Skip to main content

A Type Composition Logic for Generative Lexicon

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Advances in Generative Lexicon Theory

Part of the book series: Text, Speech and Language Technology ((TLTB,volume 46))

Abstract

In this paper, we outline a model of semantics that integrates aspects of discourse-sensitive logics with the compositional mechanisms available from lexically-driven semantic interpretation. Specifically, we concentrate on developing a composition logic required to properly model complex types within the Generative Lexicon (henceforth GL), for which we employ SDRT principles. As we are presently interested in the composition of information to construct logical forms, we will build on one standard way of arriving at such representations, the lambda calculus, in which functional types are exploited. We outline a new type calculus that captures one of the fundamental ideas of GL: providing a set of techniques governing type shifting possibilities for various lexical items so as to allow for the combination of lexical items in cases where there is an apparent type mismatch. These techniques themselves should follow from the structure of the lexicon and its underlying logic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a fuller discussion and a theory of this interaction using default unification and the glue logic DICE of SDRT see Asher and Lascarides (1995) or Lascarides and Copestake (1995).

  2. 2.

    Here the notation of earlier work on dot objects suggested these interpretations; but our approach here is resolutely different from those older attempts at description. We are very explicit that • is a type constructor and has nothing to do with the construction of a complex object.

  3. 3.

    Not all copredications need involve dot objects. Some may exploit events that are conventionally associated with the types of the subjects, like those described in qualia structure. In (7), for example, it appears as though some predicates make reference to aspects having to do with the so called telic qualia role of the subject NP they are predicating i.e., the smoking and drinking events, respectively.

    (7)

    a.Arnold’s cigar is Cuban and lasted the whole afternoon.

     

    b.Your last glass of wine was a Merlot and lasted half an hour.

    Hence, copredication does not uniquely identify NPs typed as dot objects. Similarly, it is unclear whether grinding operations, which also license copredications, should be analyzed as involving dot objects, type-changing operations, or involve the exploitation of lexical information from the qualia structure. See Pustejovsky (1995) for discussion.

  4. 4.

    The felicity of copredications often depends on the order of the predications as well. This again we feel is due to discourse factors. We don’t go into this here, as it would involve bringing in too much of the SDRT framework, obscuring our restricted aim here to provide a type composition logic. In any case, we will keep such rhetorical constraints on felicitous copredications with dot objects separate from the composition logic.

  5. 5.

    As a result, such concepts are actually double dot objects, but we ignore this point for now, cf. Pustejovsky 1995.

  6. 6.

    We note as well that such types may be subject to discourse effects like parallelism; for instance, (9b) improves if we shift the second event to the past:

    (9b’)

    The newspaper was founded in 1878 and weighed 5 lbs in its first edition.

    But we will not attempt to integrate such discourse effects with our story about complex types here.

  7. 7.

    Klein and Sag (1985) take this approach to multiple subcategorization phenomena. However, as discussed in Pustejovsky (1995), type-shifting the predicate in such cases does not change the basic meaning of the predicate, but only the surface typing. Both Klein and Sag’s analysis of believe and Godard and Jayez’s (1993) treatment of coercion predicates involve meaning postulates to relate verb senses. The alternative analysis here is similar to the sense transfer operation proposed in Nunberg (1995). As we see, however, this is an inappropriate use of transfer.

  8. 8.

    This point is due to Melissa Bowerman, pc.

  9. 9.

    The name is intended to evoke an analogy to a similar relation in discourse. But the development of that analogy is for another time.

  10. 10.

    In Asher (2004), the O-Elab relation is assumed to be asymmetric, but the work that is supposed to do there is perhaps better explained on pragmatic grounds than by stipulating a strange part of relation.

  11. 11.

    For more on fences and their usefulness in discourse semantics, see Asher and Fernando (1997).

  12. 12.

    The details of the relationship between \( e \) and its subtypes, as a join semi-lattice, in the simple type domain are spelled out in Pustejovsky (2001,2011).

  13. 13.

    Classic GL analyses (Bouillon 1997; Pustejovsky and Boguraev 1993; Pustejovsky 1995) have argued that adjectival subselection selects for a particular qualia role or the corresponding type for a quale within the feature structure of the nominal semantics. That is, they are typed to modify the particular qualia role of the noun in a specific construction. We compare this analysis to the present one below.

  14. 14.

    Results are largely equivalent if we choose HPSG as our syntactic guide; there the verb will be the lexical head and will once again force us to change the NP’s type.

  15. 15.

    For some cases we may have to treat the existential quantifier on \( v \) as having its force determined by the original over \( x \). As in DRT, we would have to treat such quantifiers over x as unselective. The cases we have in mind would be those where \( \phi \) is of the form \( Qx(\psi (x),\chi (x)) \), and both restrictor and nuclear scope have material that is responsible for typing \( x \) originally as being of complex type. We will not deal with this complexity here.

  16. 16.

    This effectively replaces the Dot Object Subtyping rule, \( \dot{\Theta}^{\textit{llet}} \), as developed in Pustejovsky (1995) pp. 150–151.

  17. 17.

    We assume for illustration purposes that the computation will accommodate the presuppositions of definiteness locally in the composition.

  18. 18.

    For details on how such distributive and cumulative readings together are possible, see Asher and Wang 2003.

References

  • Amadio, R., & Curien, P. L. (1998). Domains and lambda calculi. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N. (1993). Reference to abstract objects in discourse. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher N. (2004). Things and their aspects, manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N. (2011). The web of words. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Fernando, T. (1997). Effective labeling for disambiguation. In Proceedings of the second international workshop in computational linguistics, Tilburg, The Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Lascarides, A. (1995). Lexical disambiguation in a discourse context. Journal of Semantics, 1, 69–108, Oxford University Press.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Lascarides, A. (1998). The semantics and pragmatics of presupposition. Journal of Semantics, 16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Lascarides, A. (2001). Indirect speech acts. Synthese, 128, 183–228.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Lascarides, A. (2003). Logics of conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouillon, P. (1997). Polymorphie et sémantique lexicale: le cas des adjectifs. Lille: Presses Universitaires du Spetentrion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter, B. (1992). Typed feature structures. Computational Linguistics, 18, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copestake, A., & Briscoe, T. (1992). Lexical operations in a unification-based framework. In J. Pustejovsky & S. Bergler (Eds.), Lexical semantics and knowledge reperesentation. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copestake, A., & Briscoe, T. (1995). Semi-productive polysemy and sense extension. Journal of Semantics, 15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crole, R. (1993). Categories for types. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Crouch, D., & van Genabith, J. (2000). Linear logic for linguists, ESSLLI-00 Course material manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danlos, L. (1999). Event coherence in causal discourses. In P. Bouillon & F. Busa (Eds.), The syntax of word meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Lepore, E. (1998). The emptiness of the lexicon: Critical reflections on J. Pustejovsky’s “The Generative Lexicon”. Linguistic Inquiry, 29, 269–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godard, D., & Jayez, J. (1993). Towards a proper treatment of Coercion Phenomena. In Proceeding of the 1993 European ACL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1990). Dynamic predicate logic. Linguistics and Philosophy, 14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendriks, H. (1993). Flexible Montague Grammar, LP-1990-09. Logic, Philosophy and Linguistics (LP) Series: ILLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbs, J., Stickel, M. E., Appelt, D. E., & Martin, P. (1993). Interpretation as abduction. Artificial Intelligence, 63, 69–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, W. A. (1980). The formulas-as-types notion of construction. In J. P. Seldin & J. R. Hindley (Eds.), To H. B. Curry: Essays on combinatory logic, lambda calculus and formalism. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. (1997). The architecture of the language faculty. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. (2002). Foundations of language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From discourse to logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, E., & Sag, I. (1985). Type-driven translation. Linguistics and Philosophy, 8, 163–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lascarides, A., & Asher, N. (1993). Temporal interpretation, discourse relations and commonsense entailment. Linguistics and Philosophy, 16, 437–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lascarides, A., & Copestake, A. (1995). The pragmatics of word meaning. In Proceedings SALT V.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, B., & Hovav, M. R. (1995). Unaccusatives: At the syntax-lexical semantics interface. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1973). The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In K. Hintikka, J. Moravcsik, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Approaches to natural language (pp. 221–242). Dordrecht: Kluwer. (Reprinted in Thomason 1974, pp. 247–270).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Moravcsik, J. (1975). Aitia as generative factor in Aristotle’s philosophy. Dialogue, 14, 622–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moravcsik, J. (1998). Meaning, creativity, and the partial inscrutability of the human mind. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrill, G. (1992). Type-logical grammar. Utrecht: Onderzoeksinstituut voor Taal en Spraak.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nunberg, G. (1995). Transfers of meaning. Journal of Semantics, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B., & Rooth, M. (1983). Generalized conjunction and type ambiguity. In S. Bäuerle & A. von Stechow (Eds.), Meaning, use, and interpretation of language. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1991). The generative lexicon. Computational Linguistics, 17, 409–441.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1994). Semantic typing and degrees of polymorphism. In C. Martin-Vide (Ed.), Current issues in mathematical linguistics. Holland: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1995). The generative lexicon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1998). The semantics of lexical underspecification. Folia Linguistica, XXXII.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (2001). Type construction and the logic of concepts. In P. Bouillon & F. Busa (Eds.), The Syntax of Word Meaning.: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (forthcoming). Meaning in context: Mechanisms of selection in language. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (2011). Coercion in a general theory of argument selection. Journal of Linguistics, 49(6).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J., & Boguraev, B. (1993). Lexical knowledge representation and natural language processing. Artificial Intelligence, 63, 193–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J., & Busa, F. (1997). Denominal verbs, ms. Brandeis University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verspoor, K. (1997). Contextually dependent lexical semantics. Ph.D: Dissertation, University of Edinburgh.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Sheila Asher, Pascal Denis, Tim Fernando, Ivan Sag, Stan Peters, David Israel, Alex Lascarides, Ann Copestake, José Castaño, Roser, Saurí, and Johanna Seibt for helpful comments on earlier drafts. This work was partially supported by NIH Grant DC03660, to James Pustejovsky.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicholas Asher .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Asher, N., Pustejovsky, J. (2013). A Type Composition Logic for Generative Lexicon. In: Pustejovsky, J., Bouillon, P., Isahara, H., Kanzaki, K., Lee, C. (eds) Advances in Generative Lexicon Theory. Text, Speech and Language Technology, vol 46. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5189-7_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5189-7_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-007-5188-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-5189-7

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics