Skip to main content

Testimony and Argument: A Bayesian Perspective

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Bayesian Argumentation

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 362))

Abstract

Philosophers have become increasingly interested in testimony (e.g. Coady, Testimony: A philosophical study. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1992; Kusch & Lipton, Stud Hist Philos Sci 33:209–217). In the context of argumentation and persuasion, the distinction between the content of a message and its source is a natural and important one. The distinction has consequently attracted considerable attention within psychological research. There has also been a range of normative attempts to deal with the question of how source and message characteristics should combine to give rise to an overall evaluation of evidential strength (e.g. Walton, Witness testimony evidence: Argumentation, artificial intelligence, and law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2008). This chapter treats this issue from the perspective of the Bayesian approach to argument (Hahn & Oaksford, Psychol Rev 114:704–732, 2007a; Hahn et al., Informal Log 29:337–367, 2009) and summarises empirical evidence on key intuitions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In fact, because it is the case both that A,B |-- A&B and that A&B |-- A as well as A&B |--B, the MIN rule (Eq. 1) can only be satisfied consistently in the case of the conjunction by assuming that Plausibility(A&B) = MIN Plausibility(A), Plausibility(B) (see also Walton 1992, pp. 36, 37; Rescher 1976, p. 16, Theorem 3).

  2. 2.

    The lottery paradox concerns the tension between the fact that it seems rational to believe that each individual ticket of a lottery is likely to lose, yet the conjunction of all of these individual beliefs is false. The preface paradox involves imagining the statements of a book each of which engenders great confidence but which are likely to include an error. Much has been said about these ‘paradoxes’ of rational acceptance. On the present view, what they illustrate is the simple point made here, namely, that one would not want to evaluate conjuncts without consideration of the relationships between statements. The ‘paradoxes’ are consequences of the way seemingly ‘objective’ probabilities concerning lottery tickets or coin flips combine. Hence, any theory of rational belief that wishes to reflect basic mathematical facts about processes of sampling with (coin tosses) or without replacement (lotteries) must respect these combination properties also.

  3. 3.

    If P(A) + P(B) is greater than 1, then P(A & B) will be at a minimum when P(A & ¬B) = 1P(B).

    Therefore, P(A & B) will be at a minimum when it equals P(A)(1P(B)), that is, P(A) + P(B )1. Note also that this means it is the sum of the two probabilities that determines the lower bound on the probability of the conjunct, not the minimum of these two probabilities.

  4. 4.

    The term ‘evidence’ is used here and in the following to refer to anything that might be considered in support of a hypothesis (i.e., a ‘reason’). Hence, the term is used more broadly here than in many discussions of testimony; specifically, something can be evidence for a hypothesis even if that hypothesis turns out to be false, that is, what is often referred to as ‘potential evidence’ (Achinstein 1987); likewise, the term ‘evidence’ as used here includes information which, objectively, turns out not to be diagnostic (cf. Graham 1997); information which is subjectively non-diagnostic is likewise referred to as evidence in this chapter and simply constitutes evidence that is maximally weak.

  5. 5.

    This simple case is also familiar from, for example, Bayesian treatments of the Humean position on miracles; see, e.g. Tucker (2005) and references therein.

  6. 6.

    While there have been very detailed examinations of the impact of source credibility within social psychology (e.g. Birnbaum et al. 1976; Birnbaum and Stegner 1979; Birnbaum and Mellers 1983), these studies have not simultaneously manipulated the diagnosticity of the message content. Finally, both message content and source characteristics have been manipulated simultaneously in a large number of social psychological studies of persuasion (e.g. Chaiken 1980; Petty et al. 1981; Petty and Cacioppo 1984, of many). However, differences in theoretical focus have meant that the data from these studies have typically not been analysed in such a way as to address the question of how these two factors combine because as indicated in the ‘Introduction’, persuasion researchers have typically considered source and content as alternatives that are indicative of two separate cognitive routes to persuasion and have consequently used these factors almost exclusively as a means by which to isolate these different routes. Hence, a comprehensive review by Pornpitakpan (2004) lists fewer than a handful of studies examining the combined effects of message source and content on persuasion.

References

  • Achinstein, P. (1987). Concepts of evidence. Mind, 87, 22–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, E. W. (1998). A primer of probability logic. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adler, J. (2006). Epistemological problems of testimony. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, M. H., & Mellers, B. (1983). Bayesian inference: Combining base rates with opinions of sources who vary in credibility. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 45, 792–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, M. H., & Stegner, S. E. (1979). Source credibility in social judgment: Bias, expertise and the judge’s point of view. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37, 48–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, M. H., Wong, R., & Wong, L. K. (1976). Combining information from sources that vary in credibility. Memory & Cognition, 4, 330–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blamey, J. (this volume). Upping the stakes and the preface paradox. In F. Zenker (Ed.), Bayesian argumentation: The practical side of probability (pp. xx&xx). Dordrecht: Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowell, T., & Kemp, G. (2002). Critical thinking: A concise guide. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, K., & Russo, J. (2001). Biased interpretation of evidence by mock jurors. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 7, 91–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chaiken, S. (1980). Heuristic versus systematic information processing and the use of source versus message cues in persuasion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 39, 752–766.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coady, C. A. J. (1992). Testimony: A philosophical study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L. J. (1982). What is necessary for testimonial corroboration? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 33, 161–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copi, I. M., & Cohen, C. (1994). Introduction to logic (9th ed.). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corner, A., & Hahn, U. (2009). Evaluating science arguments: Evidence, uncertainty & argument strength. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 15, 199–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corner, A. J., Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2011). The psychological mechanism of the slippery slope argument. Journal of Memory and Language, 64, 153–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eagly, A. H., & Chaiken, S. (1993). The psychology of attitudes. Belmont: Thompson/Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eaton, T. E., & O’Callaghan, M. G. (2001). Child-witness and defendant credibility: child evidence presentation mode and judicial instructions. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 31, 1845–1858.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ForsterLee, L., Horowitz, I. A., Athaide-Victor, E., & Brown, N. (2000). The bottom line: the effect of written expert witness statements on juror verdicts and information processing. Law and Human Behavior, 24, 259–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, R. (1987). Route analysis of credibility and hearsay. Yale Law Journal, 96, 667–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1999). Knowledge in a social world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grabmair, M., & Ashley, K. D. (this volume). A survey of uncertainties and their consequences in probabilistic legal argumentation. In F. Zenker (Ed.), Bayesian argumentation: The practical side of probability (pp. xx–xx). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, P. J. (1997). What is testimony? Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 227–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2006a). A Bayesian approach to informal argument fallacies. Synthese, 152, 207–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2006b). Why a normative theory of argument strength and why might one want it to be Bayesian? Informal Logic, 26, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2007a). The rationality of informal argumentation: A Bayesian approach to reasoning fallacies. Psychological Review, 114, 704–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2007b). The burden of proof and its role in argumentation. Argumentation, 21, 39–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., Harris, A. J. L., & Corner, A. J. (2009). Argument content and argument source: An exploration. Informal Logic, 29, 337–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U. (2011). The problem of circularity in evidence, argument and explanation. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 6, 172–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, P. L., & Corriveau, K. H. (2011). Young children’s selective trust in informants. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 366, 1179–1190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, W., Lavery, J., & Doran, K. (2010). Critical thinking: An introduction to the basic skills (6th ed.). Peterborough: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1977) An enquiry concerning human understanding (E. Steinberg, Ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jarvstad, A., & Hahn, U. (2011). Source reliability and the conjunction fallacy. Cognitive Science, 35, 682–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R. H. (2000). Manifest rationality: A pragmatic theory of argument. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krauss, D. A., & Sales, B. D. (2001). The effects of clinical and scientific expert testimony on juror decision making in capital sentencing. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law, 7, 267–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kruglanski, A. W., & Stroebe, W. (2005). The influence of beliefs and goals on attitudes: Issues of structure, function, and dynamics. In D. Albarracín, B. T. Johnson, & M. P. Zanna (Eds.), The handbook of attitudes (pp. 323–369). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch, M., & Lipton, P. (2002). Testimony: A primer. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 33, 209–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg, H. E., Jr. (1961). Probability and the logic of rational belief. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagnado, D. A., Fenton, N., & Neil, M. (2012). Legal idioms: A framework for evidential reasoning. Argument and Computation, 4, 1–18. Online first.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E. F. (1975). Leading questions and the eyewitness report. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 560–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D. C. (1965). The paradox of the preface. Analysis, 25, 205–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford, M., & Hahn, U. (2004). A Bayesian approach to the argument from ignorance. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology, 58, 75–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford, M., & Hahn, U. (this volume). Why are we convinced by the Ad Hominem argument?: Bayesian source reliability or pragma-dialectical discussion rules. In F. Zenker (Ed.), Bayesian argumentation: The practical side of probability (pp. xx–xx). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E. J. (this volume). A Bayesian simulation model of group deliberation. In F. Zenker (Ed.), Bayesian argumentation: The practical side of probability (pp. xx–xx). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (1988). Probabilistic reasoning in intelligent systems. San Mateo: Morgan Kaufman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C., & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. (1969). The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petty, R. E., & Cacioppo, J. T. (1984). Source factors and the elaboration likelihood model of persuasion. Advances in Consumer Research, 11, 668–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petty, R. E., & Wegener, D. T. (1999). The elaboration likelihood model: Current status and controversies. In S. Chaiken & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual process theories in social psychology (pp. 41–72). New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petty, R. E., Cacioppo, J. T., & Goldman, R. (1981). Personal involvement as a determinant of argument-based persuasion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 41, 847–855.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (2001). Defeasible reasoning with variable degrees of justification. Artificial Intelligence, 133, 233–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (1995). Cognitive carpentry. Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pornpitakpan, C. (2004). The persuasiveness of source credibility: A critical review of five decades’ evidence. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 34, 243–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H., & Vreeswijk, G. A. W. (2002). Logics for defeasible argumentation. In D. M. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (2nd ed., Vol. 4, pp. 219–318). Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rainbolt, G. W., & Dwyer, S. L. (2012). Critical thinking: The art of argument. Boston: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratneshwar, R., & Chaiken, S. (1991). Comprehension’s role in persuasion: The case of its moderating effect on the persuasive impact of source cues. Journal of Consumer Research, 18, 52–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reimer, T., Mata, R., & Stoecklin, M. (2004). The use of heuristics in persuasion: Deriving cues on source expertise from argument quality. Current Research in Social Psychology, 10, 69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1976). Plausible reasoning. Assen: Van Gorcum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1977). Dialectics: A controversy-oriented approach to the theory of knowledge. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuller, R. A., Terry, D., & McKimmie, B. (2001). The impact of an expert’s gender on jurors’ decisions. Law and Psychology Review, 25, 59–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schum, D. A. (1981). Sorting out the effects of witness sensitivity and response-criterion placement upon the inferential value of testimonial evidence. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 27, 153–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schum, D. A. (1994). The evidential foundations of probabilistic reasoning. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shogenji, T. (2000). Self-dependent justification without circularity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51, 287–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shogenji, T. (this volume). Reductio, coherence, and the myth of epistemic circularity. In F. Zenker (Ed.), Bayesian argumentation: The practical side of probability (pp. xx–xx). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skolnick, P., & Shaw, J. I. (2001). A comparison of eyewitness and physical evidence on Mock-Juror decision making. Criminal Justice and Behavior, 28, 614–630. doi:10.1177/009385480102800504.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, V. A., Evans, J. S., & Handley, S. J. (2005). Persuading and dissuading by conditional argument. Journal of Memory and Language, 53, 238–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tindale, C. W. (2007). Fallacies and argument appraisal. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1958). The uses of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, A. (2005). Miracles, historical testimonies, and probabilities. History and Theory, 44, 373–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1983). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychological Review, 90, 293–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2004). A systematic theory of argumentation. The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. (2003). Dialectical argumentation with argumentation schemes: An approach to legal logic. Artificial intelligence and Law, 11, 167–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1992). Rules for plausible reasoning. Informal Logic, XIV, 33–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1996). Argument schemes for presumptive reasoning. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (1997). Appeal to expert opinion. University Park: Pennsylvania State Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1998). Ad Hominem arguments. Tuscaloosa: The University of Alabama Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. M. (2001). Abductive, presumptive, and plausible arguments. Informal Logic, 21, 141–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (2004). Relevance in argumentation. Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (2008). Witness testimony evidence: argumentation, artificial intelligence, and law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D., Reed, C., & Macagno, F. (2008). Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weinstock, M., & Flaton, R. (2004). Evidence coverage and argument skills: cognitive factors in a juror’s verdict choice. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 17, 191–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wells, G. L., & Olsen, E. A. (2003). Eyewitness testimony. Annual Review of Psychology, 54, 277–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, G. (2007). A review of the lottery paradox. In W. Harper & G. Wheeler (Eds.), Probability and inference: Essays in honour of Henry E. Kyburg, Jr (pp. 1–31). London: King’s College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J., Irvine, A., & Walton, D. (2004). Critical Thinking: Logic & The Fallacies. Toronto: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ulrike Hahn .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hahn, U., Oaksford, M., Harris, A.J.L. (2013). Testimony and Argument: A Bayesian Perspective. In: Zenker, F. (eds) Bayesian Argumentation. Synthese Library, vol 362. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5357-0_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics