Advertisement

Doping Use As an Artistic Crime: On Natural Performances and Authentic Art

  • Andreas De BlockEmail author
Chapter
Part of the International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine book series (LIME, volume 52)

Abstract

The problem of fakes and forgeries is central to much theorizing in philosophical aesthetics. Although artistic fakes and forgeries share many or even all of the formal characteristics of original works, it would change our aesthetic appreciation if we were to discover, for instance, that a painting is not an original Hopper, but a perfect copy of one of Hopper’s works, painted by an unknown Belgian artist. I suspect that something very similar explains the intuitive appeal of human nature arguments in the doping debate. Much in the same way that an aesthetic judgment is also a judgment of origin and performance –and necessarily so-, the observable characteristics of an athletic performance are not the only things that aesthetically matter to us. After all, there is an aesthetically relevant difference between athletic performances and circus acts. The information that distinguishes athletic performances from circus acts (and similar phenomena) influences the aesthetic experience it engenders. In my view, the aesthetically important differences between athletic performances and circus acts all revolve around the idea that an athletic performance is necessarily a human performance. In my contribution, I will explore ‘human nature’ as an aesthetic value in sports, and I will sketch how this aesthetic value bears upon the doping debate.

Keywords

Human Nature Natural Kind Female Athlete Observable Characteristic Athletic Performance 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Augendre, J. 1996. Le Tour de France: Panorama d’un siècle. Paris: Société du Tour de France.Google Scholar
  2. Beardsley, M. 1965. On the creation of art. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 23: 291–302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Carroll, N. 1993. On being moved by nature: Between religion and natural history. In Landscape, natural beauty and the arts, ed. S. Kemal and I. Gaskell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Currie, G. 1985. The authentic and the aesthetic. American Philosophical Quarterly 22: 153–160.Google Scholar
  5. Dupre, J. 2001. Human nature and the limits of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Dutton, D. 1979. Artistic crimes: The problem of forgery in the arts. British Journal of Aesthetics 19: 304–314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Hull, D. 1986. On human nature. Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 2: 3–13.Google Scholar
  8. Kelly, D. 2011. Yuck! The nature and moral significance of disgust. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Koestler, A. 1964. The act of creation. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
  10. Kripke, S. 1980. Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Lacerda, T., and S. Mumford. 2010. Genius in art and sport. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 37: 182–193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Lessing, A. 1965. What is wrong with a forgery? Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 23: 461–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Levinson, J. 2003. Elster on artistic creativity. In The creation of art, ed. B. Gaut and P. Livingston, 235–256. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Levy, D. 1980. Perversions and the unnatural as moral categories. Ethics 90: 191–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Machery, E. 2008. A plea for human nature. Philosophical Psychology 21: 321–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Mameli, M. 2008. On innateness: The clutter hypothesis and the cluster hypothesis. The Journal of Philosophy 105: 719–736.Google Scholar
  17. Mark, T.C. 1980. On works of virtuosity. The Journal of Philosophy 77: 28–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. McFee, G. 2005. The artistic and the aesthetic. British Journal of Aesthetics 45: 368–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Miller, I. 1998. The anatomy of disgust. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Sontag, S. 1978. Illness as metaphor. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  21. Stein, R., and C. Nemeroff. 1995. Moral overtones of food: Judgments of others based on what they eat. Personality & Social Psychology Bulletin 21: 480–490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Suits, B. 1978. The grasshopper: Games, life and utopia. London: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
  23. Walton, K.L. 1970. Categories of art. Philosophical Review 79: 334–367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Zimniuch, F. 2009. Crooked: A history of cheating in sport. Lanham: Taylor Trade Publishing.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Centre for Logic and Analytical PhilosophyKU Leuven UniversityLeuvenBelgium

Personalised recommendations