Advertisement

The Berlin Group and the Vienna Circle: Affinities and Divergences

  • Nikolay MilkovEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science book series (BSPS, volume 273)

Abstract

The Vienna Circle and the Berlin Group were schools of scientific philosophy that fought a common enemy—philosophical idealism and philosophical traditionalism in general. Their historically decisive influence makes it all the more disappointing that their intertwined story has not come down to us with due regard to its complexity. For the received account—that the Vienna Circle directed the scientific philosophy of the 1920s and 1930s—perpetuates an oversimplified picture of a seminal development of twentieth-century Western intellectual history. The fact is that the Berlin Group was an equal partner with the Vienna Circle, albeit one that pursued an itinerary of its own. But while the latter presented its defining projects in readily discernible terms and became immediately popular, the Berlin Group, whose project was at least as significant as that of its Austrian counterpart, remained largely unrecognized. The task of this chapter is to distinguish the Berliners’ work from that of the Vienna Circle and to bring to light its impact in the history of scientific philosophy.

Keywords

Logical Analysis Analytic Philosophy Philosophical Logic Logical Positivist Logical Empiricism 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Anonymous. 1930. Gesellschaft für empirische philosophie: Berlin. Erkenntnis 1: 72–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Ayer, Alfred. 1936. Language, truth, and logic. London: Gollancz.Google Scholar
  3. Blumberg, Albert E., and Helmut Feigl. 1931. Logical positivism. A new movement in European philosophy. Journal of Philosophy 28: 281–296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Carnap, Rudolf. 1936. Von der Erkenntnistheorie zur Wissenschaftslogik. In Wiener Kreis, ed. Michael Stoeltzner and Thomas Uebel, 260–266. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.Google Scholar
  5. Cohen, Hermann. 1902. Logik der reinen Erkenntnis. Berlin: Cassirer.Google Scholar
  6. Dahms, Hans-Joachim. 1994. Positivismusstreit. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  7. Danneberg, Lutz. 1998. Der logische Empirismus der zwanziger und dreißiger Jahre: Rezeption und Ausstrahlung. In Hans Reichenbach: Philosophie im Umkreis der Physik, ed. Hans Poser and Ulrich Dirks, 119–138. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.Google Scholar
  8. Danneberg, Lutz, and Schernus Wilhelm. 1994. Die Gesellschaft für wissenschaftliche Philosophie. In Hans Reichenbach und die Berliner Gruppe, ed. Lutz Danneberg et al., 391–481. Braunschweig: Vieweg.Google Scholar
  9. Danneberg, Lutz, et al. (eds.). 1994. Hans Reichenbach und die Berliner Gruppe. Braunschweig: Vieweg.Google Scholar
  10. Dubislav, Walter. 1926a. Die Fries’sche Lehre von der Begründung: Darstellung und Kritik. Dömitz: Mattig.Google Scholar
  11. Dubislav, Walter. 1926b. Über den sogenannten analytischen und synthetischen Urteile. Berlin: Weiss.Google Scholar
  12. Dubislav, Walter. 1926c. Über die definition. Berlin: Weiss.Google Scholar
  13. Dubislav, Walter. 1927. Über die definition, 2nd ed. Berlin: Weiss.Google Scholar
  14. Dubislav, Walter. 1929a. Zur Methodenlehre des Kritizismus. Langensalza: Beyer & Söhne.Google Scholar
  15. Dubislav, Walter. 1929b. Joseph Petzoldt in memoriam. Annalen der Philosophie 8: 289–295.Google Scholar
  16. Dubislav, Walter. 1929c. Elementarer Nachweis der Widerspruchslosigkeit des Logik-Kalküls. Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik 161: 107–112.Google Scholar
  17. Dubislav, Walter. 1930. Über den sogenannten Gegenstand der Mathematik. Erkenntnis 1: 27–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Dubislav, Walter. 1931. Die definition, 3rd ed. Leipzig: Felix Meiner.Google Scholar
  19. Dubislav, Walter. 1933. Naturphilosophie. Berlin: Junker und Dünnhaupt.Google Scholar
  20. Dubislav, Walter. 1937. Zur Unbegründlichkeit der Forderungssätze. Theoria 3: 330–342.Google Scholar
  21. Eberhardt, F., and C. Glymour. 2008. Introduction. In The concept of probability in the mathematical representation of reality, ed. Hans Reichenbach, and trans. Frederick Eberhardt, and Clark Glymour, 1–36. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
  22. Einstein, Albert. 1928. Hans Reichenbach: Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre. Deutsche Literaturzeitung 1: 19–20.Google Scholar
  23. Ferrari, Massimo. 2008. Moritz Schlick in Wien: Die Wende der Philosophie. In Moritz Schlick: Leben, Werk und Wirkung, ed. Fynn O. Engler and Mathias Iven, 91–113. Berlin: Parerga.Google Scholar
  24. Franke, Holger. 1991. Leonard Nelson. Ammersbek bei Hamburg: Verlag an der Lottbek.Google Scholar
  25. Friedman, Michael. 1992. Kant and the exact sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Friedman, Michael. 1999. Reconsidering logical positivism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Friedman, Michael. 2005. Ernst Cassirer and contemporary philosophy of science. Angelaki 10: 119–128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Friedman, Michael, and Alfred Nordmann (eds.). 2006. The Kantian legacy in nineteenth-century science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  29. Gabriel, Gottfried. 2004. Introduction: Carnap brought home. In Carnap brought home. The view from Jena, ed. S. Awodey and C. Klein, 3–23. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
  30. Gerner, Karin. 1997. Hans Reichenbach: Sein Leben und Wirken. Osnabrück: Autorenpress.Google Scholar
  31. Giere, Ronald. 1996. From wissenschaftliche philosophie to philosophy of science. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 16: 335–354.Google Scholar
  32. Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2003. Theory and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of science. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  33. Grelling, Kurt. 1910. Die philosophische Grundlagen der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung. Abhandlungen der Fries’schen Schule 3: 439–478.Google Scholar
  34. Grelling, Kurt. 1929. Realism and logic: An investigation in Russell’s metaphysics. The Monist 39: 501–520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Grelling, Kurt. 1930. Die Philosophie der Raum–Zeit-Lehre. Philosophischer Anzeiger 4: 101–128.Google Scholar
  36. Grelling, Kurt. 1933. Bemerkungen zu Dubislav, Die Definition. Erkenntnis 3: 189–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Grelling, Kurt. 1939. A logical theory of dependence. In Foundations of gestalt theory, ed. Barry Smith 1988, 217–228. München: Philosophia.Google Scholar
  38. Grelling, Kurt, and Paul Oppenheim. 1937/1938. Der Gestaltbegriff im Lichte der neuen Logik. Erkenntnis 7: 211–225. 357–359.Google Scholar
  39. Grelling, Kurt, and Paul Oppenheim. 1939. Logical analysis of ‘Gestalt’ as ‘functional Whole’. In Foundations of gestalt theory, ed. Barry Smith, 210–216. Philosophia: München.Google Scholar
  40. Haller, Rudolf, and Stadler Friedrich (eds.). 1993. Wien–Berlin–Prag. Der Aufstieg der wissenschaftlichen Philosophie. Wien: Hölder–Pichler–Tempsky.Google Scholar
  41. Hardcastle, Gary. 2006. Logical empiricism. In The philosophy of science: An encyclopedia, ed. Sahotra Sarkar and Jessica Pfeifer, 458–465. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  42. Hempel, Carl. 1951. General system theory: A new approach to unity of science. Human Biology 23: 313–322.Google Scholar
  43. Hempel, Carl. 1991. Hans Reichenbach remembered. Erkenntnis 35: 5–10.Google Scholar
  44. Hempel, Carl. 2000. Intellectual autobiography—The interview with Richard Nollan. In Science, explanation, and rationality, ed. James H. Fetzer, 3–35. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Hentschel, Klaus. 1991. Die Korrespondenz Petzold-Reichenbach. Berlin: ERS.Google Scholar
  46. Herzberg, Lily. 1928. Die philosophischen Hauptströmungen im Monistenbund. Annalen der Philosophie 7: 113–135. 177–199.Google Scholar
  47. Hilbert, David. 1900. Mathematical problems. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 8: 437–479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Hoffmann, D. 1994. Zur Geschichte der Berliner ‘Gesellschaft für empirische/wissenschaftliche Philosophie’. In Hans Reichenbach und die Berliner Gruppe, ed. Lutz Danneberg et al., 21–31. Braunschweig: Vieweg.Google Scholar
  49. Hoffmann, D. 2007. The society for empirical/scientific philosophy. In Cambridge companion to logical empiricism, ed. Alan Richardson and Thomas Uebel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  50. Howard, Don. 2000. Two left turns make a right: On the curious political career of North American philosophy of science at midcentury. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 18: 25–93.Google Scholar
  51. Iven, Mathias. 2008. Moritz Schlick. Die frühen Jahre (1881–1907). Berlin: Paregra.Google Scholar
  52. Joergensen, Joergen. 1951. The development of logical empiricism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  53. Kaila, Eino S. 1930. Der logistische neupositivismus. Eine kritische studie. Turku: Annales Universitatis Fennicae Aboensis.Google Scholar
  54. Kitcher, Philipp. 2001. Carl Hempel. In A companion to analytic philosophy, ed. A.P. Martinich and D. Sosa, 148–159. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Leitko, Hubert. 1987. Wissenschaft in Berlin. Berlin: Dietz.Google Scholar
  56. Leitko, Hubert. 1998. Wissenschaft in Berlin um 1930. In Hans Reichenbach: Philosophie im Umkreis der Physik, ed. Hans Poser and Ulrich Dirks, 139–155. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.Google Scholar
  57. Lewin, Kurt. 1920. Die verwandtschaftsbegriffe in biologie und physik und die darstellung vollständiger stammbäume. Berlin: Bornträger.Google Scholar
  58. Lewin, Kurt. 1925. Über Idee und Aufgabe der Vergleichenden Wissenschaftstheorie. Symposion 1: 61–93.Google Scholar
  59. Luchins, Abraham S., and Edith H. Luchins. 2000. Kurt Grelling: Steadfast scholar in a time of madness. Gestalt Theory 22: 228–281.Google Scholar
  60. Mayer, Verena. 1991. Die Konstruktion der Erfahrungswelt—Carnap und Husserl. Erkenntnis 35: 287–304.Google Scholar
  61. McMullin, Ernan. 1970. The history and philosophy of science: A taxonomy. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5: 12–67.Google Scholar
  62. Milkov, Nikolay. 2002. The joint philosophical program of Russell and Wittgenstein (March–November 1912) and its downfall. Contributions of the Austrian Wittgenstein Society 10: 60–62.Google Scholar
  63. Milkov, Nikolay. 2003. L. Susan Stebbing’s criticism of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 10: 351–363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Milkov, Nikolay. 2005. Russell studies in Germany today. The Bertrand Russell Society Quarterly 125(6): 35–47.Google Scholar
  65. Milkov, Nikolay. 2011. Anmerkungen des Herausgebers. In Ziele und Wege der heutigen Naturphilosophie: Fünf Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftstheorie, ed. Hans Reichenbach and N. Milkov, 147–158. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.Google Scholar
  66. Moran, Dermot (ed.). 2008. The Routledge companion to twentieth century philosophy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  67. Mulder, Henk. 1968. Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener Kreis. Journal of the History of Philosophy 6: 386–390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Neurath, Otto. 1929. The Vienna circle of the scientific conception of the world. In Empiricism and sociology, ed. Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen, 301–318. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  69. Neurath, Otto. 1930. Historische Anmerkungen. Erkenntnis 1: 311–314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Neurath, Otto. 1931. Physikalismus. Scientia 50: 297–303.Google Scholar
  71. Neurath, Otto. 1931b. Physicalism: The philosophy of the Viennese circle. The Monist 41: 618–623.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Neurath, Otto. 1932. Protocol sentences. In Logical positivism, ed. Alfred J. Ayer, 199–208. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
  73. Neurath, Otto. 1936. Die Entwicklung des Wiener Kreises und die Zukunft des logischen Empirismus. In ibid., Gesammelte philosophische Schriften, 2 vols., ed. Rudolf Haller et al., 673–702. Wien: Hölder–Pichler–Tempsky.Google Scholar
  74. Oppenheim, Paul. 1926. Die natürliche Ordnung der Wissenschaften: Grundgesetze der vergleichenden Wissenschaftslehre. Jena: Fischer.Google Scholar
  75. Padovani, Flavia. 2008. Probability and causality in the early works of Hans Reichenbach, Ph.D. dissertation, Geneva: University of Geneva.Google Scholar
  76. Peckhaus, Volker. 1990. Hilbertprogramm und kritische Philosophie: das Göttinger Modell interdisziplinärer Zusammenarbeit zwischen Mathematik und Philosophie. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.Google Scholar
  77. Peckhaus, Volker. 1994. Von Nelson zu Reichenbach: Kurt Grelling in Göttingen und Berlin. In Hans Reichenbach und die Berliner Gruppe, ed. Lutz Danneberg et al., 53–86. Braunschweig: Vieweg.Google Scholar
  78. Peckhaus, Volker. 2003. The pragmatism of Hilbert’s programme. Synthese 137: 141–156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. Petzäll, Åke. 1931. Logistischer Positivismus: Versuch einer Darstellung und Würdigung der philosophischen Grundanschauungen des sog. Wiener Kreises der wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung. Göteborgs högskolas årsskrift 37: 3. 36 pages.Google Scholar
  80. Poser, Hans, and Ulrich Dirks (eds.). 1998. Hans Reichenbach: Philosophie im Umkreis der Physik. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.Google Scholar
  81. Putnam, Hilary. 1991. Reichenbach’s Metaphysical picture. Erkenntnis 35: 61–75.Google Scholar
  82. Reichenbach, Hans. 1914. Zum Lietzschen Vortragsabend. Göttinger Akademische Wochenschau 10:5 (12.06.), 38.Google Scholar
  83. Reichenbach, Hans. 1920. The theory of relativity and a priori knowledge. Trans. Maria Reichenbach. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  84. Reichenbach, Hans. 1928a. Philosophie der Raum–Zeit Lehre. Berlin: de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  85. Reichenbach, Hans. 1928b. [Russell:] An early appreciation. In Bertrand Russell: Philosopher of the century, ed. Ralph Schoenman, 129–133. London: Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
  86. Reichenbach, Hans. 1929. Bertrand Russell. In Obelisk Almanach, 82–92. Berlin and Munich: Drei-Masken Verlag.Google Scholar
  87. Reichenbach, Hans. 1930. Zur Einführung. Erkenntnis 1: 1–3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  88. Reichenbach, Hans. 1931a. Zum Anschaulichkeitsproblem der Geometrie. Erkenntnis 2: 61–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  89. Reichenbach, Hans. 1931b. Ziele und Wege der heutigen Naturphilosophie. Leipzig: Felix Meiner.Google Scholar
  90. Reichenbach, Hans. 1932. Wahrscheinlichkeitslogik. Sonderausgabe der Sitzungsberichte der Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften 29: 471–490.Google Scholar
  91. Reichenbach, Hans. 1936a. Logical empiricism in Germany and the present state of its problems. The Journal of Philosophy 33: 141–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  92. Reichenbach, Hans. 1936b. Ansprache bei der Begrüßung der Pariser Kongresses. In Actes de congrès international de philosophie scientifique. Paris 1035, Tome I: Philosophie scientifique et empirisme logique, 16–18. Paris: Hermann.Google Scholar
  93. Reichenbach, Hans. 1938. Experience and prediction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  94. Reichenbach, Hans. 1947. Elements of symbolic logic. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
  95. Reichenbach, Hans. 1951. The rise of scientific philosophy. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  96. Reichenbach, Hans. 1953. Der Aufstieg der wissenschaftlichen Philosophie. Trans. Maria Reichenbach. Berlin: Herbig.Google Scholar
  97. Reichenbach, Hans. 2006. Defending Einstein: Hans Reichenbach’s writings on space, time, and motion, ed. Steven Gimbel and Anke Walz. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  98. Rescher, Nicholas. 1966. The logic of commands. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  99. Rescher, Nicholas. 1997. H2O: Hempel–Helmer–Oppenheim: An episode in the history of scientific philosophy in the 20th century. Philosophy of Science 64: 334–360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  100. Rescher, Nicholas. 2005. The Berlin school of logical empiricism and its legacy. In Studies in 20th century philosophy, ed. Nicholas Rescher, 119–148. Ontos: Frankfurt.Google Scholar
  101. Richardson, Alan, and Thomas Uebel. 2007. Cambridge companion to logical empiricism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  102. Salmon, Wesley. 1999. The spirit of logical empiricism: Carl G. Hempel’s role in twentieth-century philosophy of science. Philosophy of Science 66: 333–350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  103. Salmon, Wesley. 2001. Logical empiricism. In A companion to the philosophy of science, ed. W.H. Newton-Smith, 233–251. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  104. Sarkar, Sahotra, and Pfeifer Jessica. 2006. The philosophy of science: An introduction. In The philosophy of science: An encyclopedia, ed. Sahotra Sarkar and Pfeifer Jessica, xi–xxvi. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  105. Sarkar, Sahotra, and Jessica Pfeifer (eds.). 2006. The philosophy of science: An encyclopedia. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  106. Schernus, Wilhelm. 1994. Alexander herzberg: Psychologie, medizin und wissenschaftliche philosophie. In Hans Reichenbach und die Berliner Gruppe, ed. Lutz Danneberg et al., 33–51. Braunschweig: Vieweg.Google Scholar
  107. Schlick, Moritz. 1918. Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  108. Schlick, Moritz. 1930. Die Wende der Philosophie. Erkenntnis 1: 4–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  109. Simons, Peter. 1997. Review of Kush, Psychologism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48: 439–443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  110. Smith, Barry (ed.). 1988. Foundations of Gestalt theory. München: Philosophia.Google Scholar
  111. Smith, Barry. 1997. The Neurath–Haller thesis: Austria and the rise of scientific philosophy. In Austrian philosophy past and present, ed. Keith Lehrer and Johann C. Marek, 1–20. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  112. Stadler, Friedrich. 1991. Aspects of the social background and position of the Vienna circle at the University of Vienna. In Rediscovering the forgotten Vienna circle, ed. Thomas Uebel, 51–77. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  113. Stadler, Friedrich. 1997. Studien zum Wiener Kreis. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  114. Stebbing, Susan. 1933. Logical positivism and analysis. Proceedings of the British Academy 19: 53–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  115. Stölzner, Michael. 2001. Die Kausalitätsdebatte in den Naturwissenschaften. Zu einem Milieuproblem in Formans These. In Wissenschaft: Transformationen im Verhältnis von Wissenschaft und Alltag, ed. H. Franz, 85–128. Bielefeld: Institut für Wissenschafts- und Technikforschung.Google Scholar
  116. Stölzner, Michael. 2002. How metaphysical is ‘deepening the foundations’?—hahn and frank on Hilbert’s axiomatic method. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 9: 245–262.Google Scholar
  117. Stumpf, Carl. 1892. Über den Begriff der mathematischen Wahrscheinlichkeit. Sitzungsberichte der philosophisch-philologischen und historischen Classe der Königlich Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften 20: 37–120.Google Scholar
  118. Thiel, Christian. 1993. Carnap und die wissenschaftliche Philosophie auf der Erlanger Tagung 1923. In Wien–Berlin–Prag Der Aufstieg der wissenschaftlichen Philosophie, ed. Rudolf Haller and Stadler Friedrich, 175–188. Wien: Hölder–Pichler–Tempsky.Google Scholar
  119. van Fraassen, Bas. 2002. The empirical stance. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  120. von Aster, Ernst. 1913. Prinzipien der Erkenntnislehre. München: Quelle & Meyer.Google Scholar
  121. Wittmann, Simone. 1998. Das Frühwerk Kurt Lewins. Frankfurt: Peter Lang.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht. 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of PaderbornPaderbornGermany

Personalised recommendations