Skip to main content

Open Theism and Other Models of Divine Providence

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Abstract

In this paper I define ‘open theism’ as a version of ‘broadly classical theism’ distinguished by commitment to a causally, epistemically, and providentially open future. After clarifying open theism, I then compare and contrast the open theistic model of divine providence with its chief competitors: theological determinism, Molinism, and process theism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This paper draws on material from Rhoda (2008, 2010a, b). Rhoda (2008) was read at the Models of God mini-conference at the 2007 Pacific APA.

  2. 2.

    The medieval Jewish philosopher Levi ben Gerson, a.k.a. Gersonides (1288–1344 CE) is perhaps the earliest clear proponent of open theism. See Gersonides (1987). The Christian scholar Calcidius (4th c. CE) has also been floated as an early open theist, but the attribution is less clear. See Den Boeft (1970) for details. Still earlier anticipations of open theism can be found in both Cicero (106–43 BCE) and Alexander of Aphrodisias (late 2nd to early 3rd c. CE). For Cicero, see his De Fato and De Divinatione. For Alexander, see Sharples (1983).

  3. 3.

    Pinnock et al. (1994).

  4. 4.

    See, for example, Coffman (2001) and Olsen (2003).

  5. 5.

    See Pinnock et al. (1994: 156) and Cobb and Pinnock (2000). My use of ‘he’ in reference to God is due merely to terminological conservatism and is not meant to imply that God has a gender or that masculine metaphors are more revealing of God’s essence than feminine ones.

  6. 6.

    See Pinnock et al. (1994: esp. chs. 2–4).

  7. 7.

    The final sentence distinguishes open theism from process theism.

  8. 8.

    I use ‘causally necessary’ and ‘unpreventable’ interchangeably. Somewhat roughly, a state of affairs (event) is causally necessary or unpreventable as of time t if and only if it obtains (occurs) in all logically possible worlds having the same causal history as the actual world up to and including t. Similarly, a proposition is causally necessary as of time t if and only if it is true in all logically possible worlds having the same causal history as the actual world up to and including t. On my usage, it follows that logically and metaphysically necessary truths or states of affairs are also causally necessary.

  9. 9.

    Restriction to the causally relevant actual past is needed to avoid begging the question against Ockhamism, which affirms a causally open future while positing as part of the actual past something (viz., divine foreknowledge) that entails a unique causally possible future. For a good primer on Ockhamism see the essays in Fischer (1989).

  10. 10.

    See, e.g., Pinnock et al. (1994: 156).

  11. 11.

    They believe this on the basis of philosophical arguments like Pike’s (1965) and Edwards’ (2009 [1754]: II.12).

  12. 12.

     <p>  is short for ‘the proposition that p’ (i.e., the proposition named by the sentence enclosed in angle brackets).

  13. 13.

    Borges (1998: 119–128).

  14. 14.

    In Rhoda (2008) I ended my analysis of open theism’s core commitments with (4). Subsequent discussions with Joseph Jedwab convinced me to add (5).

  15. 15.

    The distinction between strong and weak actualization comes from Plantinga (1974: 173). S strongly actualizes F iff S’s actions are causally sufficient for, and known by S to be causally sufficient for, F’s coming to pass. S weakly actualizes F iff S’s actions are counterfactually sufficient for, and known by S to be counterfactually sufficient for, F’s coming to pass.

  16. 16.

    Westminster Confession of Faith 3.1.

  17. 17.

    The term ‘freewill theism’ comes from Basinger (1996).

  18. 18.

    Craig (2001).

  19. 19.

    Creel (2005 [1986]: 9–12).

  20. 20.

    This seems to be Sanders’s (1997: 196–197, and note 117) view. He clearly wants to go further than Creel in the extent to which he attributes passibility to God.

  21. 21.

    For a more detailed presentation of this argument for alethic openness, see Rhoda et al. (2006) and Rhoda (2010b). For related arguments that a causally open and alethically settled future requires an ontically settled future, see Rea (2006) and Finch and Rea (2008).

  22. 22.

    Swinburne (1993: 180), Hasker (1989: 187, 2001: 111).

  23. 23.

    See, e.g., Ware (2000).

  24. 24.

    For detailed exposition of Molinism, see Flint (1998) and Freddoso (1988).

  25. 25.

    For detailed exposition of process theism, see Cobb and Griffin (1976).

  26. 26.

    Freddoso (1988: 3) nicely states the doctrine of meticulous providence as follows: “God, the divine artisan, freely and knowingly plans, orders, and provides for all the effects that constitute His artifact, the created universe with its entire history, and executes His chosen plan by playing an active causal role sufficient to ensure its exact realization.”

  27. 27.

    By ‘unavoidable’ here I of course mean unavoidable for God.

References

  • Basinger, David. 1996. The case for freewill theism. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borges, Jorge Luis. 1998. Collected fictions. Trans. Andrew Hurley. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobb Jr., John B., and David Ray Griffin. 1976. Process theology: An introductory exposition. Philadelphia: Westminster Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobb Jr., John B., and Clark H. Pinnock (eds.). 2000. Searching for an adequate God: A dialogue between process and free will theists. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coffman, Elesha. 2001. Open debate in the openness debate. Christianity Today 45(3). http://www.christianitytoday.com/ct/2001/february19/3.42.html.

  • Craig, William Lane. 2001. Time and eternity: Exploring God’s relationship to time. Wheaton: Crossway Books.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Creel, Richard. 2005 [1986]. Divine impassibility. Eugene: Wipf and Stock.

    Google Scholar 

  • Den Boeft, J. 1970. Calcidius on fate: His doctrine and sources. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, Jonathan. 2009 [1754]. Freedom of the will. Vancouver: Eremitical Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finch, Alicia, and Michael Rea. 2008. Presentism and Ockham’s way out. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion 1: 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, John Martin (ed.). 1989. God, foreknowledge, and freedom. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flint, Thomas P. 1998. Divine providence: The Molinist account. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freddoso, Alfred J. 1988. Introduction to Luis de Molina. On divine foreknowledge (Part IV of the Concordia). Trans. Alfred J. Freddoso. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gersonides. 1987. The wars of the lord, vol. 2. Trans. Seymour Feldman. Philadelphia: The Jewish Publication Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasker, William. 1989. God, time, and knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasker, William. 2001. The foreknowledge conundrum. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 50: 97–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsen, Ted. 2003. ETS leadership issues recommendations on kicking out open theists. Christianity Today, 47(October), web-only. http://www.christianitytoday.com/ct/2003/octoberweb-only/10-27-41.0.html.

  • Pike, Nelson. 1965. Divine omniscience and voluntary action. Philosophical Review 74: 27–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinnock, Clark, et al. 1994. The openness of God. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, Alvin. 1974. The nature of necessity. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rea, Michael C. 2006. Presentism and fatalism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84: 511–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rhoda, Alan R. 2008. Generic open theism and some varieties thereof. Religious Studies 44: 225–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rhoda, Alan R. 2010a. Gratuitous evil and divine providence. Religious Studies 46(3): 281–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rhoda, Alan R. 2010b. The fivefold openness of the future. In God in an open universe: Science, metaphysics, and open theism, ed. William Hasker, Dean Zimmerman, and Thomas Jay Oord. Eugene: Pickwick.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhoda, Alan R., Gregory A. Boyd, and Thomas G. Belt. 2006. Open theism, omniscience, and the nature of the future. Faith and Philosophy 23: 432–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanders, John. 1997. The God who risks. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharples, R.W. (Translation and commentary). 1983. Alexander of Aphrodisias on fate. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, Richard. 1993. The coherence of theism. Rev. edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ware, Bruce A. 2000. God’s lesser glory: The diminished God of open theism. Wheaton: Crossway.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alan R. Rhoda .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rhoda, A.R. (2013). Open Theism and Other Models of Divine Providence. In: Diller, J., Kasher, A. (eds) Models of God and Alternative Ultimate Realities. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5219-1_24

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics