can conclude that Clausewitz’ view of war is not outdated in the modern era – it should not be thrown overboard – with the advent of nuclear weapons or with the ability of states to mobilise all their resources to fight.Footnote 41 It is rather than in our thinking about wars and the states system we need to supplement this view with (at least) two other concepts.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Forge, J. (2013). War and Realism. In: Designed to Kill: The Case Against Weapons Research. Research Ethics Forum, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5736-3_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics