Advertisement

Argumentation with (Bounded) Rational Agents

Chapter
  • 1.9k Downloads
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 362)

Abstract

A major reason for our communication is to influence our conversational partners. This is so both if our preferences are aligned, and when they are not. In the latter case, our communicative acts are meant to manipulate our partners. We all know that attempts to manipulate are nothing out of the ordinary. Unfortunately, the standard theory of rational communicative behavior predicts that any such attempt will be seen through and is thus useless. The main aim of this chapter is to investigate which assumptions of the standard theory we have to give up to account for our communicative behavior, when preferences between partners are not aligned.

Keywords

Decision Maker Nash Equilibrium Common Knowledge Signaling Game Sequential Equilibrium 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Anscombre, J. C., & Ducrot, O. (1983). L’Argumentation dans la Langue. Brussels: Mardaga.Google Scholar
  2. Axelrod, R., & Hamilton, W. (1981). The evolution of cooperation. Science, 411, 1390–1396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Crawford, V. (2003). Lying for strategic advantage: rational and boundedly rational misrepresentations of intentions. American Economic Review, 93, 133–149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Crawford, V., & Sobel, J. (1982). Strategic information transmission. Econometrica, 50, 1431–1451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. de Jaegher, K. (2003). Error-proneness as a handicap signal. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 224, 139–152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Ducrot, O. (1973). La preuve et le dire. Paris: Mame.Google Scholar
  7. Farrell, J. (1988). Communication, coordination and Nash equilibrium. Economic Letters, 27, 209–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Farrell, J. (1993). Meaning and credibility in cheap-talk games. Games and Economic Behavior, 5, 514–531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Feinberg, Y. (2008). Meaningful talk. In K. Apt & R. van Rooij (Eds.), New perspectives on games and interaction (pp. 105–120). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Franke, M. (2009). Signal to act. Game theory in pragmatics. PhD thesis, University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  11. Glazer, J., & Rubinstein, A. (2008). A study in the pragmatics of persuasion: A game theoretical approach. In K. Apt & R. van Rooij (Eds.), New perspectives on games and interaction (pp. 121–140). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Grafen, A. (1990). Biological signals as handicaps. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 144, 517–546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Grice, H. P. (1967). Logic and conversation. Typescript from the William James Lectures, Harvard University (Published in Grice, P. (1989), Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 22–40).Google Scholar
  14. Horn, L. (1989). A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  15. Hurd, P. (1995). Communication in discrete action-response games. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 174, 217–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Keynes, J. M. (1936). The general theory of employment, interest and money. New York: Harcourt Brace and Co.Google Scholar
  17. Lewis, D. (1969). Convention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Matthews, S., Okuno-Fujiwara, M., & Postlewaite, A. (1991). Refining cheaptalk equilibra. Journal of Economic Theory, 55, 247–273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Merin, A. (1999), Die Relevanz der Relevanz: Fallstudie zur formalen Semantik der englishen Konjunktion ‘but’ (Arbeitspapiere SFB 340, nr. 142), Stuttgart: Stuttgart University.Google Scholar
  20. Milgrom, P., & Roberts, J. (1986). Relying on the information of interested parties. Journal of Economics, 17, 18–32.Google Scholar
  21. Moulin, H. (1986). Game theory for the social sciences (2nd ed.). New York: NYU Press.Google Scholar
  22. Nagel, R. (1995). Unraveling in guessing games: An experimental study. American Economic Review, 85, 1313–1326.Google Scholar
  23. Rabin, M. (1990). Communication between rational agents. Journal of Economic-Theory, 51, 144–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Spence, M. (1973). Job market signalling. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 87, 355–374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Stalnaker, R. (2006). Saying and meaning, cheap talk and credibility. In A. Benz, G. Jäger, & R. van Rooij (Eds.), Game theory and pragmatics. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan.Google Scholar
  26. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choices. Science, 211, 453–458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. van Rooij, R. (2004). Cooperative versus argumentative communication. Philosophia Scientia, 2, 195–205.Google Scholar
  29. Zahavi, A. (1975). Mate selection – A selection for a handicap. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 53, 205–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute for Logic, Language and ComputationUniversity of AmsterdamAmsterdamThe Netherlands
  2. 2.Utrecht School of EconomicsUtrecht UniversityUtrechtThe Netherlands

Personalised recommendations