Skip to main content

Why Are We Convinced by the Ad Hominem Argument?: Bayesian Source Reliability and Pragma-Dialectical Discussion Rules

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Bayesian Argumentation

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 362))

Abstract

There has been little empirical research on the ad hominem argument. What there is has been carried in the tradition of the pragma-dialectic approach by investigating the reasonableness of the ad hominem argument which is determined by the discussion stage in which it is deployed (van Eemeren et al., Fallacies and judgements of reasonableness. Springer, Dordrecht, 2009). The experiment reported in this chapter investigates how convincing people find the ad hominem argument from the emerging Bayesian epistemic perspective on argumentation (Hahn and Oaksford, Psychol Rev 114:704–732, 2007), in which people are argued to be sensitive to the reliability of the source of an argument. The experiment varied source reliability, initial degree of belief in the conclusion, and whether the ad hominem was a pro or a con argument. A Bayesian account of the effect of reliability on posterior degree of beliefs after hearing the argument provided excellent fits to the data. Moreover, the results were not consistent with the pragma-dialectic approach, as no differences were observed between conditions where a discussion rule was violated and a control condition where it was not violated. However, further experimentation is required to fully establish this conclusion.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In this example and the next, a deterministic relationship is assumed between the conclusion and the argument, such that the conclusion guarantees the argument with probability 1 if true and probability zero if false.

References

  • Anderson, J. R. (1990). The adaptive character of thought. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brinton, A. (1995). The ad hominem. In H. V. Nansen & R. C. Pinto (Eds.), Fallacies: Classical background and contemporary developments (pp. 213–222). University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cherniak, C. (1986). Minimal rationality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coady, C. A. J. (1992). Testimony: A philosophical study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1974). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Inquiries into truth and interpretation (pp. 183–198). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eagly, A. H., & Chaiken, S. (1993). The psychology of attitudes. Belmont: Thompson Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (2000). Philosophical theories of probability. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2006). A Bayesian approach to informal argument fallacies. Synthese, 152, 207–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2007). The rationality of informal argumentation: A Bayesian approach to reasoning fallacies. Psychological Review, 114, 704–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., Harris, A. J. L., & Corner, A. (2009). Argument content and argument source: An exploration. Informal Logic, 29, 337–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, A.J.L., & Hahn, U. (2009). Bayesian rationality in evaluating multiple testimonies: Incorporating the role of coherence. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 35, 1366–1373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ikuenobe, P. (2004). On the theoretical unification and nature of the fallacies. Argumentation, 18, 189–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, B. T., Maio, G. R., & Smith-McLallen, A. (2005). Communication and attitude change: Causes, processes, and effects. In D. Albarracin, B. T. Johnson, & M. P. Zanna (Eds.), The handbook of attitudes and attitude change: Basic principles (pp. 617–669). Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E. J. (2005). Against coherence: Truth, probability and justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C., & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. (1969). The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shogenji, T. (1999). Is coherence truth-conducive? Analysis, 59, 338–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2004). A systematic theory of argumentation. The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Snoeck Henkemans, F. (1996). Fundamentals of argumentation theory. Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Garssen, B., & Meuffels, B. (2009). Fallacies and judgements of reasonableness. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Voss, J. F., & Van Dyke, J. A. (2001). Argumentation in psychology: Background comments. Discourse Processes, 32, 89–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1990). What is reasoning? What is argument? Journal of Philosophy, 87, 399–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (2000). Case study of the use of a circumstantial ad hominem in political argumentation. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 33, 101–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (2009). Ad hominem arguments. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, N. L. (1959). Substance without substrata. The Review of Metaphysics, 12, 521–539.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mike Oaksford .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix: Experimental Materials

Appendix: Experimental Materials

1.1 Abusive

  • (A) (Even) After listening to him, I think it’s possible (strongly believe) that Ford cars simply (don’t) drive better.

  • (B) Actually, you should be certain that they don’t drive any better.

  • (A) Why do you think that?

  • (B) Because how would he know? He doesn’t know the first thing about cars.

1.2 Circumstantial

  • (B) I think it’s possible (highly likely) that her recommendation to use Stelcom Ltd is (not) a good one; (even though) she says that they are the only contractor in the Netherlands that can handle such an enormous job.

  • (B) Well, you should be absolutely certain that her recommendation isn’t a good one.

  • (A) Why do you say that?

  • (B) How can we really believe her? Surely, it’s no coincidence that the company is owned by her father-in-law.

1.3 Tu Quoque

  • (A) It’s possible (highly likely) he was (wasn’t) right to criticise the way in which they processed the data statistically.

  • (B) Well, you should be convinced that he wasn’t right to criticise them.

  • (A) What do you mean?

  • (B) Because he said they should have expressed the figures as percentages. But how can he say that when his own statistics are not up to the mark.

1.4 Control

  • (A) I think it’s possible (strongly believe) that her scientific integrity is (isn’t) impeccable. She says her research has always been honest and sound.

  • (B) Well, you should be convinced that her integrity isn’t impeccable.

  • (A) Why do you say that?

  • (B) Well, how can you really believe her? She has already been caught twice tampering with her research results.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Oaksford, M., Hahn, U. (2013). Why Are We Convinced by the Ad Hominem Argument?: Bayesian Source Reliability and Pragma-Dialectical Discussion Rules. In: Zenker, F. (eds) Bayesian Argumentation. Synthese Library, vol 362. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5357-0_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics