Advertisement

The Relationship Between Physics and Mathematics in the XIXth Century: The Disregarded Birth of a Foundational Pluralism

  • Antonino DragoEmail author
Chapter
Part of the History of Mechanism and Machine Science book series (HMMS, volume 16)

Abstract

In my previous historical works I suggested that four scientific choices constitute the foundations of Physics. By means of these choices I will interpret the history of the relationship between Mathematics and Theoretical Physics in the nineteenth century. A particular pair of choices shaped the Newtonian relationship between Mathematics and Physics, which was so efficient in producing new theoretical results that it became a paradigm. In the nineteenth century new formulations of mechanics were made according to different basic choices, so that in theoretical Physics three other pairs of choices began to co-exist with the Newtonian relationship. Very few scientists of that time recognised this pluralism; instead, the community of physicists interpreted the new theories as either mere variations of the dominant one, or loose scientific attitudes to be put aside in order to follow the theoretical progress of the dominant paradigm. But just after the mid-century the pluralism of the relationships between Physics and Mathematics came to the fore again, this time the previous alternative choices shaped new physical theories – thermodynamics, electromagnetism – concerning entirely new fields of phenomena. But this novelty was interpreted as simply a conflict – possibly, a contradiction – between the new basic notions and the old ones; in particular, at the end of the nineteenth century there was a great debate about the theoretical role played by the new notion of energy in contrast with the old notion of force. The persistent lack of awareness of the pluralism of relationships is the reason for both the inconclusiveness of this debate and the dramatic crisis occurring in theoretical Physics from the year 1900. This time the crisis was caused above all by two experimental data (both the quantum and the light velocity of light c as the highest possible velocity) which are incompatible with the Newtonian relationship between Mathematics and Physics. Correspondingly, two “revolutionary” theories emerged, again according to the alternative choices to those of this paradigm; both theories required a new relationship with Mathematics, including respectively discrete mathematics and groups.

Keywords

Theoretical Physic Nineteenth Century Physical Theory Basic Notion Newtonian Mechanic 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Agassi J (1969) Unity and diversity in science. In: Cohen RS, Wartofsky MW (eds) Boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol 4. Reidel, Boston, pp 463–522Google Scholar
  2. Alexander HG (ed) (1956) Leibniz–Clarke correspondence. The Manchester University Press, ManchesterzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  3. Barrow-Green J (1997) Poincaré and the three body problem. The American Mathematical Society, ProvidencezbMATHGoogle Scholar
  4. Bazhanov VA, Drago A (1998) Towards a more adequate appraisal of Lobachevskii’s scholarly work. Atti della Fondazione Giorgio Ronchi 54:125–139Google Scholar
  5. Bazhanov VA, Drago A (2010) A logical analysis of Lobachevsky’s geometrical theory. Atti della Fondazione Giorgio Ronchi 64:453–481Google Scholar
  6. Ben-David J (1964) The scientist’s role in society. The Chicago University Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  7. Birembaut A (1975) Sadi Carnot et son temps de 1817 à 1832. In: Taton 1976, pp 53–80Google Scholar
  8. Bishop E (1967) Foundations of constructive mathematics. Mc Graw-Hill, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  9. Boltzmann L ([1896] 1974) Theoretical physics and philosophical problems. Reidel, DordrechtCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Bridgman P (1943) The nature of thermodynamics. The Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  11. Brunschvicg L (1922) L’Experience Humaine et la Causalité Physique. Alcan, ParisGoogle Scholar
  12. Burtt EA (1924) The metaphysical foundations of modern science. Routledge and Kegan, LondonGoogle Scholar
  13. Cardwell DSL (1971) From Watt to Clausius: the rise of thermodynamics in the early industrial age. Heinemann, LondonGoogle Scholar
  14. Carnot L (1813) Réflexions sur la métaphysique du calcul infinitésimal. Courcier, ParisGoogle Scholar
  15. Carnot L (1803) Principes fondamentaux de l'équilibre et du mouvement. Deterville, ParisGoogle Scholar
  16. Carnot L (1786) Essai sur les machines en général. Defay, Dijon (It. tr. and critical edition by Drago A and Manno SD, CUEN, Naples, 1994)Google Scholar
  17. Carnot S (1824) Réflexions sur la puissance motrice du feu. Bachelier, Paris (critical edition by Fox R, Vrin, Paris, 1978)Google Scholar
  18. Comte A (1830–1842) Cours de Philosophie Positive. Rouen Frères, ParisGoogle Scholar
  19. D’Alembert J et al (1751–1772) Elémens. In: Encyclopédie Française. Briasson–David–Le Bréton–Durand, Paris, p 17Google Scholar
  20. Da Costa N, Doria FA (1991) Undecidability and incompleteness in classical mechanics. International Journal of theoretical Physics 30:1041–1073MathSciNetADSzbMATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. van Dalen D, Troelstra A (1988) Constructivism in mathematics. North-Holland, AmsterdamGoogle Scholar
  22. Drago A (2010) La teoria delle relatività di Einstein del 1905 esaminata secondo il modello di organizzazione basata su un problema. In: Giannetto E, Giannini G, Toscano M (eds) Relatività, Quanti, Chaos e altre rivoluzioni della Fisica. Proceedings of XXVII SISFA Congress. Guaraldi, Rimini, pp 215–224Google Scholar
  23. Drago A (2009) The Lagrange’s arguing in Méchanique Analytique. In: Giorgilli A, Sacchi Landriani G (eds) Sfogliando la Méchanique Analytique. Giornata di Studio su Louis Lagrange. LED, Milano, pp 193–214Google Scholar
  24. Drago A (2005) A.N. Kolmogoroff and the relevance of the double negation law in science. In: Sica G (ed) Essays on the foundations of mathematics and logic. Polimetrica, Milano, pp 57–81Google Scholar
  25. Drago A (2004a) A new appraisal of old formulations of mechanics. The American Journal of Physics 72:407–9ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Drago A (2004b) Lo schema paradigmatico della didattica della Fisica: la ricerca di un'unità tra quattro teorie. Giornale di Fisica 45:173–191Google Scholar
  27. Drago A (2003a) The introduction of actual infinity in modern science: mathematics and physics in both Cavalieri and Torricelli. Ganita Bharati Bull Soc Math India 25:79–98MathSciNetzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  28. Drago A (2003b) Volta and the strange history of electromagnetism. In: Giannetto EA (ed) Volta and the history of electricity. Hoepli, Milano, pp 97–111Google Scholar
  29. Drago A (2002) The introduction to non-Euclidean geometries by Bolyai through an arguing of non-classical logic. In: International Conference Bolyai 2002, Hungarian Academy of Science, BudapestGoogle Scholar
  30. Drago A (1996) Mathematics and alternative theoretical physics: the method for linking them together. Epistemologia 19:33–50Google Scholar
  31. Drago A (1993) The principle of virtual works as a source of two traditions in 18th century mechanics. History of physics in Europe in 19th and 20th centuries. SIF, Bologna, pp 69–80Google Scholar
  32. Drago A (1991) Le due opzioni. La Meridiana, MolfettaGoogle Scholar
  33. Drago A (1990) Le lien entre mathématique et physique dans la mécanique de Lazare Carnot. In: Charnay JP (ed) Lazare Carnot ou le savant–citoyen. P. Université Paris–Sorbonne, Paris, pp501–515Google Scholar
  34. Drago A (1986) Relevance of constructive mathematics to theoretical physics. In: Agazzi E et al (eds) Logica e Filosofia della Scienza, oggi, vol 2. CLUEB, Bologna, pp 267–272Google Scholar
  35. Drago A, Pisano R (2000) Interpretazione e ricostruzione delle Réflexions di Sadi Carnot mediante la logica non classica. Giornale di Fisica 41:195–215 (Engl. tr. in: Atti della Fondazione Giorgio Ronchi (2004) 59:615–644)Google Scholar
  36. Drago A, Oliva R (1999) Atomism and the reasoning by non-classical logic. Hyle 5:43–55Google Scholar
  37. Drago A, Romano L (1995) La polemica delle corde vibranti vista alla luce della matematica costruttiva. In: Rossi A (ed) Proceedings of XIII SISFA congress. Conte, Lecce, pp 253–258Google Scholar
  38. Drago A, Saiello P (1995) Newtonian mechanics and the kinetic theory of gas. In: Kovacs L (ed) History of science in teaching physics. Studia Physica Savariensia, Szombathély, pp 113–118Google Scholar
  39. Dugas R (1963) La thérmodynamique au sens de Boltzmann. Griffon, NeuchateGoogle Scholar
  40. Dugas R (1950) Histoire de la Mécanique. Griffon, NeuchâtelzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  41. Duhem P (1906) La théorie physique, son objet et sa structure. Chevalier et Rivière, ParisGoogle Scholar
  42. Duhem P (1903) L’évolution de la Mécanique. Hermann, ParisGoogle Scholar
  43. Einstein A (1934) Mein Weltbild. Querido, Amsterdam (Engl. tr. Ideas and Opinions, Crown, New York, 1954)Google Scholar
  44. Feyerabend PK (1969) Against Method. Verso, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  45. Fourier C (1822) Théorie analytique de la chaleur. Didot, ParisGoogle Scholar
  46. Galileo G (1638) Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche, intorno a due nuove scienze. Elsevier, LeidaGoogle Scholar
  47. Garber E (1998) The language of physics: the calculus and the development of theoretical physics in Europe, 1759–1914. Birkhaüser, BerlinGoogle Scholar
  48. Gillispie CC (1971) Lazare Carnot savant. Princeton University Press, PrincetonzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  49. Grattan-Guinness I (1990) Convolutions in French mathematics 1800–1840. Birkhaüser, BerlinzbMATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Guicciardini N (1999) Isaac Newton on mathematical certainty and method. The Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  51. Hankins TL (1970) Jean d’Alembert. Science and the enlightenment. The Clarendon Press, OxfordzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  52. Harman PM (1998) The natural philosophy of James Clerk Maxwell. The Cambridge University Press, CambridgezbMATHGoogle Scholar
  53. Hellmann G (1993) Constructive mathematics and quantum mechanics. Unbounded operators and spectral theorem. Journal of Philosophical Logic 22:221–248MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Helmholtz H (1884) Principien der Statik monocyclischer Systeme. Journal fuer die reine und angewandte Mathematik 97:111–140, 317–336Google Scholar
  55. Jouguet E (1908) Lectures de Mécanique. Gauthier–Villars, PariszbMATHGoogle Scholar
  56. Kogbetlianz FG (1968) Fundamentals of mathematics from an advanced point of view. Gordon and Breach, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  57. Koyré A (1959) From the closed world to the infinite universe. The Johns Hopkins University Press, BaltimoreGoogle Scholar
  58. Kuhn TS (1969) The structure of the scientific revolutions. The Chicago University Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  59. Lagrange JL (1797) Théorie des Fonctions Analytiques. Imprimerie de la Republique, ParisGoogle Scholar
  60. Lagrange JL (1788) Mécanique Analytique. Lesaint, Paris (Engl. tr. Kluwer, Dodrecht, 1997)Google Scholar
  61. Lobachevsky NI (1835–1838) New principles of geometry (in Russian), Kazan (Engl. tr.: by Halsted GB, Geometrical researches on the theory of parallels, Neomonic ser, no, 4, Austin, 1892; repr. Chicago, London, 1942; and New principles of geometry with complete theory of parallels, Neomonic ser. no. 5 Austin, 1897)Google Scholar
  62. Lobachevsky NI (1833) Algebra or calculus of finites (in Russian), KazanGoogle Scholar
  63. Mach E ([1896] 1986) Principles of theory of heat. Reidel, BostonCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Mach E (1905) Erkenntnis und Irrtum. Barth, Leipzig (Engl. tr. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1975)Google Scholar
  65. Markov AA (1962) On constructive mathematics. Trudy Math Inst Steklov 67:8–14 (Engl. tr. Am Math Soc Translations (1971) 98:1–9)Google Scholar
  66. Mastermann M (1970) The nature of a paradigm. In: Lakatos I, Musgrave A (eds) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. The Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 59–89Google Scholar
  67. Ostwald W (1895) La déroute de l’atomisme contemporaine. Revue Générale des Sciences 21/15 November:953Google Scholar
  68. Planck M (1893) Vorlesungen der Thermodynamik (Fr. tr.: Leçons de Thérmodynamique, Hermann, Paris, 1913, 2 edn)Google Scholar
  69. Poincaré H (1905) La valeur de la Science. Hermann, ParisGoogle Scholar
  70. Poincaré H (1903) La science et l'hypothèse. Flammarion, ParisGoogle Scholar
  71. Poinsot L (1975) La théorie de l’équilibre et du mouvement des systèmes. Vrin, ParisGoogle Scholar
  72. Rankine WJM (1855) Heat, theory of the mechanical action of, or thermodynamics. In: Nichol JP (ed) A cyclopaedia of the physical sciences, 1st edn. Griffin, London, pp 338–354Google Scholar
  73. Robelin LP (1832) Notice sur Sadi. Rev Encyclopédique 55:528–530Google Scholar
  74. Scott WL (1970) The conflict between atomism and conservation laws, 1644–1860. Elsevier, LondonGoogle Scholar
  75. Shapiro A (1984) Experiment and mathematics in Newton’s theory of color. Physics Today 37:34–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  76. Taton A (ed) (1976) Sadi Carnot et l’essor de la thermodynamique, Table Ronde du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique. École Polytechnique, 11–13 Juin 1974. Éditions du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, ParisGoogle Scholar
  77. Taton A (1964) La Génie du XIXe siècle. In: Taton A (ed) Histoire Générale des Sciences, vol III, chap. I. P.U.F., ParisGoogle Scholar
  78. Thackray A (1970) Atoms and powers. An essay on Newtonian matter and the development of chemistry. The Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  79. Truesdell CC (1960) A program toward rediscovering the rational mechanics of the age of reason. Archive for the History of Exact Sciences 1:3–36MathSciNetzbMATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  80. Venel F (1754) Chemie. In: Diderot D, D’Alembert J (eds) Encyclopédie Française. ParisGoogle Scholar
  81. Vuchinich A (1963) Science and Russian culture: a history to 1860. The Stanford University Press, StanfordGoogle Scholar
  82. Weyl H ([1926] 1929) Group theory and quantum mechanics. Dover, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  83. Zagoskin NP (1906) History of Kazan University, Kazan University Press, Kazan, Parts 1–4Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of PisaPisaItaly

Personalised recommendations