Advertisement

Why Are We Convinced by the Ad Hominem Argument?: Bayesian Source Reliability and Pragma-Dialectical Discussion Rules

Chapter
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 362)

Abstract

There has been little empirical research on the ad hominem argument. What there is has been carried in the tradition of the pragma-dialectic approach by investigating the reasonableness of the ad hominem argument which is determined by the discussion stage in which it is deployed (van Eemeren et al., Fallacies and judgements of reasonableness. Springer, Dordrecht, 2009). The experiment reported in this chapter investigates how convincing people find the ad hominem argument from the emerging Bayesian epistemic perspective on argumentation (Hahn and Oaksford, Psychol Rev 114:704–732, 2007), in which people are argued to be sensitive to the reliability of the source of an argument. The experiment varied source reliability, initial degree of belief in the conclusion, and whether the ad hominem was a pro or a con argument. A Bayesian account of the effect of reliability on posterior degree of beliefs after hearing the argument provided excellent fits to the data. Moreover, the results were not consistent with the pragma-dialectic approach, as no differences were observed between conditions where a discussion rule was violated and a control condition where it was not violated. However, further experimentation is required to fully establish this conclusion.

Keywords

Belief Condition Argument Type Initial Claim Argument Strength Confrontation Stage 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Anderson, J. R. (1990). The adaptive character of thought. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  2. Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Brinton, A. (1995). The ad hominem. In H. V. Nansen & R. C. Pinto (Eds.), Fallacies: Classical background and contemporary developments (pp. 213–222). University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Cherniak, C. (1986). Minimal rationality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Coady, C. A. J. (1992). Testimony: A philosophical study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Davidson, D. (1974). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Inquiries into truth and interpretation (pp. 183–198). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Eagly, A. H., & Chaiken, S. (1993). The psychology of attitudes. Belmont: Thompson Wadsworth.Google Scholar
  8. Gillies, D. (2000). Philosophical theories of probability. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  9. Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2006). A Bayesian approach to informal argument fallacies. Synthese, 152, 207–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2007). The rationality of informal argumentation: A Bayesian approach to reasoning fallacies. Psychological Review, 114, 704–732.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Hahn, U., Harris, A. J. L., & Corner, A. (2009). Argument content and argument source: An exploration. Informal Logic, 29, 337–367.Google Scholar
  12. Harris, A.J.L., & Hahn, U. (2009). Bayesian rationality in evaluating multiple testimonies: Incorporating the role of coherence. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 35, 1366–1373.Google Scholar
  13. Ikuenobe, P. (2004). On the theoretical unification and nature of the fallacies. Argumentation, 18, 189–211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Johnson, B. T., Maio, G. R., & Smith-McLallen, A. (2005). Communication and attitude change: Causes, processes, and effects. In D. Albarracin, B. T. Johnson, & M. P. Zanna (Eds.), The handbook of attitudes and attitude change: Basic principles (pp. 617–669). Mahwah: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  15. Olsson, E. J. (2005). Against coherence: Truth, probability and justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Perelman, C., & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. (1969). The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
  17. Shogenji, T. (1999). Is coherence truth-conducive? Analysis, 59, 338–345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2004). A systematic theory of argumentation. The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  19. van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Snoeck Henkemans, F. (1996). Fundamentals of argumentation theory. Mahwah: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  20. van Eemeren, F. H., Garssen, B., & Meuffels, B. (2009). Fallacies and judgements of reasonableness. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Voss, J. F., & Van Dyke, J. A. (2001). Argumentation in psychology: Background comments. Discourse Processes, 32, 89–111.Google Scholar
  22. Walton, D. N. (1990). What is reasoning? What is argument? Journal of Philosophy, 87, 399–419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Walton, D. N. (2000). Case study of the use of a circumstantial ad hominem in political argumentation. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 33, 101–115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Walton, D. N. (2009). Ad hominem arguments. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.Google Scholar
  25. Wilson, N. L. (1959). Substance without substrata. The Review of Metaphysics, 12, 521–539.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Psychological Science, Birkbeck CollegeUniversity of LondonLondonUK
  2. 2.School of PsychologyCardiff UniversityCardiffUK

Personalised recommendations