Skip to main content

Conclusion: The Young and the Mature Descartes Agonistes

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Descartes-Agonistes

Part of the book series: Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ((AUST,volume 27))

  • 599 Accesses

Abstract

This Chapter concludes the argument and has two segments: First, a ‘Coda’ rounds out and underlines the key themes of this study, with special emphasis on what Descartes himself could have understood as the ‘mathematical’ bent of his natural philosophical enterprise, given what we have discovered in this volume. Then, an ‘Epilogue’ surveys some salient points about the subsequent career of the mature Descartes, illuminated by our study of his earlier career. In addition, we discover his (somewhat surprising) relations to the next phase in the Scientific Revolution, and hypothesize about what might have happened, had he lived into that phase (whose contours were analyzed as part of the conceptual and historiographical foundations set down in Chap. 2).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cf. above Chap. 6, note 19.

  2. 2.

    For extended argument along these lines see Schuster (2009).

  3. 3.

    Descartes habitually displayed a secretive, reclusive, publicly masked and overtly tricky persona. This was a man who lived by the mottos ‘he lives well who is well hidden’ and ‘masked I go forth.’ Descartes announced ‘Bene vixit, bene qui latuit’ as his motto to Mersenne in April 1634 (AT I, p. 286). (Descartes proclaimed ‘larvatus prodeo’ (masked I go forth) in the middle of some fragmentary youthful ruminations preserved in AT X, p.213.) There is excellent evidence on these points for his mature career, and hints and clues about it for the earlier period. (Clarke 2006) Part of this, no doubt, was cultural, conditioned, in Descartes and others, by the superheated political and religious tensions of the Baroque age, which also elicited intense and elaborate courtesy as a defence against incipient social breakdown and chaos Schuster (2012a).

  4. 4.

    Westman (1980), Biagioli (1989), Bennett (1991), Dear (1995), Johnston (1996).

  5. 5.

    The reader should recall our delineation of several species of physico-mathematician above, Sect. 2.5.3. Notable exceptions actually prove the point. Consider those master practical mathematicians, such as Simon Stevin, who played upon mixed mathematical fields from outside the realm of natural philosophizing, aiming not to make natural philosophical capital, but to expand and systematize the realm of practical mathematics. Indeed the mixed mathematical disciplines can be seen as a contested borderland in play between certain practical mathematicians and, as we have seen mathematically adept, ambitious natural philosophers. On this topic, see also J.A. Schuster, ‘Consuming and appropriating the mixed mathematical fields, or, being ‘influenced’ by them: the case of the young Descartes’, available on my website http://descartes-agonistes.com.

  6. 6.

    Gaukroger (1995) 338, 345, 352, 362; Schuster (1995) 135–36.

  7. 7.

    Above, Sect. 2.7.

  8. 8.

    For example: hard results in mixed mathematics were to be used in physico-mathematics; his respect for the way the sheer opacity of raw experience of fall nullified his initiatives on a physico-mathematics of fall; his concern for what would count as empirically grounded and workable measures of dimensions in later Regulae; and the multiple ways Le Monde and the path to it were strewn with interest in and respect shown to putatively agreed experiences or matters of fact, as we have seen in Chap. 8, passim.

  9. 9.

    However, see above, Sect. 12.12, point [3] on how Descartes’ mature style of cosmographical explanatory/descriptive narrative created a situation in which factual detail tended to shape narrative detail, rather than prompt alterations in the structure of basic concepts.

  10. 10.

    Clarke (1989), McClaughlin (1996, 2000).

  11. 11.

    Shapin (1994) famously announced the advent at the early Royal Society of London, from the early 1660s onward, of an atheoretical ‘experimental science’ of ‘matters of fact’ exchanged in a culture of gentlemanly trust. He ignored the continuation of heated natural philosophical contestation, in muted circumstances and under a public rhetoric of ‘matters of fact only’. Moreover, no fact in natural philosophy or any science is not ‘theory-loaded’, as almost any first year student in History and Philosophy of Science or Science and Technology Studies anywhere in the world can tell you. On the myth of merely matter of fact science at the Royal Society, see Schuster and Taylor (1997). For a clear demonstration that the contemporary Florentine Accademia del Cimento was also rife with natural philosophical agendas and conflicts, hidden below a public façade, see the important work of Boschiero (2007).

  12. 12.

    Well canvassed in Clarke (2006), pp.535–60

  13. 13.

    In his two somewhat contrasting accounts of the terrain traditionally covered by theses concerning a ‘crisis’ of the seventeenth century, Theodore K. Rabb (1975, 2006) has drawn attention to the contrasts— psychological, attitudinal and cultural—across varied intellectual and artistic pursuits (including what he calls ‘science’) between the tense, anguished and deeply contested generations of the earlier seventeenth century and the modulated, controlled and more confident generations of the later seventeenth century. These map onto our Scientific Revolution phases of ‘civil war in natural philosophy’ and its contrasted sequel, the ‘CMF’ phase. As Descartes might have bridged these phases in a more mellow old age, so in fact did figures who had lived on into the Restoration following upon the more immediately manifested English political and religious crisis, such as Walter Charleton (Booth 2004), John Wilkins, Henry More, Seth Ward, or even the considerably younger Boyle, who inflected from a youthful van Helmontian with Puritan leanings into an impeccably establishment Restoration Anglican and carefully hedged corpuscular-mechanical natural philosopher. The Royal Society was founded by, and for a long time included in its membership, individuals who had survived the generation long English crisis, not those too young to have experienced it.

  14. 14.

    Gabbey (1980). More generally on Descartes’ unintended contributions to later developments in physical optics and the emerging ‘classical mechanics’, see Schuster, ‘Cartesian Physics’ in J.Z. Buchwald and R. Fox, The Oxford Handbook of the History of Physics (OUP forthcoming). Also cf. above, Chap. 11, note 2.

  15. 15.

    On ‘seeing the natural philosophical causes’ directly in well grounded mixed mathematical results, see above Chap. 3, and papers on Descartes’ and Kepler’s physico-mathematical optics by Schuster, Raz Chen-Morris, Ofer Gal and Sven Dupré in Synthèse 185 (2012), in particular, Schuster (2012).

  16. 16.

    Chapter 6 Note 19.

  17. 17.

    On Newton, Feyerabend (1970) and discussion of same above, Sect. 6.3. In this counter-factual conceit about a ‘Restoration Descartes’, it is certainly the case that in committing to a piecemeal, hypothetical corpuscular-mechanism, he would have had to give up not only metaphysical grounding, as mentioned, but also his mature practice in the Principles, of weaving large cosmographical explanatory narratives, just what Huygens criticized him for (Chap. 12, note 105. On how laws of nature and generalized grasp of facts fed into this mode of explanation in the Principles cf. also Sect. 12.12, point [3], and Sect. 12.9, note 78) .

  18. 18.

    John Henry (1986) was perhaps the most important early advocate of this important insight.

  19. 19.

    I believe that Thomas Kuhn first made the sorts of points which follow, although I have not been able to find a statement of these points in his published work. He may well have argued them informally, in graduate seminars, or in personal discussion, during the time I studied in the Princeton HPS Program he headed (1969–1974).

  20. 20.

    Alternatively, we can drop the hypothetical conceit and state these points as the results of a deconstruction of Descartes’ natural philosophy: Completely mechanist and anti-spirit at the declaratory level, Cartesianism harbored the curious ‘first matter’ which Descartes insisted behaves fully mechanically, but which just as easily might on occasion have been argued to have non-mechanical capabilities. This is because consistency between declaratory glosses of the entire system and the meaning and function of particular parts thereof, was, as usual, up for negotiation amongst actors, including the author of the discourse. No rule, logic or imperative controlling the construction and negotiation of natural philosophical discourse could or did impose a single ‘correct conclusion’ about such matters.

References

Works of Descartes and Their Abbreviations

  • AT  =  Oeuvres de Descartes (revised edition, 12 vols.), edited by C. Adam and P. Tannery (Paris, 1964–1976). References are by volume number (in roman) and page number (in Arabic).

    Google Scholar 

  • SG  =  The World and Other Writings, edited and translated by Stephen Gaukroger (Cambridge,1998).

    Google Scholar 

  • MM  =  René Descartes, The Principles of Philosophy, translated by V. R. Miller and R. P. Miller (Dordrecht, 1991)

    Google Scholar 

  • MSM  =  Rene Descartes, Le Monde, ou Traité de la lumière, translated by Michael S. Mahoney (New York, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  • CSM(K)  =  The Philosophical Writings Of Descartes, 3 vols., translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch, and (for vol. 3) Anthony Kenny, (Cambridge, 1988) References are by volume number (in roman) and page number (in arabic).

    Google Scholar 

  • HR  =  The Philosophical Works of Descartes, vol I translated by E.S. Haldane and G.R.T. Ross (Cambridge, 1968 [1st ed. 1911])

    Google Scholar 

Other

  • Bennett, Jim. 1991. The challenge of practical mathematics. In Science, culture and popular belief in renaissance Europe, ed. Stephen Pumfrey, Paolo L. Rossi, and Maurice Slawinski, 176–190. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biagioli, Mario. 1989. The social status of Italian mathematicians, 1450–1600. History of Science 27: 41–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Booth, Emily. 2004. A subtle and myterious machine’: The medical world of Walter Charleton (1619–1707), Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 18. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boschiero, Luciano. 2007. Experiment and natural philosophy in seventeenth century Tuscany: The history of the Accademia del Cimento, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 21. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, Desmond. 1989. Occult powers and hypotheses: Cartesian natural philosophy under Louis XIV. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, Desmond. 2006. Descartes, a biography. Cambridge: CUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dear, Peter. (1995) Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution. Chicago, Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dear, Peter. 2001. Revolutionizing the Sciences: European Knowledge and its Ambitions, 1500–1700. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbey, A. 1980. Force and inertia in the seventeenth century: Descartes and Newton. In Descartes: Philosophy, mathematics and physics, ed. S. Gaukroger, 230–320. Sussex: Harvester.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaukroger, S. 1995. Descartes: An Intellectual Biography. Oxford:OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P.K. 1970. Classical empiricism. In The Newtonian heritage, ed. R.E. Butts and J.W. Davis, 150–170. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, John. 1986. Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre–Newtonian matter theory. History of Science 24: 335–381.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, Stephen. 1996. ‘The identity of the mathematical practitioner in 16th century England’, in Der `mathematicus’: Zur Entwicklung und Bedeutung einer neun Berufsgruppe in der Zeit Gerhard Mercators. Ed. Irmgard Hantsche. Bochum, 93–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • McClaughlin, Trevor. 1996. Was there an empirical movement in mid-seventeenth century France? Experiments in Jacques Rohault’s Traité de physique. Revue d’Histoire des Sciences 49: 459–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McClaughlin, Trevor. 2000. Descartes, experiments, and a first generation Cartesian, Jacques Rohault. In Descartes’ natural philosophy, ed. S. Gaukroger, J.A. Schuster, and J. Sutton, 330–346. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabb, Theodore K. 1975. The struggle for stability in early modern Europe. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabb, Theordore K. 2006. The last days of the renaissance and the march to modernity. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, John. 1995. Descartes Agonistes: New Tales of Cartesian Mechanism. Perspectives on Science 3: 99–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, J.A. 2009. Descartes—Philosopher of the Scientific Revolution; Or Natural Philosopher in the Scientific Revolution. Journal of Historical Biography 5: 48–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, J.A. 2012. ‘Physico-mathematics and the search for causes in Descartes’ optics—1619–1637’, Synthèse 185: 467–499. [published online Dec. 2011 DOI 10.1007/s11229-011-9979-4].

  • Schuster, J.A. 2012a. What was the relation of Baroque culture to the trajectory of Early Modern Natural Philosophy? In O.Gal and R. Chen-Morris eds. Science in the Age of the Baroque, Archives internationales d’histoire des ideés 209: 1–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, John, and Alan B.H. Taylor. 1997. Blind trust: The gentlemanly origins of experimental science. Social Studies of Science 27: 503–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven. 1994. A social history of truth: Civility and science in seventeenth century England. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westman, Robert. 1980. The Astronomer’s role in the sixteenth century: A preliminary survey. History of Science 18: 105–147.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Schuster .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schuster, J. (2012). Conclusion: The Young and the Mature Descartes Agonistes . In: Descartes-Agonistes. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol 27. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4746-3_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics